Suppose, to fix our ideas, that we take first a case of conceptual knowledge; and let it be our knowledge of the tigers in India, as we sit here. Exactly what do we MEAN by saying that we here know the tigers? What is the precise fact that the cognition so confidently claimed is KNOWN-AS, to use Shadworth Hodgson’s inelegant but valuable form of words?
Most men would answer that what we mean by knowing the tigers is having them, however absent in body, become in some way present to our thought; or that our knowledge of them is known as presence of our thought to them. A great mystery is usually made of this peculiar4 presence in absence; and the scholastic philosophy, which is only common sense grown pedantic5, would explain it as a peculiar kind of existence, called INTENTIONAL6 EXISTENCE of the tigers in our mind. At the very least, people would say that what we mean by knowing the tigers is mentally POINTING towards them as we sit here.
But now what do we mean by POINTING, in such a case as this? What is the pointing known-as, here?
To this question I shall have to give a very prosaic7 answer — one that traverses the prepossessions not only of common sense and scholasticism, but also those of nearly all the epistemological writers whom I have ever read. The answer, made brief, is this: The pointing of our thought to the tigers is known simply and solely8 as a procession of mental associates and motor consequences that follow on the thought, and that would lead harmoniously9, if followed out, into some ideal or real context, or even into the immediate1 presence, of the tigers. It is known as our rejection10 of a jaguar11, if that beast were shown us as a tiger; as our assent12 to a genuine tiger if so shown. It is known as our ability to utter all sorts of propositions which don’t contradict other propositions that are true of the real tigers. It is even known, if we take the tigers very seriously, as actions of ours which may terminate in directly intuited tigers, as they would if we took a voyage to India for the purpose of tiger-hunting and brought back a lot of skins of the striped rascals13 which we had laid low. In all this there is no self-transcendency in our mental images TAKEN BY THEMSELVES. They are one phenomenal fact; the tigers are another; and their pointing to the tigers is a perfectly14 commonplace intra-experiential relation, IF YOU ONCE GRANT A CONNECTING WORLD TO BE THERE. In short, the ideas and the tigers are in themselves as loose and separate, to use Hume’s language, as any two things can be; and pointing means here an operation as external and adventitious15 as any that nature yields.16
I hope you may agree with me now that in representative knowledge there is no special inner mystery, but only an outer chain of physical or mental intermediaries connecting thought and thing. TO KNOW AN OBJECT IS HERE TO LEAD TO IT THROUGH A CONTEXT WHICH THE WORLD SUPPLIES. All this was most instructively set forth16 by our colleague D. S. Miller17 at our meeting in New York last Christmas, and for re-confirming my sometime wavering opinion, I owe him this acknowledgment. 17
Let us next pass on to the case of immediate or intuitive acquaintance with an object, and let the object be the white paper before our eyes. The thought-stuff and the thing-stuff are here indistinguishably the same in nature, as we saw a moment since, and there is no context of intermediaries or associates to stand between and separate the thought and thing. There is no ‘presence in absence’ here, and no ‘pointing,’ but rather an allround embracing of the paper by the thought; and it is clear that the knowing cannot now be explained exactly as it was when the tigers were its object. Dotted all through our experience are states of immediate acquaintance just like this. Somewhere our belief always does rest on ultimate data like the whiteness, smoothness, or squareness of this paper. Whether such qualities be truly ultimate aspects of being, or only provisional suppositions of ours, held-to till we get better informed, is quite immaterial for our present inquiry18. So long as it is believed in, we see our object face to face. What now do we mean by ‘knowing’ such a sort of object as this? For this is also the way in which we should know the tiger if our conceptual idea of him were to terminate by having led us to his lair19?
This address must not become too long, so I must give my answer in the fewest words. And let me first say this: So far as the white paper or other ultimate datum20 of our experience is considered to enter also into some one else’s experience, and we, in knowing it, are held to know it there as well as here; so far, again, as it is considered to be a mere21 mask for hidden molecules22 that other now impossible experiences of our own might some day lay bare to view; so far it is a case of tigers in India again — the things known being absent experiences, the knowing can only consist in passing smoothly23 towards them through the intermediary context that the world supplies. But if our own private vision of the paper be considered in abstraction from every other event, as if it constituted by itself the universe (and it might perfectly well do so, for aught we can understand to the contrary), then the paper seen and the seeing of it are only two names for one indivisible fact which, properly named, is THE DATUM, THE PHENOMENON, OR THE EXPERIENCE. The paper is in the mind and the mind is around the paper, because paper and mind are only two names that are given later to the one experience, when, taken in a larger world of which it forms a part, its connections are traced in different directions. 18 In any case, however, it is the same stuff figures in all the sets of lines.
TO KNOW IMMEDIATELY, THEN, OR INTUITIVELY, IS FOR MENTAL CONTENT AND OBJECT TO BE IDENTICAL. This is a very different definition from that which we gave of representative knowledge; but neither definition involves those mysterious notions of self-transcendency and presence in absence which are such essential parts of the ideas of knowledge, both of philosophers and of common men.
点击收听单词发音
1 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 scholastic | |
adj.学校的,学院的,学术上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 symbolically | |
ad.象征地,象征性地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 pedantic | |
adj.卖弄学问的;迂腐的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 intentional | |
adj.故意的,有意(识)的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 prosaic | |
adj.单调的,无趣的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 harmoniously | |
和谐地,调和地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 rejection | |
n.拒绝,被拒,抛弃,被弃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 jaguar | |
n.美洲虎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 assent | |
v.批准,认可;n.批准,认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 rascals | |
流氓( rascal的名词复数 ); 无赖; (开玩笑说法)淘气的人(尤指小孩); 恶作剧的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 adventitious | |
adj.偶然的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 miller | |
n.磨坊主 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 lair | |
n.野兽的巢穴;躲藏处 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 datum | |
n.资料;数据;已知数 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 molecules | |
分子( molecule的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 smoothly | |
adv.平滑地,顺利地,流利地,流畅地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |