There is a hierarchy2 of facts; some have no reach; they teach us nothing but themselves. The scientist who has ascertained3 them has learned nothing but a fact, and has not become more capable of foreseeing new facts. Such facts, it seems, come once, but are not destined4 to reappear.
There are, on the other hand, facts of great yield; each of them teaches us a new law. And since a choice must be made, it is to these that the scientist should devote himself.
Doubtless this classification is relative and depends upon the weakness of our mind. The facts of slight outcome are the complex facts, upon which various circumstances may exercise a sensible influence, circumstances too numerous and too diverse for us to discern them all. But I should rather say that these are the facts we think complex, since the intricacy of these circumstances surpasses the range of our mind. Doubtless a mind vaster and finer than ours would think differently of them. But what matter; we can not use that superior mind, but only our own.
The facts of great outcome are those we think simple; may be they really are so, because they are influenced only by a small number of well-defined circumstances, may be they take on an appearance of simplicity5 because the various circumstances upon which they depend obey the laws of chance and so come to mutually compensate6. And this is what happens most often. And so we have been obliged to examine somewhat more closely what chance is.
Facts where the laws of chance apply become easy of access to the scientist who would be discouraged before the extraordinary complication of the problems where these laws are not applicable. We have seen that these considerations apply not only to the physical sciences, but to the mathematical sciences. The method of demonstration7 is not the same for the physicist8 and the mathematician9. But the methods of invention are very much alike. In both cases they consist in passing up from the fact to the law, and in finding the facts capable of leading to a law.
To bring out this point, I have shown the mind of the mathematician at work, and under three forms: the mind of the mathematical inventor and creator; that of the unconscious geometer who among our far distant ancestors, or in the misty10 years of our infancy11, has constructed for us our instinctive12 notion of space; that of the adolescent to whom the teachers of secondary education unveil the first principles of the science, seeking to give understanding of the fundamental definitions. Everywhere we have seen the r?le of intuition and of the spirit of generalization13 without which these three stages of mathematicians14, if I may so express myself, would be reduced to an equal impotence.
And in the demonstration itself, the logic15 is not all; the true mathematical reasoning is a veritable induction16, different in many regards from the induction of physics, but proceeding17 like it from the particular to the general. All the efforts that have been made to reverse this order and to carry back mathematical induction to the rules of logic have eventuated only in failures, illy concealed18 by the employment of a language inaccessible19 to the uninitiated. The examples I have taken from the physical sciences have shown us very different cases of facts of great outcome. An experiment of Kaufmann on radium rays revolutionizes at the same time mechanics, optics and astronomy. Why? Because in proportion as these sciences have developed, we have the better recognized the bonds uniting them, and then we have perceived a species of general design of the chart of universal science. There are facts common to several sciences, which seem the common source of streams diverging20 in all directions and which are comparable to that knoll21 of Saint Gothard whence spring waters which fertilize22 four different valleys.
And then we can make choice of facts with more discernment than our predecessors23 who regarded these valleys as distinct and separated by impassable barriers.
It is always simple facts which must be chosen, but among these simple facts we must prefer those which are situated24 upon these sorts of knolls25 of Saint Gothard of which I have just spoken.
And when sciences have no direct bond, they still mutually throw light upon one another by analogy. When we studied the laws obeyed by gases we knew we had attacked a fact of great outcome; and yet this outcome was still estimated beneath its value, since gases are, from a certain point of view, the image of the milky26 way, and those facts which seemed of interest only for the physicist, ere long opened new vistas27 to astronomy quite unexpected.
And finally when the geodesist sees it is necessary to move his telescope some seconds to see a signal he has set up with great pains, this is a very small fact; but this is a fact of great outcome, not only because this reveals to him the existence of a small protuberance upon the terrestrial globe, that little hump would be by itself of no great interest, but because this protuberance gives him information about the distribution of matter in the interior of the globe, and through that about the past of our planet, about its future, about the laws of its development.
The End
点击收听单词发音
1 expounded | |
论述,详细讲解( expound的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 hierarchy | |
n.等级制度;统治集团,领导层 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 ascertained | |
v.弄清,确定,查明( ascertain的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 simplicity | |
n.简单,简易;朴素;直率,单纯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 compensate | |
vt.补偿,赔偿;酬报 vi.弥补;补偿;抵消 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 demonstration | |
n.表明,示范,论证,示威 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 physicist | |
n.物理学家,研究物理学的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 mathematician | |
n.数学家 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 misty | |
adj.雾蒙蒙的,有雾的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 infancy | |
n.婴儿期;幼年期;初期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 instinctive | |
adj.(出于)本能的;直觉的;(出于)天性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 generalization | |
n.普遍性,一般性,概括 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 mathematicians | |
数学家( mathematician的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 logic | |
n.逻辑(学);逻辑性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 induction | |
n.感应,感应现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 proceeding | |
n.行动,进行,(pl.)会议录,学报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 concealed | |
a.隐藏的,隐蔽的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 inaccessible | |
adj.达不到的,难接近的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 diverging | |
分开( diverge的现在分词 ); 偏离; 分歧; 分道扬镳 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 knoll | |
n.小山,小丘 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 fertilize | |
v.使受精,施肥于,使肥沃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 predecessors | |
n.前任( predecessor的名词复数 );前辈;(被取代的)原有事物;前身 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 situated | |
adj.坐落在...的,处于某种境地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 knolls | |
n.小圆丘,小土墩( knoll的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 milky | |
adj.牛奶的,多奶的;乳白色的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 vistas | |
长条形景色( vista的名词复数 ); 回顾; 展望; (未来可能发生的)一系列情景 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |