“What are you, where did you come from, and whither are you bound?”— the question which from Homer’s days has been put to the wayfarer2 in strange lands — is likewise the all-absorbing question which man is ever asking of the universe of which he is himself so tiny yet so wondrous3 a part. From the earliest times the ultimate purpose of all scientific research has been to elicit4 fragmentary or partial responses to this question, and philosophy has ever busied itself in piecing together these several bits of information according to the best methods at its disposal, in order to make up something like a satisfactory answer. In old times the best methods which philosophy had at its disposal for this purpose were such as now seem very crude, and accordingly ancient philosophers bungled5 considerably6 in their task, though now and then they came surprisingly near what would to-day be called the truth. It was natural that their methods should be crude, for scientific inquiry7 had as yet supplied but scanty8 materials for them to work with, and it was only after a very long course of speculation9 and criticism that men could find out what ways of going to work are likely to prove successful and what are not. The earliest thinkers, indeed, were further hindered from accomplishing much by the imperfections of the language by the aid of which their thinking was done; for science and philosophy have had to make a serviceable terminology10 by dint11 of long and arduous12 trial and practice, and linguistic13 processes fit for expressing general or abstract notions accurately14 grew up only through numberless failures and at the expense of much inaccurate15 thinking and loose talking. As in most of nature’s processes, there was a great waste of energy before a good result could be secured. Accordingly primitive16 men were very wide of the mark in their views of nature. To them the world was a sort of enchanted17 ground, peopled with sprites and goblins; the quaint18 notions with which we now amuse our children in fairy tales represent a style of thinking which once was current among grown men and women, and which is still current wherever men remain in a savage19 condition. The theories of the world wrought20 out by early priest-philosophers were in great part made up of such grotesque21 notions; and having become variously implicated22 with ethical23 opinions as to the nature and consequences of right and wrong behaviour, they acquired a kind of sanctity, so that any thinker who in the light of a wider experience ventured to alter or amend24 the primitive theory was likely to be vituperated as an irreligious man or atheist25. This sort of inference has not yet been wholly abandoned, even in civilized26 communities. Even to-day books are written about “the conflict between religion and science,” and other books are written with intent to reconcile the two presumed antagonists27. But when we look beneath the surface of things, we see that in reality there has never been any conflict between religion and science, nor is any reconciliation28 called for where harmony has always existed. The real historical conflict, which has been thus curiously29 misnamed, has been the conflict between the more-crude opinions belonging to the science of an earlier age and the less-crude opinions belonging to the science of a later age. In the course of this contest the more-crude opinions have usually been defended in the name of religion, and the less-crude opinions have invariably won the victory; but religion itself, which is not concerned with opinion, but with the aspiration31 which leads us to strive after a purer and holier life, has seldom or never been attacked. On the contrary, the scientific men who have conducted the battle on behalf of the less-crude opinions have generally been influenced by this religious aspiration quite as strongly as the apologists of the more-crude opinions, and so far from religious feeling having been weakened by their perennial34 series of victories, it has apparently35 been growing deeper and stronger all the time. The religious sense is as yet too feebly developed in most of us; but certainly in no preceding age have men taken up the work of life with more earnestness or with more real faith in the unseen than at the present day, when so much of what was once deemed all-important knowledge has been consigned36 to the limbo37 of mythology38.
The more-crude theories of early times are to be chiefly distinguished39 from the less-crude theories of to-day as being largely the products of random40 guesswork. Hypothesis, or guesswork, indeed, lies at the foundation of all scientific knowledge. The riddle41 of the universe, like less important riddles42, is unravelled43 only by approximative trials, and the most brilliant discoverers have usually been the bravest guessers. Kepler’s laws were the result of indefatigable44 guessing, and so, in a somewhat different sense, was the wave-theory of light. But the guesswork of scientific inquirers is very different now from what it was in older times. In the first place, we have slowly learned that a guess must be verified before it can be accepted as a sound theory; and, secondly45, so many truths have been established beyond contravention, that the latitude46 for hypothesis is much less than it once was. Nine tenths of the guesses which might have occurred to a mediaeval philosopher would now be ruled out as inadmissible, because they would not harmonize with the knowledge which has been acquired since the Middle Ages. There is one direction especially in which this continuous limitation of guesswork by ever-accumulating experience has manifested itself. From first to last, all our speculative48 successes and failures have agreed in teaching us that the most general principles of action which prevail to-day, and in our own corner of the universe, have always prevailed throughout as much of the universe as is accessible to our research. They have taught us that for the deciphering of the past and the predicting of the future, no hypotheses are admissible which are not based upon the actual behaviour of things in the present. Once there was unlimited49 facility for guessing as to how the solar system might have come into existence; now the origin of the sun and planets is adequately explained when we have unfolded all that is implied in the processes which are still going on in the solar system. Formerly50 appeals were made to all manner of violent agencies to account for the changes which the earth’s surface has undergone since our planet began its independent career; now it is seen that the same slow working of rain and tide, of wind and wave and frost, of secular51 contraction52 and of earthquake pulse, which is visible to-day, will account for the whole. It is not long since it was supposed that a species of animals or plants could be swept away only by some unusual catastrophe53, while for the origination of new species something called an act of “special creation” was necessary; and as to the nature of such extraordinary events there was endless room for guesswork; but the discovery of natural selection was the discovery of a process, going on perpetually under our very eyes, which must inevitably54 of itself extinguish some species and bring new ones into being. In these and countless55 other ways we have learned that all the rich variety of nature is pervaded56 by unity57 of action, such as we might expect to find if nature is the manifestation58 of an infinite God who is without variableness or shadow of turning, but quite incompatible59 with the fitful behaviour of the anthropomorphic deities60 of the old mythologies61. By thus abstaining62 from all appeal to agencies that are extra-cosmic, or not involved in the orderly system of events that we see occurring around us, we have at last succeeded in eliminating from philosophic63 speculation the character of random guesswork which at first of necessity belonged to it. Modern scientific hypothesis is so far from being a haphazard64 mental proceeding65 that it is perhaps hardly fair to classify it with guesses. It is lifted out of the plane of guesswork, in so far as it has acquired the character of inevitable66 inference from that which now is to that which has been or will be. Instead of the innumerable particular assumptions which were once admitted into cosmic philosophy, we are now reduced to the one universal assumption which has been variously described as the “principle of continuity,” the “uniformity of nature,” the “persistence of force,” or the “law of causation,” and which has been variously explained as a necessary datum67 for scientific thinking or as a net result of all induction68. I am not unwilling69, however, to adopt the language of a book which has furnished the occasion for the present discussion, and to say that this grand assumption is a supreme70 act of faith, the definite expression of a trust that the infinite Sustainer of the universe “will not put us to permanent intellectual confusion.” For in this mode of statement the harmony between the scientific and the religious points of view is well brought out. It is as affording the only outlet71 from permanent intellectual confusion that inquirers have been driven to appeal to the principle of continuity; and it is by unswerving reliance upon this principle that we have obtained such insight into the past, present, and future of the world as we now possess.
The work just mentioned1 is especially interesting as an attempt to bring the probable destiny of the human soul into connection with the modern theories which explain the past and future career of the physical universe in accordance with the principle of continuity. Its authorship is as yet unknown, but it is believed to be the joint72 production of two of the most eminent73 physicists74 in Great Britain, and certainly the accurate knowledge and the ingenuity75 and subtlety76 of thought displayed in it are such as to lend great probability to this conjecture77. Some account of the argument it contains may well precede the suggestions presently to be set forth79 concerning the Unseen World; and we shall find it most convenient to begin, like our authors, with a brief statement of what the principle of continuity teaches as to the proximate beginning and end of the visible universe. I shall in the main set down only results, having elsewhere2 given a simple exposition of the arguments upon which these results are founded.
1 The Unseen Universe; or, Physical Speculations80 on a Future State. [Attributed to Professors TAIT and BALFOUR STEWART.] New York: Macmillan & Co. 1875. 8vo. pp. 212.
2 Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy, based on the Doctrine81 of Evolution. Boston: J. R. Osgood & Co. 1875. 2 vols. 8vo.
The first great cosmological speculation which has been raised quite above the plane of guesswork by making no other assumption than that of the uniformity of nature, is the well-known Nebular Hypothesis. Every astronomer84 knows that the earth, like all other cosmical bodies which are flattened85 at the poles, was formerly a mass of fluid, and consequently filled a much larger space than at present. It is further agreed, on all hands, that the sun is a contracting body, since there is no other possible way of accounting86 for the enormous quantity of heat which he generates. The so-called primeval nebula83 follows as a necessary inference from these facts. There was once a time when the earth was distended87 on all sides away out to the moon and beyond it, so that the matter now contained in the moon was then a part of our equatorial zone. And at a still remoter date in the past, the mass of the sun was diffused88 in every direction beyond the orbit of Neptune89, and no planet had an individual existence, for all were indistinguishable parts of the solar mass. When the great mass of the sun, increased by the relatively90 small mass of all the planets put together, was spread out in this way, it was a rare vapour or gas. At the period where the question is taken up in Laplace’s treatment of the nebular theory, the shape of this mass is regarded as spheroidal; but at an earlier period its shape may well have been as irregular as that of any of the nebulae which we now see in distant parts of the heavens, for, whatever its primitive shape, the equalization of its rotation91 would in time make it spheroidal. That the QUANTITY of rotation was the same then as now is unquestionable; for no system of particles, great or small, can acquire or lose rotation by any action going on within itself, any more than a man could pick himself up by his waistband and lift himself over a stone wale So that the primitive rotating spheroidal solar nebula is not a matter of assumption, but is just what must once have existed, provided there has been no breach92 of continuity in nature’s operations. Now proceeding to reason back from the past to the present, it has been shown that the abandonment of successive equatorial belts by the contracting solar mass must have ensued in accordance with known mechanical laws; and in similar wise, under ordinary circumstances. each belt must have parted into fragments, and the fragments chasing each other around the same orbit, must have at last coalesced93 into a spheroidal planet. Not only this, but it has also been shown that as the result of such a process the relative sizes of the planets would be likely to take the order which they now follow; that the ring immediately succeeding that of Jupiter would be likely to abort95 and produce a great number of tiny planets instead of one good-sized one; that the outer planets would be likely to have many moons, and that Saturn96, besides having the greatest number of moons, would be likely to retain some of his inner rings unbroken; that the earth would be likely to have a long day and Jupiter a short one; that the extreme outer planets would be not unlikely to rotate in a retrograde direction; and so on, through a long list of interesting and striking details. Not only, therefore, are we driven to the inference that our solar system was once a vaporous nebula, but we find that the mere97 contraction of such a nebula, under the influence of the enormous mutual98 gravitation of its particles, carries with it the explanation of both the more general and the more particular features of the present system. So that we may fairly regard this stupendous process as veritable matter of history, while we proceed to study it under some further aspects and to consider what consequences are likely to follow.
Our attention should first be directed to the enormous waste of energy which has accompanied this contraction of the solar nebula. The first result of such a contraction is the generation of a great quantity of heat, and when the heat thus generated has been lost by radiation into surrounding space it becomes possible for the contraction to continue. Thus, as concentration goes on, heat is incessantly99 generated and incessantly dissipated. How long this process is to endure depends chiefly on the size of the contracting mass, as small bodies radiate heat much faster than large ones. The moon seems to be already thoroughly100 refrigerated, while Jupiter and Saturn are very much hotter than the earth, as is shown by the tremendous atmospheric101 phenomena102 which occur on their surfaces. The sun, again, generates heat so rapidly, owing to his great energy of contraction, and loses it so slowly, owing to his great size, that his surface is always kept in a state of incandescence103. His surface-temperature is estimated at some three million degrees of Fahrenheit104, and a diminution105 of his diameter far too small to be detected by the finest existing instruments would suffice to maintain the present supply of heat for more than fifty centuries. These facts point to a very long future during which the sun will continue to warm the earth and its companion planets, but at the same time they carry on their face the story of inevitable ultimate doom106. If things continue to go on as they have all along gone on, the sun must by and by grow black and cold, and all life whatever throughout the solar system must come to an end. Long before this consummation, however, life will probably have become extinct through the refrigeration of each of the planets into a state like the present state of the moon, in which the atmosphere and oceans have disappeared from the surface. No doubt the sun will continue to give out heat a long time after heat has ceased to be needed for the support of living organisms. For the final refrigeration of the sun will long be postponed107 by the fate of the planets themselves. The separation of the planets from their parent solar mass seems to be after all but a temporary separation. So nicely balanced are they now in their orbits that they may well seem capable of rolling on in their present courses forever. But this is not the case. Two sets of circumstances are all the while striving, the one to drive the planets farther away from the sun, the other to draw them all into it. On the one hand, every body in our system which contains fluid matter has tides raised upon its surface by the attraction of neighbouring bodies. All the planets raise tides upon the surface of the sun and the periodicity of sun-spots (or solar cyclones) depends upon this fact. These tidal waves act as a drag or brake upon the rotation of the sun, somewhat diminishing its rapidity. But, in conformity108 with a principle of mechanics well known to astronomers109, though not familiar to the general reader, all the motion of rotation thus lost by the sun is added to the planets in the shape of annual motion of revolution, and thus their orbits all tend to enlarge — they all tend to recede78 somewhat from the sun. But this state of things, though long-enduring enough, is after all only temporary, and will at any rate come to an end when the sun and planets have become solid. Meanwhile another set of circumstances is all the time tending to bring the planets nearer to the sun, and in the long run must gain the mastery. The space through which the planets move is filled with a kind of matter which serves as a medium for the transmission of heat and light, and this kind of matter, though different in some respects from ordinary ponderable matter, is yet like it in exerting friction110. This friction is almost infinitely111 little, yet it has a wellnigh infinite length of time to work in, and during all this wellnigh infinite length of time it is slowly eating up the momentum112 of the planets and diminishing their ability to maintain their distances from the sun. Hence in course of time the planets will all fall into the sun, one after another, so that the solar system will end, as it began, by consisting of a single mass of matter.
But this is by no means the end of the story. When two bodies rush together, each parts with some of its energy of motion, and this lost energy of motion reappears as heat. In the concussion113 of two cosmical bodies, like the sun and the earth, an enormous quantity of motion is thus converted into heat. Now heat, when not allowed to radiate, or when generated faster than it can be radiated, is transformed into motion of expansion. Hence the shock of sun and planet would at once result in the vaporization of both bodies; and there can be no doubt that by the time the sun has absorbed the outermost114 of his attendant planets, he will have resumed something like his original nebulous condition. He will have been dilated115 into a huge mass of vapour, and will have become fit for a new process of contraction and for a new production of life-bearing planets.
We are now, however, confronted by an interesting but difficult question. Throughout all this grand past and future career of the solar system which we have just briefly116 traced, we have been witnessing a most prodigal117 dissipation of energy in the shape of radiant heat. At the outset we had an enormous quantity of what is called “energy of position,” that is, the outer parts of our primitive nebula had a very long distance through which to travel towards one another in the slow process of concentration; and this distance was the measure of the quantity of work possible to our system. As the particles of our nebula drew nearer and nearer together, the energy of position continually lost reappeared continually as heat, of which the greater part was radiated off, but of which a certain amount was retained. All the gigantic amount of work achieved in the geologic118 development of our earth and its companion planets, and in the development of life wherever life may exist in our system, has been the product of this retained heat. At the present day the same wasteful119 process is going on. Each moment the sun’s particles are losing energy of position as they draw closer and closer together, and the heat into which this lost energy is metamorphosed is poured out most prodigally120 in every direction. Let us consider for a moment how little of it gets used in our system. The earth’s orbit is a nearly circular figure more than five hundred million miles in circumference121, while only eight thousand miles of this path are at any one time occupied by the earth’s mass. Through these eight thousand miles the sun’s radiated energy is doing work, but through the remainder of the five hundred million it is idle and wasted. But the case is far more striking when we reflect that it is not in the plane of the earth’s orbit only that the sun’s radiance is being poured out. It is not an affair of a circle, but of a sphere. In order to utilize122 all the solar rays, we should need to have an immense number of earths arranged so as to touch each other, forming a hollow sphere around the sun, with the present radius123 of the earth’s orbit. We may well believe Professor Tyndall, therefore, when he tells us that all the solar radiance we receive is less than a two-billionth part of what is sent flying through the desert regions of space. Some of the immense residue124 of course hits other planets stationed in the way of it, and is utilized125 upon their surfaces; but the planets, all put together, stop so little of the total quantity that our startling illustration is not materially altered by taking them into the account. Now this two-billionth part of the solar radiance poured out from moment to moment suffices to blow every wind, to raise every cloud, to drive every engine, to build up the tissue of every plant, to sustain the activity of every animal, including man, upon the surface of our vast and stately globe. Considering the wondrous richness and variety of the terrestrial life wrought out by the few sunbeams which we catch in our career through space, we may well pause overwhelmed and stupefied at the thought of the incalculable possibilities of existence which are thrown away with the potent126 actinism that darts127 unceasingly into the unfathomed abysms of immensity. Where it goes to or what becomes of it, no one of us can surmise128.
Now when, in the remote future, our sun is reduced to vapour by the impact of the several planets upon his surface, the resulting nebulous mass must be a very insignificant129 affair compared with the nebulous mass with which we started. In order to make a second nebula equal in size and potential energy to the first one, all the energy of position at first existing should have been retained in some form or other. But nearly all of it has been lost, and only an insignificant fraction remains130 with which to endow a new system. In order to reproduce, in future ages, anything like that cosmical development which is now going on in the solar system, aid must be sought from without. We must endeavour to frame some valid131 hypothesis as to the relation of our solar system to other systems.
Thus far our view has been confined to the career of a single star — our sun — with the tiny, easily-cooling balls which it has cast off in the course of its development. Thus far, too, our inferences have been very secure, for we have been dealing132 with a circumscribed133 group of phenomena, the beginning and end of which have been brought pretty well within the compass of our imagination. It is quite another thing to deal with the actual or probable career of the stars in general, inasmuch as we do not even know how many stars there are, which form parts of a common system, or what. are their precise dynamic relations to one another. Nevertheless we have knowledge of a few facts which may support some cautious inferences. All the stars which we can see are undoubtedly134 bound together by relations of gravitation. No doubt our sun attracts all the other stars within our ken33, and is reciprocally attracted by them. The stars, too, lie mostly in or around one great plane, as is the case with the members of the solar system. Moreover, the stars are shown by the spectroscope to consist of chemical elements identical with those which are found in the solar system. Such facts as these make it probable that the career of other stars, when adequately inquired into, would be found to be like that of our own sun. Observation daily enhances this probability, for our study of the sidereal135 universe is continually showing us stars in all stages of development. We find irregular nebulae, for example; we find spiral and spheroidal nebulae; we find stars which have got beyond the nebulous stage, but are still at a whiter heat than our sun; and we also find many stars which yield the same sort of spectrum136 as our sun. The inference seems forced upon us that the same process of concentration which has gone on in the case of our solar nebula has been going on in the case of other nebulae. The history of the sun is but a type of the history of stars in general. And when we consider that all other visible stars and nebulae are cooling and contracting bodies, like our sun, to what other conclusion could we very well come? When we look at Sirius, for instance, we do not see him surrounded by planets, for at such a distance no planet could be visible, even Sirius himself, though fourteen times larger than our sun, appearing only as a “twinkling little star.” But a comparative survey of the heavens assures us that Sirius can hardly have arrived at his present stage of concentration without detaching, planet-forming rings, for there is no reason for supposing that mechanical laws out there are at all different from what they are in our own system. And the same kind of inference must apply to all the matured stars which we see in the heavens.
When we duly take all these things into the account, the case of our solar system will appear as only one of a thousand cases of evolution and dissolution with which the heavens furnish us. Other stars, like our sun, have undoubtedly started as vaporous masses, and have thrown off planets in contracting. The inference may seem a bold one, but it after all involves no other assumption than that of the continuity of natural phenomena. It is not likely, therefore, that the solar system will forever be left to itself. Stars which strongly gravitate toward each other, while moving through a perennially137 resisting medium, must in time be drawn138 together. The collision of our extinct sun with one of the Pleiades, after this manner, would very likely suffice to generate even a grander nebula than the one with which we started. Possibly the entire galactic system may, in an inconceivably remote future, remodel139 itself in this way; and possibly the nebula from which our own group of planets has been formed may have owed its origin to the disintegration140 of systems which had accomplished141 their career in the depths of the bygone eternity142.
When the problem is extended to these huge dimensions, the prospect143 of an ultimate cessation of cosmical work is indefinitely postponed, but at the same time it becomes impossible for us to deal very securely with the questions we have raised. The magnitudes and periods we have introduced are so nearly infinite as to baffle speculation itself: One point, however, we seem dimly to discern. Supposing the stellar universe not to be absolutely infinite in extent, we may hold that the day of doom, so often postponed, must come at last. The concentration of matter and dissipation of energy, so often checked, must in the end prevail, so that, as the final outcome of things, the entire universe will be reduced to a single enormous ball, dead and frozen, solid and black, its potential energy of motion having been all transformed into heat and radiated away. Such a conclusion has been suggested by Sir William Thomson, and it is quite forcibly stated by the authors of “The Unseen Universe.” They remind us that “if there be any one form of energy less readily or less completely transformable than the others, and if transformations144 constantly go on, more and more of the whole energy of the universe will inevitably sink into this lower grade as time advances.” Now radiant heat, as we have seen, is such a lower grade of energy. “At each transformation145 of heat-energy into work, a large portion is degraded, while only a small portion is transformed into work. So that while it is very easy to change all of our mechanical or useful energy into heat, it is only possible to transform a portion of this heat-energy back again into work. After each change, too, the heat becomes more and more dissipated or degraded, and less and less available for any future transformation. In other words,” our authors continue, “the tendency of heat is towards equalization; heat is par1 excellence146 the communist of our universe, and it will no doubt ultimately bring the system to an end. . . . . It is absolutely certain that life, so far as it is physical, depends essentially147 upon transformations of energy; it is also absolutely certain that age after age the possibility of such transformations is becoming less and less; and, so far as we yet know, the final state of the present universe must be an aggregation148 (into one mass) of all the matter it contains, i. e. the potential energy gone, and a practically useless state of kinetic149 energy, i. e. uniform temperature throughout that mass.” Thus our authors conclude that the visible universe began in time and will in time come to an end; and they add that under the physical conditions of such a universe “immortality150 is impossible.”
Concerning the latter inference we shall by and by have something to say. Meanwhile this whole speculation as to the final cessation of cosmical work seems to me — as it does to my friend, Professor Clifford3 — by no means trustworthy. The conditions of the problem so far transcend152 our grasp that any such speculation must remain an unverifiable guess. I do not go with Professor Clifford in doubting whether the laws of mechanics are absolutely the same throughout eternity; I cannot quite reconcile such a doubt with faith in the principle of continuity. But it does seem to me needful, before we conclude that radiated energy is absolutely and forever wasted, that we should find out what becomes of it. What we call radiant heat is simply transverse wave-motion, propagated with enormous velocity153 through an ocean of subtle ethereal matter which bathes the atoms of all visible or palpable bodies and fills the whole of space, extending beyond the remotest star which the telescope can reach. Whether there are any bounds at all to this ethereal ocean, or whether it is as infinite as space itself, we cannot surmise. If it be limited, the possible dispersion of radiant energy is limited by its extent. Heat and light cannot travel through emptiness. If the ether is bounded by surrounding emptiness, then a ray of heat, on arriving at this limiting emptiness, would be reflected back as surely as a ball is sent back when thrown against a solid wall. If this be the case, it will not affect our conclusions concerning such a tiny region of space as is occupied by the solar system, but it will seriously modify Sir William Thomson’s suggestion as to the fate of the universe as a whole. The radiance thrown away by the sun is indeed lost so far as the future of our system is concerned, but not a single unit of it is lost from the universe. Sooner or later, reflected back in all directions, it must do work in one quarter or another, so that ultimate stagnation154 be comes impossible. It is true that no such return of radiant energy has been detected in our corner of the world; but we have not yet so far disentangled all the force-relations of the universe that we are entitled to regard such a return as impossible. This is one way of escape from the consummation of things depicted156 by our authors. Another way of escape is equally available, if we suppose that while the ether is without bounds the stellar universe also extends to infinity157. For in this case the reproduction of nebulous masses fit for generating new systems of worlds must go on through space that is endless, and consequently the process can never come to an end and can never have had a beginning. We have, therefore, three alternatives: either the visible universe is finite, while the ether is infinite; or both are finite; or both are infinite. Only on the first supposition, I think, do we get a universe which began in time and must end in time. Between such stupendous alternatives we have no grounds for choosing. But it would seem that the third, whether strictly158 true or not, best represents the state of the case relatively to our feeble capacity of comprehension. Whether absolutely infinite or not, the dimensions of the universe must be taken as practically infinite, so far as human thought is concerned. They immeasurably transcend the capabilities159 of any gauge160 we can bring to bear on them. Accordingly all that we are really entitled to hold, as the outcome of sound speculation, is the conception of innumerable systems of worlds concentrating out of nebulous masses, and then rushing together and dissolving into similar masses, as bubbles unite and break up — now here, now there — in their play on the surface of a pool, and to this tremendous series of events we can assign neither a beginning nor an end.
3 Fortnightly Review, April, 1875.
We must now make some more explicit161 mention of the ether which carries through space the rays of heat and light. In closest connection with the visible stellar universe, the vicissitudes162 of which we have briefly traced, the all-pervading163 ether constitutes a sort of unseen world remarkable164 enough from any point of view, but to which the theory of our authors ascribes capacities hitherto unsuspected by science. The very existence of an ocean of ether enveloping165 the molecules167 of material bodies has been doubted or denied by many eminent physicists, though of course none have called in question the necessity for some interstellar medium for the transmission of thermal168 and luminous169 vibrations170. This scepticism has been, I think, partially172 justified173 by the many difficulties encompassing174 the conception, into which, however, we need not here enter. That light and heat cannot be conveyed by any of the ordinary sensible forms of matter is unquestionable. None of the forms of sensible matter can be imagined sufficiently175 elastic176 to propagate wave-motion at the rate of one hundred and eighty-eight thousand miles per second. Yet a ray of light is a series of waves, and implies some substance in which the waves occur. The substance required is one which seems to possess strangely contradictory177 properties. It is commonly regarded as an “ether” or infinitely rare substance; but, as Professor Jevons observes, we might as well regard it as an infinitely solid “adamant.” “Sir John Herschel has calculated the amount of force which may be supposed, according to the undulatory theory of light, to be exerted at each point in space, and finds it to be 1,148,000,000,000 times the elastic force of ordinary air at the earth’s surface, so that the pressure of the ether upon a square inch of surface must be about 17,000,000,000,000, or seventeen billions of pounds.”4 Yet at the same time the resistance offered by the ether to the planetary motions is too minute to be appreciable178. “All our ordinary notions,” says Professor Jevons, “must be laid aside in contemplating179 such an hypothesis; yet [it is] no more than the observed phenomena of light and heat force us to accept. We cannot deny even the strange suggestion of Dr. Young, that there may be independent worlds, some possibly existing in different parts of space, but others perhaps pervading each other, unseen and unknown, in the same space. For if we are bound to admit the conception of this adamantine firmament180, it is equally easy to admit a plurality of such.”
4 Jevons’s Principles of Science, Vol. II. p. 145. The figures, which in the English system of numeration read as seventeen billions, would in the American system read as seventeen trillions.
The ether, therefore, is unlike any of the forms of matter which we can weigh and measure. In some respects it resembles a fluid, in some respects a solid. It is both hard and elastic to an almost inconceivable degree. It fills all material bodies like a sea in which the atoms of the material bodies are as islands, and it occupies the whole of what we call empty space. It is so sensitive that a disturbance181 in any part of it causes a “tremour which is felt on the surface of countless worlds.” Our old experiences of matter give us no account of any substance like this; yet the undulatory theory of light obliges us to admit such a substance, and that theory is as well established as the theory of gravitation. Obviously we have here an enlargement of our experience of matter. The analysis of the phenomena of light and radiant heat has brought us into mental relations with matter in a different state from any in which we previously182 knew it. For the supposition that the ether may be something essentially different from matter is contradicted by all the terms we have used in describing it. Strange and contradictory as its properties may seem, are they any more strange than the properties of a gas would seem if we were for the first time to discover a gas after heretofore knowing nothing but solids and liquids? I think not; and the conclusion implied by our authors seems to me eminently183 probable, that in the so-called ether we have simply a state of matter more primitive than what we know as the gaseous184 state. Indeed, the conceptions of matter now current, and inherited from barbarous ages, are likely enough to be crude in the extreme. It is not strange that the study of such subtle agencies as heat and light should oblige us to modify them; and it will not be strange if the study of electricity should entail185 still further revision of our ideas.
We are now brought to one of the profoundest speculations of modern times, the vortex-atom theory of Helmholtz and Thomson, in which the evolution of ordinary matter from ether is plainly indicated. The reader first needs to know what vortex-motion is; and this has been so beautifully explained by Professor Clifford, that I quote his description entire: “Imagine a ring of india-rubber, made by joining together the ends of a cylindrical186 piece (like a lead-pencil before it is cut), to be put upon a round stick which it will just fit with a little stretching. Let the stick be now pulled through the ring while the latter is kept in its place by being pulled the other way on the outside. The india-rubber has then what is called vortex-motion. Before the ends were joined together, while it was straight, it might have been made to turn around without changing position, by rolling it between the hands. Just the same motion of rotation it has on the stick, only that the ends are now joined together. All the inside surface of the ring is going one way, namely, the way the stick is pulled; and all the outside is going the other way. Such a vortex-ring is made by the smoker187 who purses his lips into a round hole and sends out a puff188 of smoke. The outside of the ring is kept back by the friction of his lips while the inside is going forwards; thus a rotation is set up all round the smoke-ring as it travels out into the air.” In these cases, and in others as we commonly find it, vortex-motion owes its origin to friction and is after a while brought to an end by friction. But in 1858 the equations of motion of an incompressible frictionless189 fluid were first successfully solved by Helmholtz, and among other things he proved that, though vortex-motion could not be originated in such a fluid, yet supposing it once to exist, it would exist to all eternity and could not be diminished by any mechanical action whatever. A vortex-ring, for example, in such a fluid, would forever preserve its own rotation, and would thus forever retain its peculiar190 individuality, being, as it were, marked off from its neighbour vortex-rings. Upon this mechanical truth Sir William Thomson based his wonderfully suggestive theory of the constitution of matter. That which is permanent or indestructible in matter is the ultimate homogeneous atom; and this is probably all that is permanent, since chemists now almost unanimously hold that so-called elementary molecules are not really simple, but owe their sensible differences to the various groupings of an ultimate atom which is alike for all. Relatively to our powers of comprehension the atom endures eternally; that is, it retains forever unalterable its definite mass and its definite rate of vibration171. Now this is just what a vortex-ring would do in an incompressible frictionless fluid. Thus the startling question is suggested, Why may not the ultimate atoms of matter be vortex-rings forever existing in such a frictionless fluid filling the whole of space? Such a hypothesis is not less brilliant than Huyghens’s conjectural191 identification of light with undulatory motion; and it is moreover a legitimate192 hypothesis, since it can be brought to the test of verification. Sir William Thomson has shown that it explains a great many of the physical properties of matter: it remains to be seen whether it can explain them all.
Of course the ether which conveys thermal and luminous undulations is not the frictionless fluid postulated193 by Sir William Thomson. The most conspicuous194 property of the ether is its enormous elasticity195, a property which we should not find in a frictionless fluid. “To account for such elasticity,” says Professor Clifford (whose exposition of the subject is still more lucid196 than that of our authors), “it has to be supposed that even where there are no material molecules the universal fluid is full of vortex-motion, but that the vortices are smaller and more closely packed than those of [ordinary] matter, forming altogether a more finely grained structure. So that the difference between matter and ether is reduced to a mere difference in the size and arrangement of the component197 vortex-rings. Now, whatever may turn out to be the ultimate nature of the ether and of molecules, we know that to some extent at least they obey the same dynamic laws, and that they act upon one another in accordance with these laws. Until, therefore, it is absolutely disproved, it must remain the simplest and most probable assumption that they are finally made of the same stuff, that the material molecule166 is some kind of knot or coagulation198 of ether.”5
5 Fortnightly Review, June, 1875, p. 784.
Another interesting consequence of Sir William Thomson’s pregnant hypothesis is that the absolute hardness which has been attributed to material atoms from the time of Lucretius downward may be dispensed199 with. Somewhat in the same way that a loosely suspended chain becomes rigid200 with rapid rotation, the hardness and elasticity of the vortex-atom are explained as due to the swift rotary201 motion of a soft and yielding fluid. So that the vortex-atom is really indivisible, not by reason of its hardness or solidity, but by reason of the indestructibleness of its motion.
Supposing, now, that we adopt provisionally the vortex theory — the great power of which is well shown by the consideration just mentioned — we must not forget that it is absolutely essential to the indestructibleness of the material atom that the universal fluid in which it has an existence as a vortex-ring should be entirely202 destitute203 of friction. Once admit even the most infinitesimal amount of friction, while retaining the conception of vortex-motion in a universal fluid, and the whole case is so far altered that the material atom can no longer be regarded as absolutely indestructible, but only as indefinitely enduring. It may have been generated, in bygone eternity, by a natural process of evolution, and in future eternity may come to an end. Relatively to our powers of comprehension the practical difference is perhaps not great. Scientifically speaking, Helmholtz and Thomson are as well entitled to reason upon the assumption of a perfectly204 frictionless fluid as geometers in general are entitled to assume perfect lines without breadth and perfect surfaces without thickness. Perfect lines and surfaces do not exist within the region of our experience; yet the conclusions of geometry are none the less true ideally, though in any particular concrete instance they are only approximately realized. Just so with the conception of a frictionless fluid. So far as experience goes, such a thing has no more real existence than a line without breadth; and hence an atomic theory based upon such an assumption may be as true ideally as any of the theorems of Euclid, but it can give only an approximatively true account of the actual universe. These considerations do not at all affect the scientific value of the theory; but they will modify the tenour of such transcendental inferences as may be drawn from it regarding, the probable origin and destiny of the universe.
The conclusions reached in the first part of this paper, while we were dealing only with gross visible matter, may have seemed bold enough; but they are far surpassed by the inference which our authors draw from the vortex theory as they interpret it. Our authors exhibit various reasons, more or less sound, for attributing to the primordial205 fluid some slight amount of friction; and in support of this view they adduce Le Sage’s explanation of gravitation as a differential result of pressure, and Struve’s theory of the partial absorption of light-rays by the ether — questions with which our present purpose does not require us to meddle206. Apart from such questions it is every way probable that the primary assumption of Helmholtz and Thomson is only an approximation to the truth. But if we accredit207 the primordial fluid with even an infinitesimal amount of friction, then we are required to conceive of the visible universe as developed from the invisible and as destined208 to return into the invisible. The vortex-atom, produced by infinitesimal friction operating through wellnigh infinite time, is to be ultimately abolished by the agency which produced it. In the words of our authors, “If the visible universe be developed from an invisible which is not a perfect fluid, then the argument deduced by Sir William Thomson in favour of the eternity of ordinary matter disappears, since this eternity depends upon the perfect fluidity of the invisible. In fine, if we suppose the material universe to be composed of a series of vortex-rings developed from an invisible universe which is not a perfect fluid, it will be ephemeral, just as the smoke-ring which we develop from air, or that which we develop from water, is ephemeral, the only difference being in duration, these lasting209 only for a few seconds, and the others it may be for billions of years.” Thus, as our authors suppose that “the available energy of the visible universe will ultimately be appropriated by the invisible,” they go on to imagine, “at least as a possibility, that the separate existence of the visible universe will share the same fate, so that we shall have no huge, useless, inert210 mass existing in after ages to remind the passer-by of a form of energy and a species of matter that is long since out of date and functionally211 effete212. Why should not the universe bury its dead out of sight?”
In one respect perhaps no more stupendous subject of contemplation than this has ever been offered to the mind of man. In comparison with the length of time thus required to efface213 the tiny individual atom, the entire cosmical career of our solar system, or even that of the whole starry214 galaxy215, shrinks into utter nothingness. Whether we shall adopt the conclusion suggested must depend on the extent of our speculative audacity216. We have seen wherein its probability consists, but in reasoning upon such a scale we may fitly be cautious and modest in accepting inferences, and our authors, we may be sure, would be the first to recommend such modesty217 and caution. Even at the dimensions to which our theorizing has here grown, we may for instance discern the possible alternative of a simultaneous or rhythmically218 successive generation and destruction of vortex-atoms which would go far to modify the conclusion just suggested. But here we must pause for a moment, reserving for a second paper the weightier thoughts as to futurity which our authors have sought to enwrap in these sublime219 physical speculations.
PART SECOND.
UP to this point, however remote from ordinary every-day thoughts may be the region of speculation which we have been called upon to traverse, we have still kept within the limits of legitimate scientific hypothesis. Though we have ventured for a goodly distance into the unknown, we have not yet been required to abandon our base of operations in the known. Of the views presented in the preceding paper, some are wellnigh certainly established, some are probable, some have a sort of plausibility220, others — to which we have refrained from giving assent221 — may possibly be true; but none are irretrievably beyond the jurisdiction222 of scientific tests. No suggestion has so far been broached223 which a very little further increase of our scientific knowledge may not show to be either eminently probable or eminently improbable. We have kept pretty clear of mere subjective224 guesses, such as men may wrangle225 about forever without coming to any conclusion. The theory of the nebular origin of our planetary system has come to command the assent of all persons qualified226 to appreciate the evidence on which it is based; and the more immediate94 conclusions which we have drawn from that theory are only such as are commonly drawn by astronomers and physicists. The doctrine of an intermolecular and interstellar ether is wrapped up in the well-established undulatory theory of light. Such is by no means the case with Sir William Thomson’s vortex-atom theory, which to-day is in somewhat the same condition as the undulatory theory of Huyghens two centuries ago. This, however, is none the less a hypothesis truly scientific in conception, and in the speculations to which it leads us we are still sure of dealing with views that admit at least of definite expression and treatment. In other words, though our study of the visible universe has led us to the recognition of a kind of unseen world underlying228 the world of things that are seen, yet concerning the economy of this unseen world we have not been led to entertain any hypothesis that has not its possible justification229 in our experiences of visible phenomena.
We are now called upon, following in the wake of our esteemed230 authors, to venture on a different sort of exploration, in which we must cut loose altogether from our moorings in the world of which we have definite experience. We are invited to entertain suggestions concerning the peculiar economy of the invisible portion of the universe which we have no means of subjecting to any sort of test of probability, either experimental or deductive. These suggestions are, therefore, not to be regarded as properly scientific; but, with this word of caution, we may proceed to show what they are.
Compared with the life and death of cosmical systems which we have heretofore contemplated231, the life and death of individuals of the human race may perhaps seem a small matter; yet because we are ourselves the men who live and die, the small event is of vastly greater interest to us than the grand series of events of which it is part and parcel. It is natural that we should be more interested in the ultimate fate of humanity than in the fate of a world which is of no account to us save as our present dwelling-place. Whether the human soul is to come to an end or not is to us a more important question than whether the visible universe, with its matter and energy, is to be absorbed in an invisible ether. It is indeed only because we are interested in the former question that we are so curious about the latter. If we could dissociate ourselves from the material universe, our habitat, we should probably speculate much less about its past and future. We care very little what becomes of the black ball of the earth, after all life has vanished from its surface; or, if we care at all about it, it is only because our thoughts about the career of the earth are necessarily mixed up with our thoughts about life. Hence in considering the probable ultimate destiny of the physical universe, our innermost purpose must be to know what is to become of all this rich and wonderful life of which the physical universe is the theatre. Has it all been developed, apparently at almost infinite waste of effort, only to be abolished again before it has attained232 to completeness, or does it contain or shelter some indestructible element which having drawn sustenance233 for a while from the senseless turmoil234 of physical phenomena shall still survive their final decay? This question is closely connected with the time-honoured question of the meaning, purpose, or tendency of the world. In the career of the world is life an end, or a means toward an end, or only an incidental phenomenon in which we can discover no meaning? Contemporary theologians seem generally to believe that one necessary result of modern scientific inquiry must be the destruction of the belief in immortal151 life, since against every thoroughgoing expounder235 of scientific knowledge they seek to hurl236 the charge of “materialism237.” Their doubts, however, are not shared by our authors, thorough men of science as they are, though their mode of dealing with the question may not be such as we can well adopt. While upholding the doctrine of evolution, and all the so-called “materialistic238” views of modern science, they not only regard the hypothesis of a future life as admissible, but they even go so far as to propound239 a physical theory as to the nature of existence after death. Let us see what this physical theory is.
As far as the visible universe is concerned, we do not find in it any evidence of immortality or of permanence of any sort, unless it be in the sum of potential and kinetic energies on the persistency240 of which depends our principle of continuity. In ordinary language “the stars in their courses” serve as symbols of permanence, yet we have found reason to regard them as but temporary phenomena. So, in the language of our authors, “if we take the individual man, we find that he lives his short tale of years, and that then the visible machinery241 which connects him with the past, as well as that which enables him to act in the present, falls into ruin and is brought to an end. If any germ or potentiality remains, it is certainly not connected with the visible order of things.” In like manner our race is pretty sure to come to an end long before the destruction of the planet from which it now gets its sustenance. And in our authors opinion even the universe will by and by become “old and effete, no less truly than the individual: it is a glorious garment this visible universe, but not an immortal one; we must look elsewhere if we are to be clothed with immortality as with a garment.”
It is at this point that our authors call attention to “the apparently wasteful character of the arrangements of the visible universe.” The fact is one which we have already sufficiently described, but we shall do well to quote the words in which our authors recur242 to it: “All but a very small portion of the sun’s heat goes day by day into what we call empty space, and it is only this very small remainder that is made use of by the various planets for purposes of their own. Can anything be more perplexing than this seemingly frightful243 expenditure244 of the very life and essence of the system? That this vast store of high-class energy should be doing nothing but travelling outwards245 in space at the rate of 188,000 miles per second is hardly conceivable, especially when the result of it is the inevitable destruction of the visible universe.”
Pursuing this teleological246 argument, it is suggested that perhaps this apparent waste of energy is “only an arrangement in virtue247 of which our universe keeps up a memory of the past at the expense of the present, inasmuch as all memory consists in an investiture of present resources in order to keep a hold upon the past.” Recourse is had to the ingenious argument in which Mr. Babbage showed that “if we had power to follow and detect the minutest effects of any disturbance, each particle of existing matter must be a register of all that has happened. The track of every canoe, of every vessel248 that has yet disturbed the surface of the ocean, whether impelled249 by manual force or elemental power, remains forever registered in the future movement of all succeeding particles which may occupy its place. The furrow250 which is left is, indeed, instantly filled up by the closing waters; but they draw after them other and larger portions of the surrounding element, and these again, once moved, communicate motion to others in endless succession.” In like manner, “the air itself is one vast library, on whose pages are forever written all that man has ever said or even whispered. There in their mutable but unerring characters, mixed with the earliest as well as the latest sighs of mortality, stand forever recorded vows251 unredeemed, promises unfulfilled, perpetuating252 in the united movements of each particle the testimony253 of man’s changeful will.”6 In some such way as this, records of every movement that takes place in the world are each moment transmitted, with the speed of light, through the invisible ocean of ether with which the world is surrounded. Even the molecular227 displacements254 which occur in our brains when we feel and think are thus propagated in their effects into the unseen world. The world of ether is thus regarded by our authors as in some sort the obverse or complement255 of the world of sensible matter, so that whatever energy is dissipated in the one is by the same act accumulated in the other. It is like the negative plate in photography, where light answers to shadow and shadow to light. Or, still better, it is like the case of an equation in which whatever quantity you take from one side is added to the other with a contrary sign, while the relation of equality remains undisturbed. Thus, it will be noticed, from the ingenious and subtle, but quite defensible suggestion of Mr. Babbage, a leap is made to an assumption which cannot be defended scientifically, but only teleologically256. It is one thing to say that every movement in the visible world transmits a record of itself to the surrounding ether, in such a way that from the undulation of the ether a sufficiently powerful intelligence might infer the character of the generating movement in the visible world. It is quite another thing to say that the ether is organized in such a complex and delicate way as to be like a negative image or counterpart of the world of sensible matter. The latter view is no doubt ingenious, but it is gratuitous257. It is sustained not by scientific analogy, but by the desire to find some assignable use for the energy which is constantly escaping from visible matter into invisible ether. The moment we ask how do we know that this energy is not really wasted, or that it is not put to some use wholly undiscoverable by human intelligence, this assumption of an organized ether is at once seen to be groundless. It belongs not to the region of science, but to that of pure mythology.
6 Babbage, Ninth Bridgewater Treatise258, p. 115; Jevons, Principles of Science, Vol. II. p. 455.
In justice to our authors, however, it should be remembered that this assumption is put forth not as something scientifically probable, but as something which for aught we know to the contrary may possibly be true. This, to be sure, we need not deny; nor if we once allow this prodigious259 leap of inference, shall we find much difficulty in reaching the famous conclusion that “thought conceived to affect the matter of another universe simultaneously260 with this may explain a future state.” This proposition, quaintly261 couched in an anagram, like the discoveries of old astronomers, was published last year in “Nature,” as containing the gist32 of the forthcoming book. On the negative-image hypothesis it is not hard to see how thought is conceived to affect the seen and the unseen worlds simultaneously. Every act of consciousness is accompanied by molecular displacements in the brain, and these are of course responded to by movements in the ethereal world. Thus as a series of conscious states build up a continuous memory in strict accordance with physical laws of motion,7 so a correlative memory is simultaneously built up in the ethereal world out of the ethereal correlatives of the molecular displacements which go on in our brains. And as there is a continual transfer of energy from the visible world to the ether, the extinction262 of vital energy which we call death must coincide in some way with the awakening263 of vital energy in the correlative world; so that the darkening of consciousness here is coincident with its dawning there. In this way death is for the individual but a transfer from one physical state of existence to another; and so, on the largest scale, the death or final loss of energy by the whole visible universe has its counterpart in the acquirement of a maximum of life by the correlative unseen world.
There seems to be a certain sort of rigorous logical consistency264 in this daring speculation; but really the propositions of which it consists are so far from answering to anything within the domain265 of human experience that we are unable to tell whether any one of them logically follows from its predecessor266 or not. It is evident that we are quite out of the region of scientific tests, and to whatever view our authors may urge we can only languidly assent that it is out of our power to disprove it.
7 See my Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy, Vol. II. pp. 142-148.
The essential weakness of such a theory as this lies in the fact that it is thoroughly materialistic in character. It is currently assumed that the doctrine of a life after death cannot be defended on materialistic grounds, but this is altogether too hasty an assumption. Our authors, indeed, are not philosophical267 materialists, like Dr. Priestley — who nevertheless believed in a future life — but one of the primary doctrines268 of materialism lies at the bottom of their argument. Materialism holds for one thing that consciousness is a product of a peculiar organization of matter, and for another thing that consciousness cannot survive the disorganization of the material body with which it is associated. As held by philosophical materialists, like Buchner and Moleschott, these two opinions are strictly consistent with each other; nay269, the latter seems to be the inevitable inference from the former, though Priestley did not so regard it. Now our authors very properly refuse to commit themselves to the opinion that mind is the product of matter, but their argument nevertheless implies that some sort of material vehicle is necessary for the continuance of mind in a future state of existence. This material vehicle they seek to supply in the theory which connects by invisible bonds of transmitted energy the perishable270 material body with its counterpart in the world of ether. The materialism of the argument is indeed partly veiled by the terminology in which this counterpart is called a “spiritual body,” but in this novel use or abuse of scriptural language there seems to me to be a strange confusion of ideas. Bear in mind that the “invisible universe” into which energy is constantly passing is simply the luminiferous ether, which our authors, to suit the requirements of their hypothesis, have gratuitously271 endowed with a complexity272 and variety of structure analogous273 to that of the visible world of matter. Their language is not always quite so precise as one could desire, for while they sometimes speak of the ether itself as the “unseen universe,” they sometimes allude274 to a primordial medium yet subtler in constitution and presumably more immaterial. Herein lies the confusion. Why should the luminiferous ether, or any primordial medium in which it may have been generated, be regarded as in any way “spiritual”? Great physicists, like less trained thinkers, are sometimes liable to be unconsciously influenced by old associations of ideas which, ostensibly repudiated275, still lurk276 under cover of the words we use. I fear that the old associations which led the ancients to describe the soul as a breath or a shadow, and which account for the etymologies277 of such words as “ghost” and “spirit,” have had something to do with this spiritualization of the interstellar ether. Some share may also have been contributed by the Platonic278 notion of the “grossness” or “bruteness” of tangible280 matter — a notion which has survived in Christian281 theology, and which educated men of the present day have by no means universally outgrown282. Save for some such old associations as these, why should it be supposed that matter becomes “spriritualized” as it diminishes in apparent substantiality? Why should matter be pronounced respectable in the inverse283 ratio of its density284 or ponderability? Why is a diamond any more chargeable with “grossness” than a cubic centimetre of hydrogen? Obviously such fancies are purely285 of mythologic286 parentage. Now the luminiferous ether, upon which our authors make such extensive demands, may be physically287 “ethereal” enough, in spite of the enormous elasticity which leads Professor Jevons to characterize it as “adamantine”; but most assuredly we have not the slightest reason for speaking of it as “immaterial” or “spiritual.” Though we are unable to weigh it in the balance, we at least know it as a transmitter of undulatory movements, the size and shape of which we can accurately measure. Its force-relations with ponderable matter are not only universally and incessantly maintained, but they have that precisely288 quantitative289 character which implies an essential identity between the innermost natures of the two substances. We have seen reason for thinking it probable that ether and ordinary matter are alike composed of vortex-rings in a quasi-frictionless fluid; but whatever be the fate of this subtle hypothesis, we may be sure that no theory will ever be entertained in which the analysis of ether shall require different symbols from that of ordinary matter. In our authors’ theory, therefore, the putting on of immortality is in no wise the passage from a material to a spiritual state. It is the passage from one kind of materially conditioned state to another. The theory thus appeals directly to our experiences of the behaviour of matter; and in deriving290 so little support as it does from these experiences, it remains an essentially weak speculation, whatever we may think of its ingenuity. For so long as we are asked to accept conclusions drawn from our experiences of the material world, we are justified in demanding something more than mere unconditioned possibility. We require some positive evidence, be it ever so little in amount; and no theory which cannot furnish such positive evidence is likely to carry to our minds much practical conviction.
This is what I meant by saying that the great weakness of the hypothesis here criticized lies in its materialistic character. In contrast with this we shall presently see that the assertion of a future life which is not materially conditioned, though unsupported by any item of experience whatever, may nevertheless be an impregnable assertion. But first I would conclude the foregoing criticism by ruling out altogether the sense in which our authors use the expression “Unseen Universe.” Scientific inference, however remote, is connected by such insensible gradations with ordinary perception, that one may well question the propriety291 of applying the term “unseen” to that which is presented to “the mind’s eye” as inevitable matter of inference. It is true that we cannot see the ocean of ether in which visible matter floats; but there are many other invisible things which yet we do not regard as part of the “unseen world.” I do not see the air which I am now breathing within the four walls of my study, yet its existence is sufficiently a matter of sense-perception as it fills my lungs and fans my cheek. The atoms which compose a drop of water are not only invisible, but cannot in any way be made the objects of sense-perception; yet by proper inferences from their behaviour we can single them out for measurement, so that Sir William Thomson can tell us that if the drop of water were magnified to the size of the earth, the constituent292 atoms would be larger than peas, but not so large as billiard-balls. If we do not see such atoms with our eyes, we have one adequate reason in their tiny dimensions, though there are further reasons than this. It would be hard to say why the luminiferous ether should be relegated293 to the “unseen world” any more than the material atom. Whatever we know as possessing resistance and extension, whatever we can subject to mathematical processes of measurement, we also conceive as existing in such shape that, with appropriate eyes and under proper visual conditions, we MIGHT see it, and we are not entitled to draw any line of demarcation between such an object of inference and others which may be made objects of sense-perception. To set apart the ether as constituting an “unseen universe” is therefore illegitimate and confusing. It introduces a distinction where there is none, and obscures the fact that both invisible ether and visible matter form but one grand universe in which the sum of energy remains constant, though the order of its distribution endlessly varies.
Very different would be the logical position of a theory which should assume the existence of an “Unseen World” entirely spiritual in constitution, and in which material conditions like those of the visible world should have neither place nor meaning. Such a world would not consist of ethers or gases or ghosts, but of purely psychical294 relations akin82 to such as constitute thoughts and feelings when our minds are least solicited295 by sense-perceptions. In thus marking off the “Unseen World” from the objective universe of which we have knowledge, our line of demarcation would at least be drawn in the right place. The distinction between psychical and material phenomena is a distinction of a different order from all other distinctions known to philosophy, and it immeasurably transcends296 all others. The progress of modern discovery has in no respect weakened the force of Descartes’s remark, that between that of which the differential attribute is Thought and that of which the differential attribute is Extension, there can be no similarity, no community of nature whatever. By no scientific cunning of experiment or deduction297 can Thought be weighed or measured or in any way assimilated to such things as may be made the actual or possible objects of sense-perception. Modern discovery, so far from bridging over the chasm298 between Mind and Matter, tends rather to exhibit the distinction between them as absolute. It has, indeed, been rendered highly probable that every act of consciousness is accompanied by a molecular motion in the cells and fibres of the brain; and materialists have found great comfort in this fact, while theologians and persons of little faith have been very much frightened by it. But since no one ever pretended that thought can go on, under the conditions of the present life, without a brain, one finds it rather hard to sympathize either with the self-congratulations of Dr. Buchner’s disciples8 or with the terrors of their opponents. But what has been less commonly remarked is the fact that when the thought and the molecular movement thus occur simultaneously, in no scientific sense is the thought the product of the molecular movement. The sun-derived energy of motion latent in the food we eat is variously transformed within the organism, until some of it appears as the motion of the molecules of a little globule of nerve-matter in the brain. In a rough way we might thus say that the chemical energy of the food indirectly299 produces the motion of these little nerve-molecules. But does this motion of nerve-molecules now produce a thought or state of consciousness? By no means. It simply produces some other motion of nerve-molecules, and this in turn produces motion of contraction or expansion in some muscle, or becomes transformed into the chemical energy of some secreting300 gland301. At no point in the whole circuit does a unit of motion disappear as motion to reappear as a unit of consciousness. The physical process is complete in itself, and the thought does not enter into it. All that we can say is, that the occurrence of the thought is simultaneous with that part of the physical process which consists of a molecular movement in the brain.9 To be sure, the thought is always there when summoned, but it stands outside the dynamic circuit, as something utterly302 alien from and incomparable with the events which summon it. No doubt, as Professor Tyndall observes, if we knew exhaustively the physical state of the brain, “the corresponding thought or feeling might be inferred; or, given the thought or feeling, the corresponding state of the brain might be inferred. But how inferred? It would be at bottom not a case of logical inference at all, but of empirical association. You may reply that many of the inferences of science are of this character; the inference, for example, that an electric current of a given direction will deflect303 a magnetic needle in a definite way; but the cases differ in this, that the passage from the current to the needle, if not demonstrable, is thinkable, and that we entertain no doubt as to the final mechanical solution of the problem. But the passage from the physics of the brain to the corresponding facts of consciousness is unthinkable. Granted that a definite thought and a definite molecular action in the brain occur simultaneously; we do not possess the intellectual organ, nor apparently any rudiment304 of the organ, which would enable us to pass by a process of reasoning from the one to the other. They appear together, but we do not know why.”10
8 The Nation once wittily305 described these people as “people who believe that they are going to die like the beasts, and who congratulate themselves that they are going to die like the beasts.”
9 For a fuller exposition of this point, see my Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy, Vol. II. pp. 436-445.
10 Fragments of Science, p. 119.
An unseen world consisting of purely psychical or spiritual phenomena would accordingly be demarcated by an absolute gulf306 from what we call the material universe, but would not necessarily be discontinuous with the psychical phenomena which we find manifested in connection with the world of matter. The transfer of matter, or physical energy, or anything else that is quantitatively307 measurable, into such an unseen world, may be set down as impossible, by reason of the very definition of such a world. Any hypothesis which should assume such a transfer would involve a contradiction in terms. But the hypothesis of a survival of present psychical phenomena in such a world, after being denuded308 of material conditions, is not in itself absurd or self-contradictory, though it may be impossible to support it by any arguments drawn from the domain of human experience. Such is the shape which it seems to me that, in the present state of philosophy, the hypothesis of a future life must assume. We have nothing to say to gross materialistic notions of ghosts and bogies, and spirits that upset tables and whisper to ignorant vulgar women the wonderful information that you once had an aunt Susan. The unseen world imagined in our hypothesis is not connected with the present material universe by any such “invisible bonds” as would allow Bacon and Addison to come to Boston and write the silliest twaddle in the most ungrammatical English before a roomful of people who have never learned how to test what they are pleased to call the “evidence of their senses.” Our hypothesis is expressly framed so as to exclude all intercourse309 whatever between the unseen world of spirit unconditioned by matter and the present world of spirit conditioned by matter in which all our experiences have been gathered. The hypothesis being framed in such a way, the question is, What has philosophy to say to it? Can we, by searching our experiences, find any reason for adopting such an hypothesis? Or, on the other hand, supposing we can find no such reason, would the total failure of experimental evidence justify310 us in rejecting it?
The question is so important that I will restate it. I have imagined a world made up of psychical phenomena, freed from the material conditions under which alone we know such phenomena. Can we adduce any proof of the possibility of such a world? Or if we cannot, does our failure raise the slightest presumption311 that such a world is impossible?
The reply to the first clause of the question is sufficiently obvious. We have no experience whatever of psychical phenomena save as manifested in connection with material phenomena. We know of Mind only as a group of activities which are never exhibited to us except through the medium of motions of matter. In all our experience we have never encountered such activities save in connection with certain very complicated groupings of highly mobile material particles into aggregates312 which we call living organisms. And we have never found them manifested to a very conspicuous extent save in connection with some of those specially47 organized aggregates which have vertebrate skeletons and mammary glands313. Nay, more, when we survey the net results of our experience up to the present time, we find indisputable evidence that in the past history of the visible universe psychical phenomena have only begun to be manifested in connection with certain complex aggregates of material phenomena. As these material aggregates have age by age become more complex in structure, more complex psychical phenomena have been exhibited. The development of Mind has from the outset been associated with the development of Matter. And to-day, though none of us has any knowledge of the end of psychical phenomena in his own case, yet from all the marks by which we recognize such phenomena in our fellow-creatures, whether brute279 or human, we are taught that when certain material processes have been gradually or suddenly brought to an end, psychical phenomena are no longer manifested. From first to last, therefore, our appeal to experience gets but one response. We have not the faintest shadow of evidence wherewith to make it seem probable that Mind can exist except in connection with a material body. Viewed from this standpoint of terrestrial experience, there is no more reason for supposing that consciousness survives the dissolution of the brain than for supposing that the pungent314 flavour of table-salt survives its decomposition315 into metallic316 sodium317 and gaseous chlorine.
Our answer from this side is thus unequivocal enough. Indeed, so uniform has been the teaching of experience in this respect that even in their attempts to depict155 a life after death, men have always found themselves obliged to have recourse to materialistic symbols. To the mind of a savage the future world is a mere reproduction of the present, with its everlasting318 huntings and fightings. The early Christians319 looked forward to a renovation320 of the earth and the bodily resurrection from Sheol of the righteous. The pictures of hell and purgatory321, and even of paradise, in Dante’s great poem, are so intensely materialistic as to seem grotesque in this more spiritual age. But even to-day the popular conceptions of heaven are by no means freed from the notion of matter; and persons of high culture, who realize the inadequacy322 of these popular conceptions, are wont323 to avoid the difficulty by refraining from putting their hopes and beliefs into any definite or describable form. Not unfrequently one sees a smile raised at the assumption of knowledge or insight by preachers who describe in eloquent324 terms the joys of a future state; yet the smile does not necessarily imply any scepticism as to the abstract probability of the soul’s survival. The scepticism is aimed at the character of the description rather than at the reality of the thing described. It implies a tacit agreement, among cultivated people, that the unseen world must be purely spiritual in constitution. The agreement is not habitually325 expressed in definite formulas, for the reason that no mental image of a purely spiritual world can be formed. Much stress is commonly laid upon the recognition of friends in a future life; and however deep a meaning may be given to the phrase “the love of God,” one does not easily realize that a heavenly existence could be worth the longing30 that is felt for it, if it were to afford no further scope for the pure and tender household affections which give to the present life its powerful though indefinable charm. Yet the recognition of friends in a purely spiritual world is something of which we can frame no conception whatever. We may look with unspeakable reverence326 on the features of wife or child, less because of their physical beauty than because of the beauty of soul to which they give expression, but to imagine the perception of soul by soul apart from the material structure and activities in which soul is manifested, is something utterly beyond our power. Nay, even when we try to represent to ourselves the psychical activity of any single soul by itself as continuing without the aid of the physical machinery of sensation, we get into unmanageable difficulties. A great part of the contents of our minds consists of sensuous327 (chiefly visual) images, and though we may imagine reflection to go on without further images supplied by vision or hearing, touch or taste or smell, yet we cannot well see how fresh experiences could be gained in such a state. The reader, if he require further illustrations, can easily follow out this line of thought. Enough has no doubt been said to convince him that our hypothesis of the survival of conscious activity apart from material conditions is not only utterly unsupported by any evidence that can be gathered from the world of which we have experience, but is utterly and hopelessly inconceivable.
It is inconceivable BECAUSE it is entirely without foundation in experience. Our powers of conception are closely determined328 by the limits of our experience. When a proposition, or combination of ideas, is suggested, for which there has never been any precedent329 in human experience, we find it to be UNTHINKABLE — the ideas will not combine. The proposition remains one which we may utter and defend, and perhaps vituperate our neighbours for not accepting, but it remains none the less an unthinkable proposition. It takes terms which severally have meanings and puts them together into a phrase which has no meaning.11 Now when we try to combine the idea of the continuance of conscious activity with the idea of the entire cessation of material conditions, and thereby330 to assert the existence of a purely spiritual world, we find that we have made an unthinkable proposition. We may defend our hypothesis as passionately331 as we like, but when we strive coolly to realize it in thought we find ourselves baulked at every step.
11 See my Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy, Vol. I. pp. 64-67.
But now we have to ask, How much does this inconceivability signify? In most cases, when we say that a statement is inconceivable, we practically declare it to be untrue; when we say that a statement is without warrant in experience, we plainly indicate that we consider it unworthy of our acceptance. This is legitimate in the majority of cases with which we have to deal in the course of life, because experience, and the capacities of thought called out and limited by experience, are our only guides in the conduct of life. But every one will admit that our experience is not infinite, and that our capacity of conception is not coextensive with the possibilities of existence. It is not only possible, but in the very highest degree probable, that there are many things in heaven, if not on earth, which are undreamed of in our philosophy. Since our ability to conceive anything is limited by the extent of our experience, and since human experience is very far from being infinite, it follows that there may be, and in all probability is, an immense region of existence in every way as real as the region which we know, yet concerning which we cannot form the faintest rudiment of a conception. Any hypothesis relating to such a region of existence is not only not disproved by the total failure of evidence in its favour, but the total failure of evidence does not raise even the slightest prima facie presumption against its validity.
These considerations apply with great force to the hypothesis of an unseen world in which psychical phenomena persist in the absence of material conditions. It is true, on the one hand, that we can bring up no scientific evidence in support of such an hypothesis. But on the other hand it is equally true that in the very nature of things no such evidence could be expected to be forthcoming: even were there such evidence in abundance, it could not be accessible to us. The existence of a single soul, or congeries of psychical phenomena, unaccompanied by a material body, would be evidence sufficient to demonstrate the hypothesis. But in the nature of things, even were there a million such souls round about us, we could not become aware of the existence of one of them, for we have no organ or faculty332 for the perception of soul apart from the material structure and activities in which it has been manifested throughout the whole course of our experience. Even our own self-consciousness involves the consciousness of ourselves as partly material bodies. These considerations show that our hypothesis is very different from the ordinary hypotheses with which science deals. The entire absence of testimony does not raise a negative presumption except in cases where testimony is accessible. In the hypotheses with which scientific men are occupied, testimony is always accessible; and if we do not find any, the presumption is raised that there is none. When Dr. Bastian tells us that he has found living organisms to be generated in sealed flasks333 from which all living germs had been excluded, we demand the evidence for his assertion. The testimony of facts is in this case hard to elicit, and only skilful334 reasoners can properly estimate its worth. But still it is all accessible. With more or less labour it can be got at; and if we find that Dr. Bastian has produced no evidence save such as may equally well receive a different interpretation335 from that which he has given it, we rightly feel that a strong presumption has been raised against his hypothesis. It is a case in which we are entitled to expect to find the favouring facts if there are any, and so long as we do not find such, we are justified in doubting their existence. So when our authors propound the hypothesis of an unseen universe consisting of phenomena which occur in the interstellar ether, or even in some primordial fluid with which the ether has physical relations, we are entitled to demand their proofs. It is not enough to tell us that we cannot disprove such a theory. The burden of proof lies with them. The interstellar ether is something concerning the physical properties of which we have some knowledge; and surely, if all the things are going on which they suppose in a medium so closely related to ordinary matter, there ought to be some traceable indications of the fact. At least, until the contrary can be shown, we must refuse to believe that all the testimony in a case like this is utterly inaccessible336; and accordingly, so long as none is found, especially so long as none is even alleged337, we feel that a presumption is raised against their theory.
These illustrations will show, by sheer contrast, how different it is with the hypothesis of an unseen world that is purely spiritual. The testimony in such a case must, under the conditions of the present life, be forever inaccessible. It lies wholly outside the range of experience. However abundant it may be, we cannot expect to meet with it. And accordingly our failure to produce it does not raise even the slightest presumption against our theory. When conceived in this way, the belief in a future life is without scientific support; but at the same time it is placed beyond the need of scientific support and beyond the range of scientific criticism. It is a belief which no imaginable future advance in physical discovery can in any way impugn338. It is a belief which is in no sense irrational339, and which may be logically entertained without in the least affecting our scientific habit of mind or influencing our scientific conclusions.
To take a brief illustration: we have alluded340 to the fact that in the history of our present world the development of mental phenomena has gone on hand in hand with the development of organic life, while at the same time we have found it impossible to explain mental phenomena as in any sense the product of material phenomena. Now there is another side to all this. The great lesson which Berkeley taught mankind was that what we call material phenomena are really the products of consciousness co-operating with some Unknown Power (not material) existing beyond consciousness. We do very well to speak of “matter” in common parlance341, but all that the word really means is a group of qualities which have no existence apart from our minds. Modern philosophers have quite generally accepted this conclusion, and every attempt to overturn Berkeley’s reasoning has hitherto resulted in complete and disastrous342 failure. In admitting this, we do not admit the conclusion of Absolute Idealism, that nothing exists outside of consciousness. What we admit as existing independently of our own consciousness is the Power that causes in us those conscious states which we call the perception of material qualities. We have no reason for regarding this Power as in itself material: indeed, we cannot do so, since by the theory material qualities have no existence apart from our minds. I have elsewhere sought to show that less difficulty is involved in regarding this Power outside of us as quasi-psychical, or in some measure similar to the mental part of ourselves; and I have gone on to conclude that this Power may be identical with what men have, in all times and by the aid of various imperfect symbols, endeavoured to apprehend343 as Deity344.12 We are thus led to a view of things not very unlike the views entertained by Spinoza and Berkeley. We are led to the inference that what we call the material universe is but the manifestation of infinite Deity to our finite minds. Obviously, on this view, Matter — the only thing to which materialists concede real existence — is simply an orderly phantasmagoria; and God and the Soul — which materialists regard as mere fictions of the imagination — are the only conceptions that answer to real existences.
12 See my Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy, Part I. Chap. IV.; Part III. Chaps. III., IV.
In the foregoing paragraph I have been setting down opinions with which I am prepared to agree, and which are not in conflict with anything that our study of the development of the objective world has taught us. In so far as that study may be supposed to bear on the question of a future life, two conclusions are open to us. First we may say that since the phenomena of mind appear and run their course along with certain specialized345 groups of material phenomena, so, too, they must disappear when these specialized groups are broken up. Or, in other words, we may say that every living person is an organized whole; consciousness is something which pertains346 to this organized whole, as music belongs to the harp347 that is entire; but when the harp is broken it is silent, and when the organized whole of personality falls to pieces consciousness ceases forever. To many well-disciplined minds this conclusion seems irresistible348; and doubtless it would be a sound one — a good Baconian conclusion — if we were to admit, with the materialists, that the possibilities of existence are limited by our tiny and ephemeral experience.
But now, supposing some Platonic speculator were to come along and insist upon our leaving room for an alternative conclusion; suppose he were to urge upon us that all this process of material development, with the discovery of which our patient study has been rewarded, may be but the temporary manifestation of relations otherwise unknown between ourselves and the infinite Deity; suppose he were to argue that psychical qualities may be inherent in a spiritual substance which under certain conditions becomes incarnated349 in matter, to wear it as a perishable garment for a brief season, but presently to cast it off and enter upon the freedom of a larger existence; — what reply should we be bound to make, bearing in mind that the possibilities of existence are in no wise limited by our experience? Obviously we should be bound to admit that in sound philosophy this conclusion is just as likely to be true as the other. We should, indeed, warn him not to call on us to help him to establish it by scientific arguments; and we should remind him that he must not make illicit350 use of his extra-experiential hypotheses by bringing them into the treatment of scientific questions that lie within the range of experience. In science, for example, we make no use of the conception of a “spiritual substance” (or of a “material substance” either), because we can get along sufficiently well by dealing solely351 with qualities. But with this general understanding we should feel bound to concede the impregnableness of his main position.
I have supposed this theory only as an illustration, not as a theory which I am prepared to adopt. My present purpose is not to treat as an advocate the question of a future life, but to endeavour to point out what conditions should be observed in treating the question philosophically352. It seems to me that a great deal is gained when we have distinctly set before us what are the peculiar conditions of proof in the case of such transcendental questions. We have gained a great deal when we have learned how thoroughly impotent, how truly irrelevant353, is physical investigation354 in the presence of such a question. If we get not much positive satisfaction for our unquiet yearnings, we occupy at any rate a sounder philosophic position when we recognize the limits within which our conclusions, whether positive or negative, are valid.
It seems not improbable that Mr. Mill may have had in mind something like the foregoing considerations when he suggested that there is no reason why one should not entertain the belief in a future life if the belief be necessary to one’s spiritual comfort. Perhaps no suggestion in Mr. Mill’s richly suggestive posthumous356 work has been more generally condemned357 as unphilosophical, on the ground that in matters of belief we must be guided, not by our likes and dislikes, but by the evidence that is accessible. The objection is certainly a sound one so far as it relates to scientific questions where evidence is accessible. To hesitate to adopt a well-supported theory because of some vague preference for a different view is in scientific matters the one unpardonable sin — a sin which has been only too often committed. Even in matters which lie beyond the range of experience, where evidence is inaccessible, desire is not to be regarded as by itself an adequate basis for belief. But it seems to me that Mr. Mill showed a deeper knowledge of the limitations of scientific method than his critics, when he thus hinted at the possibility of entertaining a belief not amenable358 to scientific tests. The hypothesis of a purely spiritual unseen world, as above described, is entirely removed from the jurisdiction of physical inquiry, and can only be judged on general considerations of what has been called “moral probability”; and considerations of this sort are likely, in the future as in the past, to possess different values for different minds. He who, on such considerations, entertains a belief in a future life may not demand that his sceptical neighbour shall be convinced by the same considerations; but his neighbour is at the same time estopped from stigmatizing359 his belief as unphilosophical.
The consideration which must influence most minds in their attitude toward this question, is the craving360, almost universally felt, for some teleological solution to the problem of existence. Why we are here now is a question of even profounder interest than whether we are to live hereafter. Unfortunately its solution carries us no less completely beyond the range of experience! The belief that all things are working together for some good end is the most essential expression of religious faith: of all intellectual propositions it is the one most closely related to that emotional yearning355 for a higher and better life which is the sum and substance of religion. Yet all the treatises361 on natural theology that have ever been written have barely succeeded in establishing a low degree of scientific probability for this belief. In spite of the eight Bridgewater Treatises, and the “Ninth” beside, dysteleology still holds full half the field as against teleology362. Most of this difficulty, however, results from the crude anthropomorphic views which theologians have held concerning God. Once admitting that the Divine attributes may be (as they must be) incommensurably greater than human attributes, our faith that all things are working together for good may remain unimpugned.
To many minds such a faith will seem incompatible with belief in the ultimate destruction of sentiency amid the general doom of the material universe. A good end can have no meaning to us save in relation to consciousness that distinguishes and knows the good from the evil. There could be no better illustration of how we are hemmed363 in than the very inadequacy of the words with which we try to discuss this subject. Such words have all gained their meanings from human experience, and hence of necessity carry anthropomorphic implications. But we cannot help this. We must think with the symbols with which experience has furnished us; and when we so think, there does seem to be little that is even intellectually satisfying in the awful picture which science shows us, of giant worlds concentrating out of nebulous vapour, developing with prodigious waste of energy into theatres of all that is grand and sacred in spiritual endeavour, clashing and exploding again into dead vapour-balls, only to renew the same toilful process without end — a senseless bubble-play of Titan forces, with life, love, and aspiration brought forth only to be extinguished. The human mind, however “scientific” its training, must often recoil364 from the conclusion that this is all; and there are moments when one passionately feels that this cannot be all. On warm June mornings in green country lanes, with sweet pine-odours wafted365 in the breeze which sighs through the branches, and cloud-shadows flitting over far-off blue mountains, while little birds sing their love-songs, and golden-haired children weave garlands of wild roses; or when in the solemn twilight366 we listen to wondrous harmonies of Beethoven and Chopin that stir the heart like voices from an unseen world; at such times one feels that the profoundest answer which science can give to our questionings is but a superficial answer after all. At these moments, when the world seems fullest of beauty, one feels most strongly that it is but the harbinger of something else — that the ceaseless play of phenomena is no mere sport of Titans, but an orderly scene, with its reason for existing, its
“One divine far-off event
To which the whole creation moves.”
Difficult as it is to disentangle the elements of reasoning that enter into these complex groups of feeling, one may still see, I think, that it is speculative interest in the world, rather than anxious interest in self, that predominates. The desire for immortality in its lowest phase is merely the outcome of the repugnance367 we feel toward thinking of the final cessation of vigorous vital activity. Such a feeling is naturally strong with healthy people. But in the mood which I have above tried to depict, this feeling, or any other which is merely self-regarding, is lost sight of in the feeling which associates a future life with some solution of the burdensome problem of existence. Had we but faith enough to lighten the burden of this problem, the inferior question would perhaps be less absorbing. Could we but know that our present lives are working together toward some good end, even an end in no wise anthropomorphic, it would be of less consequence whether we were individually to endure. To the dog under the knife of the experimenter, the world is a world of pure evil; yet could the poor beast but understand the alleviation368 of human suffering to which he is contributing, he would be forced to own that this is not quite true; and if he were also a heroic or Christian dog, the thought would perhaps take away from death its sting. The analogy may be a crude one; but the reasonableness of the universe is at least as far above our comprehension as the purposes of man surpass the understanding of the dog. Believing, however, though as a simple act of trust, that the end will crown the work, we may rise superior to the question which has here concerned us, and exclaim, in the supreme language of faith, “Though He slay369 me, yet will I trust in Him!”
July, 1875.
![](../../../skin/default/image/4.jpg)
点击
收听单词发音
![收听单词发音](/template/default/tingnovel/images/play.gif)
1
par
![]() |
|
n.标准,票面价值,平均数量;adj.票面的,平常的,标准的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2
wayfarer
![]() |
|
n.旅人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3
wondrous
![]() |
|
adj.令人惊奇的,奇妙的;adv.惊人地;异乎寻常地;令人惊叹地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4
elicit
![]() |
|
v.引出,抽出,引起 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5
bungled
![]() |
|
v.搞糟,完不成( bungle的过去式和过去分词 );笨手笨脚地做;失败;完不成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6
considerably
![]() |
|
adv.极大地;相当大地;在很大程度上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7
inquiry
![]() |
|
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8
scanty
![]() |
|
adj.缺乏的,仅有的,节省的,狭小的,不够的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9
speculation
![]() |
|
n.思索,沉思;猜测;投机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10
terminology
![]() |
|
n.术语;专有名词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11
dint
![]() |
|
n.由于,靠;凹坑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12
arduous
![]() |
|
adj.艰苦的,费力的,陡峭的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13
linguistic
![]() |
|
adj.语言的,语言学的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14
accurately
![]() |
|
adv.准确地,精确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15
inaccurate
![]() |
|
adj.错误的,不正确的,不准确的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16
primitive
![]() |
|
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17
enchanted
![]() |
|
adj. 被施魔法的,陶醉的,入迷的 动词enchant的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18
quaint
![]() |
|
adj.古雅的,离奇有趣的,奇怪的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19
savage
![]() |
|
adj.野蛮的;凶恶的,残暴的;n.未开化的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20
wrought
![]() |
|
v.引起;以…原料制作;运转;adj.制造的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21
grotesque
![]() |
|
adj.怪诞的,丑陋的;n.怪诞的图案,怪人(物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22
implicated
![]() |
|
adj.密切关联的;牵涉其中的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23
ethical
![]() |
|
adj.伦理的,道德的,合乎道德的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24
amend
![]() |
|
vt.修改,修订,改进;n.[pl.]赔罪,赔偿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25
atheist
![]() |
|
n.无神论者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26
civilized
![]() |
|
a.有教养的,文雅的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27
antagonists
![]() |
|
对立[对抗] 者,对手,敌手( antagonist的名词复数 ); 对抗肌; 对抗药 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28
reconciliation
![]() |
|
n.和解,和谐,一致 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29
curiously
![]() |
|
adv.有求知欲地;好问地;奇特地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30
longing
![]() |
|
n.(for)渴望 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31
aspiration
![]() |
|
n.志向,志趣抱负;渴望;(语)送气音;吸出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32
gist
![]() |
|
n.要旨;梗概 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33
ken
![]() |
|
n.视野,知识领域 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34
perennial
![]() |
|
adj.终年的;长久的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35
apparently
![]() |
|
adv.显然地;表面上,似乎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36
consigned
![]() |
|
v.把…置于(令人不快的境地)( consign的过去式和过去分词 );把…托付给;把…托人代售;丟弃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37
limbo
![]() |
|
n.地狱的边缘;监狱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38
mythology
![]() |
|
n.神话,神话学,神话集 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39
distinguished
![]() |
|
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40
random
![]() |
|
adj.随机的;任意的;n.偶然的(或随便的)行动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41
riddle
![]() |
|
n.谜,谜语,粗筛;vt.解谜,给…出谜,筛,检查,鉴定,非难,充满于;vi.出谜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42
riddles
![]() |
|
n.谜(语)( riddle的名词复数 );猜不透的难题,难解之谜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43
unravelled
![]() |
|
解开,拆散,散开( unravel的过去式和过去分词 ); 阐明; 澄清; 弄清楚 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44
indefatigable
![]() |
|
adj.不知疲倦的,不屈不挠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45
secondly
![]() |
|
adv.第二,其次 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46
latitude
![]() |
|
n.纬度,行动或言论的自由(范围),(pl.)地区 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47
specially
![]() |
|
adv.特定地;特殊地;明确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48
speculative
![]() |
|
adj.思索性的,暝想性的,推理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49
unlimited
![]() |
|
adj.无限的,不受控制的,无条件的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50
formerly
![]() |
|
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51
secular
![]() |
|
n.牧师,凡人;adj.世俗的,现世的,不朽的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52
contraction
![]() |
|
n.缩略词,缩写式,害病 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53
catastrophe
![]() |
|
n.大灾难,大祸 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54
inevitably
![]() |
|
adv.不可避免地;必然发生地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55
countless
![]() |
|
adj.无数的,多得不计其数的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56
pervaded
![]() |
|
v.遍及,弥漫( pervade的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57
unity
![]() |
|
n.团结,联合,统一;和睦,协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58
manifestation
![]() |
|
n.表现形式;表明;现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59
incompatible
![]() |
|
adj.不相容的,不协调的,不相配的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60
deities
![]() |
|
n.神,女神( deity的名词复数 );神祗;神灵;神明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61
mythologies
![]() |
|
神话学( mythology的名词复数 ); 神话(总称); 虚构的事实; 错误的观点 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62
abstaining
![]() |
|
戒(尤指酒),戒除( abstain的现在分词 ); 弃权(不投票) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63
philosophic
![]() |
|
adj.哲学的,贤明的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64
haphazard
![]() |
|
adj.无计划的,随意的,杂乱无章的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65
proceeding
![]() |
|
n.行动,进行,(pl.)会议录,学报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66
inevitable
![]() |
|
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67
datum
![]() |
|
n.资料;数据;已知数 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68
induction
![]() |
|
n.感应,感应现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69
unwilling
![]() |
|
adj.不情愿的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70
supreme
![]() |
|
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71
outlet
![]() |
|
n.出口/路;销路;批发商店;通风口;发泄 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72
joint
![]() |
|
adj.联合的,共同的;n.关节,接合处;v.连接,贴合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73
eminent
![]() |
|
adj.显赫的,杰出的,有名的,优良的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74
physicists
![]() |
|
物理学家( physicist的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75
ingenuity
![]() |
|
n.别出心裁;善于发明创造 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76
subtlety
![]() |
|
n.微妙,敏锐,精巧;微妙之处,细微的区别 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77
conjecture
![]() |
|
n./v.推测,猜测 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78
recede
![]() |
|
vi.退(去),渐渐远去;向后倾斜,缩进 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79
forth
![]() |
|
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80
speculations
![]() |
|
n.投机买卖( speculation的名词复数 );思考;投机活动;推断 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81
doctrine
![]() |
|
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82
akin
![]() |
|
adj.同族的,类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83
nebula
![]() |
|
n.星云,喷雾剂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84
astronomer
![]() |
|
n.天文学家 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85
flattened
![]() |
|
[医](水)平扁的,弄平的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86
accounting
![]() |
|
n.会计,会计学,借贷对照表 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87
distended
![]() |
|
v.(使)膨胀,肿胀( distend的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88
diffused
![]() |
|
散布的,普及的,扩散的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89
Neptune
![]() |
|
n.海王星 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90
relatively
![]() |
|
adv.比较...地,相对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91
rotation
![]() |
|
n.旋转;循环,轮流 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92
breach
![]() |
|
n.违反,不履行;破裂;vt.冲破,攻破 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93
coalesced
![]() |
|
v.联合,合并( coalesce的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94
immediate
![]() |
|
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95
abort
![]() |
|
v.使流产,堕胎;中止;中止(工作、计划等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96
Saturn
![]() |
|
n.农神,土星 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97
mere
![]() |
|
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98
mutual
![]() |
|
adj.相互的,彼此的;共同的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99
incessantly
![]() |
|
ad.不停地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100
thoroughly
![]() |
|
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101
atmospheric
![]() |
|
adj.大气的,空气的;大气层的;大气所引起的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102
phenomena
![]() |
|
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103
incandescence
![]() |
|
n.白热,炽热;白炽 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104
Fahrenheit
![]() |
|
n./adj.华氏温度;华氏温度计(的) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105
diminution
![]() |
|
n.减少;变小 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106
doom
![]() |
|
n.厄运,劫数;v.注定,命定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107
postponed
![]() |
|
vt.& vi.延期,缓办,(使)延迟vt.把…放在次要地位;[语]把…放在后面(或句尾)vi.(疟疾等)延缓发作(或复发) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108
conformity
![]() |
|
n.一致,遵从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109
astronomers
![]() |
|
n.天文学者,天文学家( astronomer的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110
friction
![]() |
|
n.摩擦,摩擦力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111
infinitely
![]() |
|
adv.无限地,无穷地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112
momentum
![]() |
|
n.动力,冲力,势头;动量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113
concussion
![]() |
|
n.脑震荡;震动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114
outermost
![]() |
|
adj.最外面的,远离中心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115
dilated
![]() |
|
adj.加宽的,扩大的v.(使某物)扩大,膨胀,张大( dilate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116
briefly
![]() |
|
adv.简单地,简短地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117
prodigal
![]() |
|
adj.浪费的,挥霍的,放荡的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118
geologic
![]() |
|
adj.地质的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119
wasteful
![]() |
|
adj.(造成)浪费的,挥霍的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120
prodigally
![]() |
|
adv.浪费地,丰饶地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121
circumference
![]() |
|
n.圆周,周长,圆周线 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122
utilize
![]() |
|
vt.使用,利用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123
radius
![]() |
|
n.半径,半径范围;有效航程,范围,界限 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124
residue
![]() |
|
n.残余,剩余,残渣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125
utilized
![]() |
|
v.利用,使用( utilize的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126
potent
![]() |
|
adj.强有力的,有权势的;有效力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127
darts
![]() |
|
n.掷飞镖游戏;飞镖( dart的名词复数 );急驰,飞奔v.投掷,投射( dart的第三人称单数 );向前冲,飞奔 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128
surmise
![]() |
|
v./n.猜想,推测 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129
insignificant
![]() |
|
adj.无关紧要的,可忽略的,无意义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130
remains
![]() |
|
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131
valid
![]() |
|
adj.有确实根据的;有效的;正当的,合法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132
dealing
![]() |
|
n.经商方法,待人态度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133
circumscribed
![]() |
|
adj.[医]局限的:受限制或限于有限空间的v.在…周围划线( circumscribe的过去式和过去分词 );划定…范围;限制;限定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134
undoubtedly
![]() |
|
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135
sidereal
![]() |
|
adj.恒星的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136
spectrum
![]() |
|
n.谱,光谱,频谱;范围,幅度,系列 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137
perennially
![]() |
|
adv.经常出现地;长期地;持久地;永久地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138
drawn
![]() |
|
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139
remodel
![]() |
|
v.改造,改型,改变 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140
disintegration
![]() |
|
n.分散,解体 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141
accomplished
![]() |
|
adj.有才艺的;有造诣的;达到了的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142
eternity
![]() |
|
n.不朽,来世;永恒,无穷 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143
prospect
![]() |
|
n.前景,前途;景色,视野 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144
transformations
![]() |
|
n.变化( transformation的名词复数 );转换;转换;变换 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145
transformation
![]() |
|
n.变化;改造;转变 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146
excellence
![]() |
|
n.优秀,杰出,(pl.)优点,美德 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147
essentially
![]() |
|
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148
aggregation
![]() |
|
n.聚合,组合;凝聚 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149
kinetic
![]() |
|
adj.运动的;动力学的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150
immortality
![]() |
|
n.不死,不朽 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151
immortal
![]() |
|
adj.不朽的;永生的,不死的;神的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
152
transcend
![]() |
|
vt.超出,超越(理性等)的范围 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
153
velocity
![]() |
|
n.速度,速率 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
154
stagnation
![]() |
|
n. 停滞 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
155
depict
![]() |
|
vt.描画,描绘;描写,描述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
156
depicted
![]() |
|
描绘,描画( depict的过去式和过去分词 ); 描述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
157
infinity
![]() |
|
n.无限,无穷,大量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
158
strictly
![]() |
|
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
159
capabilities
![]() |
|
n.能力( capability的名词复数 );可能;容量;[复数]潜在能力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
160
gauge
![]() |
|
v.精确计量;估计;n.标准度量;计量器 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
161
explicit
![]() |
|
adj.详述的,明确的;坦率的;显然的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
162
vicissitudes
![]() |
|
n.变迁,世事变化;变迁兴衰( vicissitude的名词复数 );盛衰兴废 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
163
pervading
![]() |
|
v.遍及,弥漫( pervade的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
164
remarkable
![]() |
|
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
165
enveloping
![]() |
|
v.包围,笼罩,包住( envelop的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
166
molecule
![]() |
|
n.分子,克分子 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
167
molecules
![]() |
|
分子( molecule的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
168
thermal
![]() |
|
adj.热的,由热造成的;保暖的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
169
luminous
![]() |
|
adj.发光的,发亮的;光明的;明白易懂的;有启发的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
170
vibrations
![]() |
|
n.摆动( vibration的名词复数 );震动;感受;(偏离平衡位置的)一次性往复振动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
171
vibration
![]() |
|
n.颤动,振动;摆动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
172
partially
![]() |
|
adv.部分地,从某些方面讲 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
173
justified
![]() |
|
a.正当的,有理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
174
encompassing
![]() |
|
v.围绕( encompass的现在分词 );包围;包含;包括 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
175
sufficiently
![]() |
|
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
176
elastic
![]() |
|
n.橡皮圈,松紧带;adj.有弹性的;灵活的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
177
contradictory
![]() |
|
adj.反驳的,反对的,抗辩的;n.正反对,矛盾对立 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
178
appreciable
![]() |
|
adj.明显的,可见的,可估量的,可觉察的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
179
contemplating
![]() |
|
深思,细想,仔细考虑( contemplate的现在分词 ); 注视,凝视; 考虑接受(发生某事的可能性); 深思熟虑,沉思,苦思冥想 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
180
firmament
![]() |
|
n.苍穹;最高层 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
181
disturbance
![]() |
|
n.动乱,骚动;打扰,干扰;(身心)失调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
182
previously
![]() |
|
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
183
eminently
![]() |
|
adv.突出地;显著地;不寻常地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
184
gaseous
![]() |
|
adj.气体的,气态的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
185
entail
![]() |
|
vt.使承担,使成为必要,需要 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
186
cylindrical
![]() |
|
adj.圆筒形的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
187
smoker
![]() |
|
n.吸烟者,吸烟车厢,吸烟室 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
188
puff
![]() |
|
n.一口(气);一阵(风);v.喷气,喘气 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
189
frictionless
![]() |
|
adj.没有摩擦力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
190
peculiar
![]() |
|
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
191
conjectural
![]() |
|
adj.推测的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
192
legitimate
![]() |
|
adj.合法的,合理的,合乎逻辑的;v.使合法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
193
postulated
![]() |
|
v.假定,假设( postulate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
194
conspicuous
![]() |
|
adj.明眼的,惹人注目的;炫耀的,摆阔气的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
195
elasticity
![]() |
|
n.弹性,伸缩力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
196
lucid
![]() |
|
adj.明白易懂的,清晰的,头脑清楚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
197
component
![]() |
|
n.组成部分,成分,元件;adj.组成的,合成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
198
coagulation
![]() |
|
n.凝固;凝结物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
199
dispensed
![]() |
|
v.分配( dispense的过去式和过去分词 );施与;配(药) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
200
rigid
![]() |
|
adj.严格的,死板的;刚硬的,僵硬的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
201
rotary
![]() |
|
adj.(运动等)旋转的;轮转的;转动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
202
entirely
![]() |
|
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
203
destitute
![]() |
|
adj.缺乏的;穷困的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
204
perfectly
![]() |
|
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
205
primordial
![]() |
|
adj.原始的;最初的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
206
meddle
![]() |
|
v.干预,干涉,插手 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
207
accredit
![]() |
|
vt.归功于,认为 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
208
destined
![]() |
|
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
209
lasting
![]() |
|
adj.永久的,永恒的;vbl.持续,维持 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
210
inert
![]() |
|
adj.无活动能力的,惰性的;迟钝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
211
functionally
![]() |
|
adv.机能上地,官能地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
212
effete
![]() |
|
adj.无生产力的,虚弱的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
213
efface
![]() |
|
v.擦掉,抹去 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
214
starry
![]() |
|
adj.星光照耀的, 闪亮的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
215
galaxy
![]() |
|
n.星系;银河系;一群(杰出或著名的人物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
216
audacity
![]() |
|
n.大胆,卤莽,无礼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
217
modesty
![]() |
|
n.谦逊,虚心,端庄,稳重,羞怯,朴素 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
218
rhythmically
![]() |
|
adv.有节奏地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
219
sublime
![]() |
|
adj.崇高的,伟大的;极度的,不顾后果的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
220
plausibility
![]() |
|
n. 似有道理, 能言善辩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
221
assent
![]() |
|
v.批准,认可;n.批准,认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
222
jurisdiction
![]() |
|
n.司法权,审判权,管辖权,控制权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
223
broached
![]() |
|
v.谈起( broach的过去式和过去分词 );打开并开始用;用凿子扩大(或修光);(在桶上)钻孔取液体 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
224
subjective
![]() |
|
a.主观(上)的,个人的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
225
wrangle
![]() |
|
vi.争吵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
226
qualified
![]() |
|
adj.合格的,有资格的,胜任的,有限制的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
227
molecular
![]() |
|
adj.分子的;克分子的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
228
underlying
![]() |
|
adj.在下面的,含蓄的,潜在的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
229
justification
![]() |
|
n.正当的理由;辩解的理由 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
230
esteemed
![]() |
|
adj.受人尊敬的v.尊敬( esteem的过去式和过去分词 );敬重;认为;以为 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
231
contemplated
![]() |
|
adj. 预期的 动词contemplate的过去分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
232
attained
![]() |
|
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
233
sustenance
![]() |
|
n.食物,粮食;生活资料;生计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
234
turmoil
![]() |
|
n.骚乱,混乱,动乱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
235
expounder
![]() |
|
陈述者,说明者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
236
hurl
![]() |
|
vt.猛投,力掷,声叫骂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
237
materialism
![]() |
|
n.[哲]唯物主义,唯物论;物质至上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
238
materialistic
![]() |
|
a.唯物主义的,物质享乐主义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
239
propound
![]() |
|
v.提出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
240
persistency
![]() |
|
n. 坚持(余辉, 时间常数) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
241
machinery
![]() |
|
n.(总称)机械,机器;机构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
242
recur
![]() |
|
vi.复发,重现,再发生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
243
frightful
![]() |
|
adj.可怕的;讨厌的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
244
expenditure
![]() |
|
n.(时间、劳力、金钱等)支出;使用,消耗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
245
outwards
![]() |
|
adj.外面的,公开的,向外的;adv.向外;n.外形 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
246
teleological
![]() |
|
adj.目的论的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
247
virtue
![]() |
|
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
248
vessel
![]() |
|
n.船舶;容器,器皿;管,导管,血管 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
249
impelled
![]() |
|
v.推动、推进或敦促某人做某事( impel的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
250
furrow
![]() |
|
n.沟;垄沟;轨迹;车辙;皱纹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
251
vows
![]() |
|
誓言( vow的名词复数 ); 郑重宣布,许愿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
252
perpetuating
![]() |
|
perpetuate的现在进行式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
253
testimony
![]() |
|
n.证词;见证,证明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
254
displacements
![]() |
|
n.取代( displacement的名词复数 );替代;移位;免职 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
255
complement
![]() |
|
n.补足物,船上的定员;补语;vt.补充,补足 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
256
teleologically
![]() |
|
adj.目的论的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
257
gratuitous
![]() |
|
adj.无偿的,免费的;无缘无故的,不必要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
258
treatise
![]() |
|
n.专著;(专题)论文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
259
prodigious
![]() |
|
adj.惊人的,奇妙的;异常的;巨大的;庞大的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
260
simultaneously
![]() |
|
adv.同时发生地,同时进行地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
261
quaintly
![]() |
|
adv.古怪离奇地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
262
extinction
![]() |
|
n.熄灭,消亡,消灭,灭绝,绝种 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
263
awakening
![]() |
|
n.觉醒,醒悟 adj.觉醒中的;唤醒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
264
consistency
![]() |
|
n.一贯性,前后一致,稳定性;(液体的)浓度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
265
domain
![]() |
|
n.(活动等)领域,范围;领地,势力范围 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
266
predecessor
![]() |
|
n.前辈,前任 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
267
philosophical
![]() |
|
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
268
doctrines
![]() |
|
n.教条( doctrine的名词复数 );教义;学说;(政府政策的)正式声明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
269
nay
![]() |
|
adv.不;n.反对票,投反对票者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
270
perishable
![]() |
|
adj.(尤指食物)易腐的,易坏的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
271
gratuitously
![]() |
|
平白 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
272
complexity
![]() |
|
n.复杂(性),复杂的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
273
analogous
![]() |
|
adj.相似的;类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
274
allude
![]() |
|
v.提及,暗指 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
275
repudiated
![]() |
|
v.(正式地)否认( repudiate的过去式和过去分词 );拒绝接受;拒绝与…往来;拒不履行(法律义务) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
276
lurk
![]() |
|
n.潜伏,潜行;v.潜藏,潜伏,埋伏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
277
etymologies
![]() |
|
n.词源学,词源说明( etymology的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
278
platonic
![]() |
|
adj.精神的;柏拉图(哲学)的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
279
brute
![]() |
|
n.野兽,兽性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
280
tangible
![]() |
|
adj.有形的,可触摸的,确凿的,实际的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
281
Christian
![]() |
|
adj.基督教徒的;n.基督教徒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
282
outgrown
![]() |
|
长[发展] 得超过(某物)的范围( outgrow的过去分词 ); 长[发展]得不能再要(某物); 长得比…快; 生长速度超过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
283
inverse
![]() |
|
adj.相反的,倒转的,反转的;n.相反之物;v.倒转 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
284
density
![]() |
|
n.密集,密度,浓度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
285
purely
![]() |
|
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
286
mythologic
![]() |
|
神话学的,神话的,虚构的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
287
physically
![]() |
|
adj.物质上,体格上,身体上,按自然规律 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
288
precisely
![]() |
|
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
289
quantitative
![]() |
|
adj.数量的,定量的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
290
deriving
![]() |
|
v.得到( derive的现在分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
291
propriety
![]() |
|
n.正当行为;正当;适当 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
292
constituent
![]() |
|
n.选民;成分,组分;adj.组成的,构成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
293
relegated
![]() |
|
v.使降级( relegate的过去式和过去分词 );使降职;转移;把…归类 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
294
psychical
![]() |
|
adj.有关特异功能现象的;有关特异功能官能的;灵魂的;心灵的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
295
solicited
![]() |
|
v.恳求( solicit的过去式和过去分词 );(指娼妇)拉客;索求;征求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
296
transcends
![]() |
|
超出或超越(经验、信念、描写能力等)的范围( transcend的第三人称单数 ); 优于或胜过… | |
参考例句: |
|
|
297
deduction
![]() |
|
n.减除,扣除,减除额;推论,推理,演绎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
298
chasm
![]() |
|
n.深坑,断层,裂口,大分岐,利害冲突 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
299
indirectly
![]() |
|
adv.间接地,不直接了当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
300
secreting
![]() |
|
v.(尤指动物或植物器官)分泌( secrete的现在分词 );隐匿,隐藏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
301
gland
![]() |
|
n.腺体,(机)密封压盖,填料盖 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
302
utterly
![]() |
|
adv.完全地,绝对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
303
deflect
![]() |
|
v.(使)偏斜,(使)偏离,(使)转向 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
304
rudiment
![]() |
|
n.初步;初级;基本原理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
305
wittily
![]() |
|
机智地,机敏地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
306
gulf
![]() |
|
n.海湾;深渊,鸿沟;分歧,隔阂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
307
quantitatively
![]() |
|
adv.数量上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
308
denuded
![]() |
|
adj.[医]变光的,裸露的v.使赤裸( denude的过去式和过去分词 );剥光覆盖物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
309
intercourse
![]() |
|
n.性交;交流,交往,交际 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
310
justify
![]() |
|
vt.证明…正当(或有理),为…辩护 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
311
presumption
![]() |
|
n.推测,可能性,冒昧,放肆,[法律]推定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
312
aggregates
![]() |
|
数( aggregate的名词复数 ); 总计; 骨料; 集料(可成混凝土或修路等用的) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
313
glands
![]() |
|
n.腺( gland的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
314
pungent
![]() |
|
adj.(气味、味道)刺激性的,辛辣的;尖锐的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
315
decomposition
![]() |
|
n. 分解, 腐烂, 崩溃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
316
metallic
![]() |
|
adj.金属的;金属制的;含金属的;产金属的;像金属的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
317
sodium
![]() |
|
n.(化)钠 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
318
everlasting
![]() |
|
adj.永恒的,持久的,无止境的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
319
Christians
![]() |
|
n.基督教徒( Christian的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
320
renovation
![]() |
|
n.革新,整修 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
321
purgatory
![]() |
|
n.炼狱;苦难;adj.净化的,清洗的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
322
inadequacy
![]() |
|
n.无法胜任,信心不足 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
323
wont
![]() |
|
adj.习惯于;v.习惯;n.习惯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
324
eloquent
![]() |
|
adj.雄辩的,口才流利的;明白显示出的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
325
habitually
![]() |
|
ad.习惯地,通常地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
326
reverence
![]() |
|
n.敬畏,尊敬,尊严;Reverence:对某些基督教神职人员的尊称;v.尊敬,敬畏,崇敬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
327
sensuous
![]() |
|
adj.激发美感的;感官的,感觉上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
328
determined
![]() |
|
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
329
precedent
![]() |
|
n.先例,前例;惯例;adj.在前的,在先的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
330
thereby
![]() |
|
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
331
passionately
![]() |
|
ad.热烈地,激烈地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
332
faculty
![]() |
|
n.才能;学院,系;(学院或系的)全体教学人员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
333
flasks
![]() |
|
n.瓶,长颈瓶, 烧瓶( flask的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
334
skilful
![]() |
|
(=skillful)adj.灵巧的,熟练的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
335
interpretation
![]() |
|
n.解释,说明,描述;艺术处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
336
inaccessible
![]() |
|
adj.达不到的,难接近的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
337
alleged
![]() |
|
a.被指控的,嫌疑的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
338
impugn
![]() |
|
v.指责,对…表示怀疑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
339
irrational
![]() |
|
adj.无理性的,失去理性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
340
alluded
![]() |
|
提及,暗指( allude的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
341
parlance
![]() |
|
n.说法;语调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
342
disastrous
![]() |
|
adj.灾难性的,造成灾害的;极坏的,很糟的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
343
apprehend
![]() |
|
vt.理解,领悟,逮捕,拘捕,忧虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
344
deity
![]() |
|
n.神,神性;被奉若神明的人(或物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
345
specialized
![]() |
|
adj.专门的,专业化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
346
pertains
![]() |
|
关于( pertain的第三人称单数 ); 有关; 存在; 适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
347
harp
![]() |
|
n.竖琴;天琴座 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
348
irresistible
![]() |
|
adj.非常诱人的,无法拒绝的,无法抗拒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
349
incarnated
![]() |
|
v.赋予(思想、精神等)以人的形体( incarnate的过去式和过去分词 );使人格化;体现;使具体化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
350
illicit
![]() |
|
adj.非法的,禁止的,不正当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
351
solely
![]() |
|
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
352
philosophically
![]() |
|
adv.哲学上;富有哲理性地;贤明地;冷静地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
353
irrelevant
![]() |
|
adj.不恰当的,无关系的,不相干的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
354
investigation
![]() |
|
n.调查,调查研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
355
yearning
![]() |
|
a.渴望的;向往的;怀念的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
356
posthumous
![]() |
|
adj.遗腹的;父亡后出生的;死后的,身后的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
357
condemned
![]() |
|
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
358
amenable
![]() |
|
adj.经得起检验的;顺从的;对负有义务的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
359
stigmatizing
![]() |
|
v.使受耻辱,指责,污辱( stigmatize的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
360
craving
![]() |
|
n.渴望,热望 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
361
treatises
![]() |
|
n.专题著作,专题论文,专著( treatise的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
362
teleology
![]() |
|
n.目的论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
363
hemmed
![]() |
|
缝…的褶边( hem的过去式和过去分词 ); 包围 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
364
recoil
![]() |
|
vi.退却,退缩,畏缩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
365
wafted
![]() |
|
v.吹送,飘送,(使)浮动( waft的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
366
twilight
![]() |
|
n.暮光,黄昏;暮年,晚期,衰落时期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
367
repugnance
![]() |
|
n.嫌恶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
368
alleviation
![]() |
|
n. 减轻,缓和,解痛物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
369
slay
![]() |
|
v.杀死,宰杀,杀戮 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |