Now, in order at length to pass on to the second part of this method, I shall first set forth1 the object aimed at, and next the means for its attainment3. The object aimed at is the acquisition of clear and distinct ideas, such as are produced by the pure intellect, and not by chance physical motions. In order that all ideas may be reduced to unity4, we shall endeavor so to associate and arrange them that our mind may, as far as possible, reflect subjectively5 the reality of nature, both as a whole and as parts.
As for the first point, it is necessary (as we have said) for our purpose that everything should be conceived, either solely6 through its essence, or through its proximate cause. If the thing be self-existent, or, as is commonly said, the cause of itself, it must be understood through its essence only; if it be not self-existent, but requires a cause for its existence, it must be understood through its proximate cause. For, in reality, the knowledge 31 of an effect is nothing else than the acquisition of more perfect knowledge of its cause.
Therefore, we may never, while we are concerned with inquiries7 into actual things, draw any conclusion from abstractions; we shall be extremely careful not to confound that which is only in the understanding with that which is in the thing itself. The best basis for drawing a conclusion will be either some particular affirmative essence, or a true and legitimate8 definition. For the understanding cannot descend9 from universal axioms by themselves to particular things, since axioms are of infinite extent, and do not determine the understanding to contemplate10 one particular thing more than another.
30 The chief rule of this part is, as appears from the first part, to review all the ideas coming to us through pure intellect, so as to distinguish them from such as we imagine: the distinction will be shown through the properties of each, namely, of the imagination and of the understanding.
31 Observe that it is thereby11 manifest that we cannot understand anything of nature without at the same time increasing our knowledge of the first cause, or God.
Its means, good definitions Conditions of definition
Thus the true method of discovery is to form thoughts from some given definition. This process will be the more fruitful and easy in proportion as the thing given be better defined. Wherefore, the cardinal12 point of all this second part of method consists in the knowledge of the conditions of good definition, and the means of finding them. I will first treat of the conditions of definition.
A definition, if it is to be called perfect, must explain the inmost essence of a thing, and must take care not to substitute for this any of its properties. In order to illustrate13 my meaning, without taking an example which would seem to show a desire to expose other people’s errors, I will choose the case of something abstract, the definition of which is of little moment. Such is a circle. If a circle be defined as a figure, such that all straight lines drawn14 from the center to the circumference15 are equal, every one can see that such a definition does not in the least explain the essence of a circle, but solely one of its properties. Though, as I have said, this is of no importance in the case of figures and other abstractions, it is of great importance in the case of physical beings and realities: for the properties of things are not understood so long as their essences are unknown. If the latter be passed over, there is necessarily a perversion16 of the succession of ideas which should reflect the succession of nature, and we go far astray from our object.
In order to be free from this fault, the following rules should be observed in definition:—
I. If the thing in question be created, the definition must (as we have said) comprehend the proximate cause. For instance, a circle should, according to this rule, be defined as follows: the figure described by any line whereof one end is fixed17 and the other free. This definition clearly comprehends the proximate cause.
II. A conception or definition of a thing should be such that all the properties of that thing, in so far as it is considered by itself, and not in conjunction with other things, can be deduced from it, as may be seen in the definition given of a circle: for from that it clearly follows that all straight lines drawn from the center to the circumference are equal. That this is a necessary characteristic of a definition is so clear to anyone, who reflects on the matter, that there is no need to spend time in proving it, or in showing that, owing to this second condition, every definition should be affirmative. I speak of intellectual affirmation, giving little thought to verbal affirmations which, owing to the poverty of language, must sometimes, perhaps, be expressed negatively, though the idea contained is affirmative.
The rules for the definition of an uncreated thing are as follows:—
I. The exclusion18 of all idea of cause — that is, the thing must not need explanation by Anything outside itself.
II. When the definition of the thing has been given, there must be no room for doubt as to whether the thing exists or not.
III. It must contain, as far as the mind is concerned, no substantives19 which could be put into an adjectival form; in other words, the object defined must not be explained through abstractions.
IV. Lastly, though this is not absolutely necessary, it should be possible to deduce from the definition all the properties of the thing defined.
All these rules become obvious to anyone giving strict attention to the matter.
I have also stated that the best basis for drawing a conclusion is a particular affirmative essence. The more specialized20 the idea is, the more it is distinct, and therefore clear. Wherefore a knowledge of particular things should be sought for as diligently21 as possible.
As regards the order of our perceptions, and the manner in which they should be arranged and united, it is necessary that, as soon as is possible and rational, we should inquire whether there be any being (and, if so, what being), that is the cause of all things, so that its essence, represented in thought, may be the cause of all our ideas, and then our mind will to the utmost possible extent reflect nature. For it will possess, subjectively, nature’s essence, order, and union. Thus we can see that it is before all things necessary for us to deduce all our ideas from physical things — that is, from real entities22, proceeding23, as far as may be, according to the series of causes, from one real entity24 to another real entity, never passing to universals and abstractions, either for the purpose of deducing some real entity from them, or deducing them from some real entity. Either of these processes interrupts the true progress of the understanding.
But it must be observed that, by the series of causes and real entities, I do not here mean the series of particular and mutable things, but only the series of fixed and eternal things. It would be impossible for human infirmity to follow up the series of particular mutable things, both on account their multitude, surpassing all calculation, and on account of the infinitely25 diverse circumstances surrounding one and the same thing, any one of which may be the cause of its existence or non-existence. Indeed, their existence has no connection with their essence, or (as we have said already) is not an eternal truth.
Neither is there any need that we should understand their series, for the essences of particular mutable things are not to be gathered from their series or order of existence, which would furnish us with nothing beyond their extrinsic26 denominations27, their relations, or, at most, their circumstances, all of which are very different from their inmost essence. This inmost essence must be sought solely from fixed and eternal things, and from the laws, inscribed28 (so to speak) in those things as in their true codes, according to which all particular things take place and are arranged; nay29, these mutable particular things depend so intimately and essentially30 (so to phrase it) upon the fixed things, that they cannot either be conceived without them.
But, though this be so, there seems to be no small difficulty in arriving at the knowledge of these particular things, for to conceive them all at once would far surpass the powers of the human understanding. The arrangement whereby one thing is understood, before another, as we have stated, should not be sought from their series of existence, nor from eternal things. For the latter are all by nature simultaneous. Other aids are therefore needed besides those employed for understanding eternal things and their laws. However, this is not the place to recount such aids, nor is there any need to do so, until we have acquired a sufficient knowledge of eternal things and their infallible laws, and until the nature of our senses has become plain to us.
Before betaking ourselves to seek knowledge of particular things, it will be seasonable to speak of such aids, as all tend to teach us the mode of employing our senses, and to make certain experiments under fixed rules and arrangements which may suffice to determine the object of our inquiry31, so that we may therefrom infer what laws of eternal things it has been produced under, and may gain an insight into its inmost nature, as I will duly show. Here, to return to my purpose, I will only endeavor to set forth what seems necessary for enabling us to attain2 to knowledge of eternal things, and to define them under the conditions laid down above.
With this end, we must bear in mind what has already been stated, namely, that when the mind devotes itself to any thought, so as to examine it, and to deduce therefrom in due order all the legitimate conclusions possible, any falsehood which may lurk32 in the thought will be detected; but if the thought be true, the mind will readily proceed without interruption to deduce truths from it. This, I say, is necessary for our purpose, for our thoughts may be brought to a close by the absence of a foundation.
If, therefore, we wish to investigate the first thing of all, it will be necessary to supply some foundation which may direct our thoughts thither33. Further, since method is reflective knowledge, the foundation which must direct our thoughts can be nothing else than the knowledge of that which constitutes the reality of truth, and the knowledge of the understanding, its properties, and powers. When this has been acquired we shall possess a foundation wherefrom we can deduce our thoughts, and a path whereby the intellect, according to its capacity, may attain the knowledge of eternal things, allowance being made for the extent of the intellectual powers.
If, as I stated in the first part, it belongs to the nature of thought to form true ideas, we must here inquire what is meant by the faculties34 and power of the understanding. The chief part of our method is to understand as well as possible the powers of the intellect, and its nature; we are, therefore, compelled (by the considerations advanced in the second part of the method) necessarily to draw these conclusions from the definition itself of thought and understanding.
How to define understanding
But, so far as we have not got any rules for finding definitions, and, as we cannot set forth such rules without a previous knowledge of nature, that is without a definition of the understanding and its power, it follows either that the definition of the understanding must be clear in itself, or that we can understand nothing. Nevertheless this definition is not absolutely clear in itself; however, since its properties, like all things that we possess through the understanding, cannot be known clearly and distinctly, unless its nature be known previously35, understanding makes itself manifest, if we pay attention to its properties, which we know clearly and distinctly. Let us, then, enumerate36 here the properties of the understanding, let us examine them, and begin by discussing the instruments for research which we find innate37 in us. See [para. 31]
The properties of the understanding which I have chiefly remarked, and which I clearly understand, are the following:—
I. It involves certainty — in other words, it knows that a thing exists in reality as it is reflected subjectively.
II. That it perceives certain things, or forms some ideas absolutely, some ideas from others. Thus it forms the idea of quantity absolutely, without reference to any other thoughts; but ideas of motion it only forms after taking into consideration the idea of quantity.
III. Those ideas which the understanding forms absolutely express infinity38; determinate ideas are derived39 from other ideas. Thus in the idea of quantity, perceived by means of a cause, the quantity is determined40, as when a body is perceived to be formed by the motion of a plane, a plane by the motion of a line, or, again, a line by the motion of a point. All these are perceptions which do not serve towards understanding quantity, but only towards determining it. This is proved by the fact that we conceive them as formed as it were by motion, yet this motion is not perceived unless the quantity be perceived also; we can even prolong the motion to form an infinite line, which we certainly could not do unless we had an idea of infinite quantity.
IV. The understanding forms positive ideas before forming negative ideas.
V. It perceives things not so much under the condition of duration as under a certain form of eternity41, and in an infinite number; or rather in perceiving things it does not consider either their number or duration, whereas, in imagining them, it perceives them in a determinate number, duration, and quantity.
VI. The ideas which we form as clear and distinct, seem to follow from the sole necessity of our nature, that they appear to depend absolutely on our sole power; with confused ideas the contrary is the case. They are often formed against our will.
VII. The mind can determine in many ways the ideas of things, which the understanding forms from other ideas: thus, for instance, in order to define the plane of an ellipse, it supposes a point adhering to a cord to be moved around two centers, or, again, it conceives an infinity of points, always in the same fixed relation to a given straight line, angle of the vertex of the cone42, or in an infinity of other ways.
VIII. The more ideas express perfection of any object, the more perfect are they themselves; for we do not admire the architect who has planned a chapel43 so much as the architect who has planned a splendid temple.
I do not stop to consider the rest of what is referred to thought, such as love, joy, &c. They are nothing to our present purpose, and cannot even be conceived unless the understanding be perceived previously. When perception is removed, all these go with it.
False and fictitious44 ideas have nothing positive about them (as we have abundantly shown), which causes them to be called false or fictitious; they are only considered as such through the defectiveness45 of knowledge. Therefore, false and fictitious ideas as such can teach us nothing concerning the essence of thought; this must be sought from the positive properties just enumerated46; in other words, we must lay down some common basis from which these properties necessarily follow, so that when this is given, the properties are necessarily given also, and when it is removed, they too vanish with it.
The rest of the treatise47 is wanting.
The End
点击收听单词发音
1 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 attainment | |
n.达到,到达;[常pl.]成就,造诣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 unity | |
n.团结,联合,统一;和睦,协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 subjectively | |
主观地; 臆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 inquiries | |
n.调查( inquiry的名词复数 );疑问;探究;打听 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 legitimate | |
adj.合法的,合理的,合乎逻辑的;v.使合法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 descend | |
vt./vi.传下来,下来,下降 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 contemplate | |
vt.盘算,计议;周密考虑;注视,凝视 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 cardinal | |
n.(天主教的)红衣主教;adj.首要的,基本的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 illustrate | |
v.举例说明,阐明;图解,加插图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 circumference | |
n.圆周,周长,圆周线 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 perversion | |
n.曲解;堕落;反常 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 exclusion | |
n.拒绝,排除,排斥,远足,远途旅行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 substantives | |
n.作名词用的词或词组(substantive的复数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 specialized | |
adj.专门的,专业化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 diligently | |
ad.industriously;carefully | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 entities | |
实体对像; 实体,独立存在体,实际存在物( entity的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 proceeding | |
n.行动,进行,(pl.)会议录,学报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 entity | |
n.实体,独立存在体,实际存在物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 infinitely | |
adv.无限地,无穷地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 extrinsic | |
adj.外部的;不紧要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 denominations | |
n.宗派( denomination的名词复数 );教派;面额;名称 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 inscribed | |
v.写,刻( inscribe的过去式和过去分词 );内接 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 nay | |
adv.不;n.反对票,投反对票者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 lurk | |
n.潜伏,潜行;v.潜藏,潜伏,埋伏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 thither | |
adv.向那里;adj.在那边的,对岸的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 faculties | |
n.能力( faculty的名词复数 );全体教职员;技巧;院 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 enumerate | |
v.列举,计算,枚举,数 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 innate | |
adj.天生的,固有的,天赋的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 infinity | |
n.无限,无穷,大量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 eternity | |
n.不朽,来世;永恒,无穷 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 cone | |
n.圆锥体,圆锥形东西,球果 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 chapel | |
n.小教堂,殡仪馆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 fictitious | |
adj.虚构的,假设的;空头的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 defectiveness | |
n.有缺陷,缺乏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 enumerated | |
v.列举,枚举,数( enumerate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 treatise | |
n.专著;(专题)论文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |