The ?sthetic psychosis has been by many evolutionists connected with sexual appetite and emotion. The evidence for this is that among animals the brilliant-hued, and, as we term them, beautiful mates are chosen in pairing time. Also graceful11 movements and melodious12 296tones are then employed. In mankind the ?sthetic feeling, as every one may recall in his own case, arose, and became prominent when near or in the teens. The rude boy and the hoyden13 girl then dress and adorn14 themselves, and a glamour15 of beauty is thrown about one who was once an entirely16 indifferent object. All the surroundings, artificial and natural, of the beloved object are looked upon and thought about in a new way of feeling, an air of attractiveness and beauty envelops17 all. The period of life of strongest sexuality, from twenty to forty, is also the period of strongest ?sthetic emotion. Further, sexuality is notedly strong among those who professionally cultivate the ?sthetic psychosis, as artists, musicians, and poets: indeed, many of the very greatest of these have been so carried away by the tender passion as to transgress19 the conventions and laws on sexual matters. In cases of precocious21 sexuality a feeling for the beautiful makes itself apparent; while with those who slowly mature, the ?sthetic feeling is similarly delayed. But does not the infant who holds out a rose to you and cries “pretty,” have a feeling for beauty? And it is surely unaffected by sexuality. What may be in the mind of a child speaking thus is hard to make out, but the activity is probably largely mimetic merely, and the term “pretty” is probably used substantively22 rather than qualitatively23; it is the name of thing rather than quality. We certainly cannot assert of a child that because it uses certain words it attaches to those words the proper meanings. This is evident from the fact that a child taught to say “pretty” will bring you any and every object and use the word, or if it learns to take merely a class of objects, as rose, it does this at dictation. The child is, however, obviously attracted by some objects rather than others, but it would be hasty to say that it perceives their beauty, when it is quite sufficient to regard them as conspicuous24 only, and striking. But we have to touch on sensing later; and we 297only add to the evidence of connection of feeling for beauty with sexual feeling, that with the old and with eunuchs the ?sthetic sense is but slight or tends to vanish. Thus positively25 and negatively there seems to be evidence that feeling for beauty originates in connection with sexual passion, either that the object of the passion is always regarded as beautiful, or that a feeling for beauty excites the passion. A girl adorns26 herself to attract lovers, knowing that to admire beauty is the first step to love. This close connection is recognised in common consciousness in that “lovely” is synonymous with beautiful, thus a “lovely” landscape or picture is a beautiful one.
That there is a close association of sexual with ?sthetic psychosis is then obvious in the case of the human being, but yet it would be quite hasty to conclude that a sweet note or a pure colour may not be ?sthetically appreciated by children before they have the first stirring toward sexuality, but still it is very easy—as I have before noted18 in the case of the child who cries “pretty!”—to mistake the quality of their interest.
But when we come to interpret the psychoses of the lower animals in connection with sexuality we may still more easily slip into a doubtful automorphism. Thus to say with Darwin, “When we behold27 a male bird elaborately displaying ... before the female, ... it is impossible to doubt that she admires the beauty of her male partner” (Descent of Man, p. 92), or more strongly still with Grant Allen, “Every crow must think its own mate beautiful” (Mind, v. 448), we too easily take for granted that these birds would feel like ourselves in corresponding circumstances. We can find a more simple explanation. That crows often maltreat those who are off colour, e.g., white, plainly does not require us to suppose that they regard white as ugly, black as beautiful, any more than we should judge that students in some Society who wear a 298black badge would be ?sthetically moved when they look with disfavour upon students who may wear a white badge. Animals are clannish28, and as a rule, suffer none but those who have the customary marks to associate with them, and especially to propagate. Hence when the peacock displays himself to his mate he simply shows to her that he has most conspicuously30 the proper marks, and she sees that he is the proper mate. These are signs of a tempting31 mate, just as here is tempting food, a very red ripe berry, but the coloration no more in the one case than the other awakens33 feeling for beauty. The hen bird probably appreciates a red feather as a red berry merely as being signs of the completely satisfying. Sexual selection, like nutriment selection, is a discrimination according to certain characters as prompted by appetite. The expanded and vari-coloured tail of a peacock is then a mere sexual characteristic which does not imply feeling for beauty in its appreciation34 as significant of sex. A small foot, long hair, and other sexual characters in woman, which are attractive to men, in like manner arouse emotion which is far from ?sthetic. We may take a perfectly35 unsexual ?sthetic pleasure in long raven36 tresses just as we do in an ebony table, but this is obviously rather late achievement.
In fact are not ?sthetic and sexual feelings mutually exclusive? So far as nude37 art is “suggestive,” so far is the feeling of its beauty lost, hence sculpture is not tinted39. And so in the presence of the nude model the artist can have merely ?sthetic emotion, whereas his visitor is apt to have emotions of another sort. We do, indeed, say that the lover dwells upon his mistress’ “beauties,” but beauties here mean attractions, and to the devoted40 lover all parts are attractive, even moles41 and freckles42 which to the ?sthetic eye are ugly.
From the evidence in hand we judge then that it is certainly not necessary to call in the feeling of the beautiful 299as the motive43 in the origin and development of sexual characters in animals and plants. Just as there is a cry of fear or a tone of anger there is a vocal44 expression of sexual feeling and emotion which has its use and is recognised as such, but whose ?sthetic quality is no more a matter of immediate45 apprehension46 than in other utilities. At least the safest interpretation47 that we can now make for all the lower grades of sexuality is that sex characters are not primarily determined48 by the feeling for beauty, but are simply immediate signs of sex to awaken32 the sexual response and secure the best mate. How is it that sexuality is so prominent in expression among some species and so little among others?—compare peacocks and blue jays—is a question on which we have no light. We are also in ignorance how the particular sexual character was evolved and not some other, for example, why is not the peacock’s tail red? Grant Allen’s suggestion that food selection has influenced sex selection may be true, but it would require a very wide and thorough investigation. Do brilliant-hued birds prefer brilliant-hued foods? How is the coloration of the scarlet49 tanager related to the coloration of its food? However, if the colouring of foods and mates were the same, it would in some cases lead to disadvantageous confusion, and on general principles we should expect such distinct elements as nutrition and sex to develop on very different lines. The cue for colour may be learned first with reference to food, but it may be carried on as sexually significant on very distinct lines. Still to distinguish a food or a mate by colour is equally non-?sthetic in itself. At least we think it improbable that ?sthetic psychosis arises as incentive50 to or reflex of sexuality in any of the lower psychic51 stages.
A theory of the origin of ?sthetic psychosis which has been pressed by some, as by Herbert Spencer, is that it arises as reflex from spontaneous outflow of energy, or more particularly in connection with play impulse. A 300horse turned loose in pasture may gambol52, running, sniffing53, looking around, all which denoting a free outflow of energy through lines of least resistance, the customary channels of activity. But we cannot seriously think that in this sensing and muscular activity there is implied any real ?sthetic psychosis, and indeed it seems quite emotionless. The emotion of fear or similar feelings aroused the original activities, but this present galloping54, etc., is automatic, and such immediate pleasure as may result from this free activity is scarcely of the ?sthetic order. The whole is of a distinctly lower order than the original activity and much below ?sthetic quality. If we recall our own state of mind in youthful “letting off steam” and in plays, we do not find ?sthetic pleasure. There is, however, a pleasure of relief and also positively a pleasure from such spontaneous outflow; but the outburst of pent-up energy automatically spent along lines of race action is a mere echo, dies out at once, and as degenerate55 form is not a starting point for origin of any new psychosis. Play as simulation of feeling and action is also removed from ?sthetic activity, as in a dog playing at fear and running, or at anger and chasing. He gets a more or less modified fear or anger, but there does not seem to be any tendency to ?sthetic psychosis. Mere imitation is more or less exact and skilful56, but emotion therein and thereat is plainly not the glow of ?sthetic emotion, but is reflex of sense of power and intelligence as qualities. Mimicry57 as mere outlet58 of energy as with monkeys is plainly not aesthetic59; here is merely an automatic outflow of force into suggested activity. When a savage60 as mimetic achievement carves the figure of man as handle to a knife, he accomplishes art, but not fine art. He has no more ?sthetic feeling than a boy or man whittling61 out a ship, it being merely an exact and skilful counterfeit62 of a real thing. Imitation for the sake of imitation or to deceive is a teleologic63 pleasure distinct from ?sthetic. Successful imitation is often said, indeed, to be 301“beautifully done,” but this means no more than well done. Even a well-baked cake is popularly spoken of as beautifully done.
We observe that superfluous65 energy rushes out along customary or habitual66 lines of activity, and so with perfect ease and economy. Activity which is easy and free is in itself pleasant, and this pleasantness in sensing and derived67 psychosis is ?sthetic feeling. Where sensing is mere escape valve of force, though facility is absolute, there is, as just pointed68 out, no ?sthetic quality, the whole tending to the merely mechanical. Owing to the fact that in nature curved lines predominate and so ocular adjustment is to them, my eye follows a curved line easier than a straight one, hence when spontaneous energy outflows in sensing activity of least resistance it will be toward curves. But spontaneous activity of this kind is, as we have explained, not ?sthetic. The law of economy in a vent20 is, greatest force, least effect, the contrary of the usual formula for economy which is, least force, greatest effect. Where energy is expensive the latter rule is to be applied69. Thus in directed and effortful sensing activity economy means the ratio of efficiency, the ratio of the amount of painful effort to desired result. But this is merely a saving of pain and not a real pleasure psychosis. When I, in using a microscope see clearly with less and less effort the objects of my study, I may take pleasure in the economical and facile accomplishment70, but this pleasure is one of satisfaction in power and skill, and so not at all ?sthetic. Again, a dyer has great skill and easy appreciation with respect to colour, but the ?sthetic side of colour is not thereby71 specially29 felt by him. Mere habitual and easy colour sensitiveness is not then thereby ?sthetic. We must, indeed, sense a colour before we can feel its beauty, but the feeling of beauty is not directly involved in any stage of the sensing evolution from the earliest and most painful effort with bare appreciation to the spontaneous 302and effortless sensing at the moment of great surplus of sensing energy.
Another way of accounting72 for ?sthetic psychosis is by association. Pleasant sights, for instance, are those with which we associate pleasure, and “pleasant” means to many, beautiful. But a traveller, thirsty in a desert land, declares that he saw no more pleasant sight than a mud hole, but this pleasure, as he himself would aver73, was far from ?sthetic. Whatever we have associated pleasure with, we regard with pleasure, but only as we have associated ?sthetic pleasure with it do we regard it with ?sthetic pleasure. Thus mere association or revival74 no more gives us the derivation of ?sthetic than any other emotion. Any pleasure or pain may be associated with any sensation or perception, and thereby re-occur with these, but the mere revival obviously does not alter the nature of the psychosis or give any new psychosis. It is not what is recalled, but how we feel about it that constitutes ?sthetic emotion. So also when the beautiful is defined by H. R. Marshall as “the permanently75 pleasurable in revival,” we get no insight into the origin, nature, and development of the ?sthetic psychosis; this purely76 objective description gives no psychological analysis. But we may question the accuracy of the description. A thing of beauty is not a joy for ever when we mean thereby the object which excites the ?sthetic psychosis, for much that has seemed beautiful to one people and age does not remain so for all peoples and times, and even with the individual, taste varies. We must also note that the permanently pleasurable in revival may not be ?sthetic, as the lover’s remembrance of a trysting place. On the whole, I do not find that ?sthetic pleasure is in any case to be ascribed to association, though it comes under the general laws of association like any other feeling. A lily excites various modes of ?sthetic impression by its form, colour, odour, poetical77 character, etc., all which may re-awaken together upon any presentation or suggestion 303of the lily. However, for the aboriginal78 lotus-eater the lily was also a pleasant sight—but not ?sthetic—from the associated pleasures of its pleasant taste and as satisfying hunger.
We have implied throughout—and common introspection approves this—that ?sthetic pleasure and emotion is a distinct psychosis which somehow arises with reference to objects. It is not some previous psychosis as modified by association, habit, economy, play-impulse, or sexuality; but it is a sui generis mode which develops on the basis of a past evolution. The simplest and earliest ?sthetic mode is plainly the sensuous79. Very commonly when looking on the delicate solid-tinted glow of early dawn I have ?sthetic pleasure, my eye dwells on it with pleasure and drinks in the pleasant light. It is obvious here that the sensing activity is carried on, not to discriminate80 food or mate nor yet as mere vent to energy; but the sensing here acts for the pleasure in the activity itself. How and why mere cognitive act, which originates as guide to life, acquires a direct pleasure value and so is carried on apart from the ends of life, and initiates81 an ?sthetic world of its own, cannot on the face of it be explained by natural selection; it is entirely apart from this order of things. But we know that sensing often carries pleasure with it as significant of life value, thus the thing tasting good was originally the good thing to eat, digest and assimilate; so also for smell, etc. But under natural selection this pleasure sanction and index was never cultivated for its own sake.
Now is there any real difference in the pleasure in, for instance, smelling, for the pure pleasure of smelling, as a perfume of fresh apples, and the pleasure from smelling the apples as detecting them when you are hungry? “How pleasant those apples smell! I do not care to eat them, but I just enjoy smelling them”; is the pleasure thus indicated the same in quality with that of the man who says, “Those apples smell so nice I would like to 304try one”? Again, if hungry, we say, “The bread tastes so good,” but we notice this pleasantness rapidly decreases as appetite is satisfied. However, if there be fresh grass butter, you may continue to eat long after appetite is satisfied, for the pure pleasure of the taste. Obviously, the latter pleasure is not a mere continuance of the former. Relish82 and taste pleasure seem distinct. Again, a red apple is a pleasant sight to a hungry man and to an artist in different ways. If our pleasure in looking at a picture of an apple is such that the mouth waters, we know at once that the pleasure is un?sthetic. He who is very fond of apples, and to whom they are always a pleasant sight, is so far barred from ?sthetic pleasure in them; while he who has no appreciation of their edibility83 is thereby prepared for ?sthetically sensing them. So also sour grapes are as pretty as sweet. The colour sense began as discriminative84 of foods, and hence red became pleasurably known, but ?sthetic appreciation is certainly much later and quite diverse. If it be asked how and when did red, already noticeable, become dwelt upon ?sthetically, all we can hazard in reply is that at some leisure moment when unmoved by appetite a surplus of energy set up an habitual sensing activity, as noticing reds, and at a certain stage when some directing is exercised, there comes a unique pleasure from the mere sensing, and the red is therefore dwelt upon. ?sthetic colour-pleasure in the simplest case arises then in every one’s experience.
Sense-pleasure is thus distinctly of two kinds, first, as arising in direct connection with general organic demands and satisfactions—the part as serving the whole; second, as arising immediately from the sense-activity—the whole as serving the part. A monkey may find an apple a pleasant sight, but loses all interest when the apple is seen to be an imitation: the monkey has the first pleasure, but not the second. The sensuous ?sthetic problem is merely to introspect the quality of the sensing-for-itself-pleasure 305as distinct from pleasantness coming from the service of life. A sense which develops its own pleasurableness is on a new line, which we term the ?sthetic. ?sthetic activity is distinct from mere vent activity of superfluous energy by reason of being carried on self-directed by the felt pleasure of activity; it implies a measure of self-direction and self-consciousness. ?sthetic activity may then be generally described as primarily a sensing carried on, not as means, but for its own sake in pleasure immediately resulting. And we find that in this very general meaning all senses have their ?sthetic activity. The temperature sense is carried on, as in basking85, for the pure pleasure of warmth. A cat behind a stove is a connoisseur86 in ?sthetic warmth sensations, and enjoys warmth for its own sake, so far as often to injure the organism as a whole. To lie in the sun and experience the thrills of pleasurable warmth and to keep up this sensing merely for the sensation pleasure is a frequent experience even with man. Again, the muscular and pressure senses often have a sphere of ?sthetic activity with athletes and lovers of exercise. When in prime condition, a man will toss weights about solely87 for the pleasure involved in the sense of pressure and of muscular activity. Touch also is plainly ?sthetic when one handles silk for the pleasure involved in its smoothness. Smell is obviously an ?sthetic activity in smelling perfumes for the pleasure of the smell. It is probable that the ?sthetic activity of this sense is far wider in some of the lower animals where the sense is much more acute, as the dog. The dog is plainly having a very different psychosis when he is smelling with pleasure a piece of meat which he is about to eat, and when he sniffs88 carrion89 and perfumes himself therewith. He gets thus a certain pleasant but gross stimulation90 quite akin10 to the pleasure some men take in musk91, an enjoyment92 of which is distinctly an animal trait. Again, the epicure93 who sips94 his rare wine is tasting for the pure pleasure of 306the taste, and exercises this sense ?sthetically. The ?sthetic of all these senses may be called the lower ?sthetic, in contradistinction to the higher ?sthetic of sight and hearing; but ?sthetic activity is throughout its whole range practically identical in nature and in the quality of its pleasure. When I lie in the sun and get warmth, not because I am cold, but for the mere pleasure of the warmth thrills, and when I keep looking at a delicate tint38 in the evening sky for the mere pleasure of the sensation, I have, as far as my introspection assures me, activities whose method and pleasure tone is identical.
Simple sensuous ?sthetic is no doubt the beginning of ?sthetic activity, but there speedily enters much complication. It often happens that single elements which separately do not excite us ?sthetically will produce a marked effect in conjunction, as complementary colours, for instance. Indeed, relation plays so large a place in our ?sthetic experience that such principles as variety and contrast, or, on the other hand, unity95, order, proportion, and harmony, have been made fundamental to the ?sthetic feeling. ?sthetic effect certainly here becomes a complex of two or more reinforcing sensations or perceptions. Where the sensuous elements of a perception are in themselves pleasing we may expect the unison96 in perception to be doubly pleasing. However, we may also conceive that ?sthetic pleasure arises as a reflex of perceptive97 activity in and for itself as a co-ordinating of impressions.
Fechner has made some experiments on what combinations are pleasing; but experiment in this direction is extremely difficult because so few people are willing to speak frankly98 of their ?sthetic feelings, being very sensitive about compromising themselves on matters of taste. There is also the great difficulty of isolation99, of making sure that association does not creep in and add unforeseen elements. If Fechner expected to get any judgments100 of value on such a matter as the golden section rectangle, he 307should have consulted only trained artists who are used to taking up the ?sthetic activity with reference to any material and expressing themselves with freedom. If this rectangle has the ?sthetic quality Fechner’s experiments suggest, it seems strange it was not adopted by the symmetry-loving Greeks in their temples, like the Parthenon.
To the spheres of simple and relational sense beauty we have to add a third—representative beauty. A colour, or two or more in combination which give ?sthetic satisfaction, will also please in hallucinatory vision and in representation proper where the revival is recognised in its unreality and representative nature, and also in recollection where the memory is willed. The mere imaging these colours without any definite time relation also gives ?sthetic pleasure. It is, indeed, a pleonasm to say that ?sthetic revivals101 are ?sthetic. However, imagination is productive as well as reproductive, hence the ideal achieves a fuller beauty than the real. Where the mind, prompted by ?sthetic desire, determines its own object, this object can more fully64 satisfy it than reality, which is always imperfect. Thus art surpasses nature, or more strictly102 is a higher nature. Idealism then is a mode of realism, and realism is but the ideal of actuality. But the imaging activity may, like the perceptive, be considered as in itself a source of ?sthetic pleasure. Imaging is primarily used in the service of life, as when walking in a forest I hear a peculiar103 cry, imagine a wolf, and flee. When imaging has been largely developed thus, it may often act as a mere vent to energy; but this kind of activity has here, no more than elsewhere, real ?sthetic quality. At the animistic stage children imagine in this way long before they ?sthetically image. When we consciously and with some self-direction enjoy imaging for its own sake, we attain104 the ?sthetic sphere. The ?sthetic pleasures which are suggested by such a phrase as—
308“Fair ship, that from the Italian shore
Sails the placid105 ocean plains”—
are not merely the sum of the original sense pleasures, but perceptive and imaginative pleasure per se is added, the image is more beautiful than the real vision, and this perception than some sense element, as the light sensation implied in “placid.”
?sthetic pleasure, even in sense, and much more in perceiving and imagining, is a delight, that is, ?sthetic quality is an emotion quality, it is not a mere feeling from an object, but a feeling about it. Now emotion may be enacted106 for emotion’s sake and so an ?sthetic pleasure wave be generated. This is the pleasure we take in the pathetic—pity, the sublime107, fear as awe108, the tragic-horror. These emotions are realized for themselves as a mode of pleasurable activity. ?sthetic emotion is also very largely emotion at emotion, as a feeling for the expressive109, still here the emotion is for its own sake.
?sthetic activity may then be described as an independent self-activity of some sense, or of perception, or imagination, or emotion as impelled110 by a pleasure, this pleasure being a distinct and new form we term ?sthetic. It is probable this pleasure first arose in connection with the exercise of the sense as a vent for spontaneous energy, and pleasure once somehow being taken in a mere activity per se, it is thenceforth conducted therefor. This is the plainest path of conjecture111 thus far. If the first ?sthetic pleasure were taken in some quiet moment of venting112 energy in sensing red, then red will continue to be sensed, impelled by the pleasure involved in the act. Granted such an origin, the development of ?sthetic psychosis can be traced in the way we have noted.
?sthetic psychosis is commonly regarded as passive, and it is indeed true that the first moment of the pleasure comes as result of an activity impelled by other motives113. New psychoses are not consciously formed but are rather 309hit upon in natural development; but once a new pleasure is felt its conditions will be attained114 and kept to by conscious effort, and the pleasure itself will receive its development only through effortful activity. It is by supreme115 effort the great artist attains116 the vision of beauty, it is by supreme effort he expresses this vision, it is by supreme effort the critic appreciates this expression. He who has no appreciation of sculpture may by patiently and earnestly observing statuary reach at length some ?sthetic pleasure. Thus the ?sthetic, like all mental modes, so far as progressive, is effortful; and it seems certain that the ?sthetic pleasures that come to us so easily are race acquirements, a heritage of culture. From its first germ onwards ?sthetic, like intellectual, like moral, like all mental activity, is the achievement of intense struggle.
With the rise of beauty we have a new utility. Here is a new pleasure which once experienced is sought and sought again, is developed, and with some natures becomes absorbing passion, the life. Objects fitted to give this pleasure are desired, are bought and sold. The beautiful is used to effect all kinds of ends. The lover adorns himself to make himself attractive, the advertiser distributes his bills in artistic117 shape, the real estate dealer118 ornaments119 his houses and grounds. Whatever will afford ?sthetic pleasure we are willing to pay for and pay high. In fact, in the person of a Patti the ?sthetic thrill becomes the most expensive taste which humanity can indulge. Art then is a utility—a something which satisfies desire—and as such it is not free or shareable. But one at a time can observe a picture from the best point of view. Rich men buy the most sightly spots in nature, the places of magnificent vistas120 and open to beautiful sunsets. Beautiful things are then desirables just like edible121 things or warm things, and as such they are not shareable. The feeling for beauty, just because it is self-contained, is far from being disinterested122. It is essentially selfish.
点击收听单词发音
1 scrutinize | |
n.详细检查,细读 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 distinctive | |
adj.特别的,有特色的,与众不同的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 cognitive | |
adj.认知的,认识的,有感知的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 bias | |
n.偏见,偏心,偏袒;vt.使有偏见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 investigation | |
n.调查,调查研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 aggregation | |
n.聚合,组合;凝聚 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 complexity | |
n.复杂(性),复杂的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 akin | |
adj.同族的,类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 graceful | |
adj.优美的,优雅的;得体的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 melodious | |
adj.旋律美妙的,调子优美的,音乐性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 hoyden | |
n.野丫头,淘气姑娘 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 adorn | |
vt.使美化,装饰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 glamour | |
n.魔力,魅力;vt.迷住 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 envelops | |
v.包围,笼罩,包住( envelop的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 noted | |
adj.著名的,知名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 transgress | |
vt.违反,逾越 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 vent | |
n.通风口,排放口;开衩;vt.表达,发泄 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 precocious | |
adj.早熟的;较早显出的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 substantively | |
adv.真实地;实质上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 qualitatively | |
质量上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 conspicuous | |
adj.明眼的,惹人注目的;炫耀的,摆阔气的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 positively | |
adv.明确地,断然,坚决地;实在,确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 adorns | |
装饰,佩带( adorn的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 behold | |
v.看,注视,看到 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 clannish | |
adj.排他的,门户之见的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 specially | |
adv.特定地;特殊地;明确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 conspicuously | |
ad.明显地,惹人注目地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 tempting | |
a.诱人的, 吸引人的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 awaken | |
vi.醒,觉醒;vt.唤醒,使觉醒,唤起,激起 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 awakens | |
v.(使)醒( awaken的第三人称单数 );(使)觉醒;弄醒;(使)意识到 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 appreciation | |
n.评价;欣赏;感谢;领会,理解;价格上涨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 raven | |
n.渡鸟,乌鸦;adj.乌亮的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 nude | |
adj.裸体的;n.裸体者,裸体艺术品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 tint | |
n.淡色,浅色;染发剂;vt.着以淡淡的颜色 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 tinted | |
adj. 带色彩的 动词tint的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 devoted | |
adj.忠诚的,忠实的,热心的,献身于...的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 moles | |
防波堤( mole的名词复数 ); 鼹鼠; 痣; 间谍 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 freckles | |
n.雀斑,斑点( freckle的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 vocal | |
adj.直言不讳的;嗓音的;n.[pl.]声乐节目 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 apprehension | |
n.理解,领悟;逮捕,拘捕;忧虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 interpretation | |
n.解释,说明,描述;艺术处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 scarlet | |
n.深红色,绯红色,红衣;adj.绯红色的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 incentive | |
n.刺激;动力;鼓励;诱因;动机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 psychic | |
n.对超自然力敏感的人;adj.有超自然力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 gambol | |
v.欢呼,雀跃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 sniffing | |
n.探查法v.以鼻吸气,嗅,闻( sniff的现在分词 );抽鼻子(尤指哭泣、患感冒等时出声地用鼻子吸气);抱怨,不以为然地说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 galloping | |
adj. 飞驰的, 急性的 动词gallop的现在分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 degenerate | |
v.退步,堕落;adj.退步的,堕落的;n.堕落者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 skilful | |
(=skillful)adj.灵巧的,熟练的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 mimicry | |
n.(生物)拟态,模仿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 outlet | |
n.出口/路;销路;批发商店;通风口;发泄 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 aesthetic | |
adj.美学的,审美的,有美感 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 savage | |
adj.野蛮的;凶恶的,残暴的;n.未开化的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 whittling | |
v.切,削(木头),使逐渐变小( whittle的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 counterfeit | |
vt.伪造,仿造;adj.伪造的,假冒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 teleologic | |
adj.目的论的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 superfluous | |
adj.过多的,过剩的,多余的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 habitual | |
adj.习惯性的;通常的,惯常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 pointed | |
adj.尖的,直截了当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 accomplishment | |
n.完成,成就,(pl.)造诣,技能 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 accounting | |
n.会计,会计学,借贷对照表 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 aver | |
v.极力声明;断言;确证 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 revival | |
n.复兴,复苏,(精力、活力等的)重振 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 permanently | |
adv.永恒地,永久地,固定不变地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 purely | |
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 poetical | |
adj.似诗人的;诗一般的;韵文的;富有诗意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 aboriginal | |
adj.(指动植物)土生的,原产地的,土著的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 sensuous | |
adj.激发美感的;感官的,感觉上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 discriminate | |
v.区别,辨别,区分;有区别地对待 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 initiates | |
v.开始( initiate的第三人称单数 );传授;发起;接纳新成员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 relish | |
n.滋味,享受,爱好,调味品;vt.加调味料,享受,品味;vi.有滋味 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 edibility | |
适食性,可食性; 可食用性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 discriminative | |
有判别力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 basking | |
v.晒太阳,取暖( bask的现在分词 );对…感到乐趣;因他人的功绩而出名;仰仗…的余泽 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 connoisseur | |
n.鉴赏家,行家,内行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 sniffs | |
v.以鼻吸气,嗅,闻( sniff的第三人称单数 );抽鼻子(尤指哭泣、患感冒等时出声地用鼻子吸气);抱怨,不以为然地说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 carrion | |
n.腐肉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 stimulation | |
n.刺激,激励,鼓舞 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 musk | |
n.麝香, 能发出麝香的各种各样的植物,香猫 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 enjoyment | |
n.乐趣;享有;享用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 epicure | |
n.行家,美食家 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 sips | |
n.小口喝,一小口的量( sip的名词复数 )v.小口喝,呷,抿( sip的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 unity | |
n.团结,联合,统一;和睦,协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 unison | |
n.步调一致,行动一致 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 perceptive | |
adj.知觉的,有洞察力的,感知的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 frankly | |
adv.坦白地,直率地;坦率地说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 isolation | |
n.隔离,孤立,分解,分离 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 judgments | |
判断( judgment的名词复数 ); 鉴定; 评价; 审判 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 revivals | |
n.复活( revival的名词复数 );再生;复兴;(老戏多年后)重新上演 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 placid | |
adj.安静的,平和的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 enacted | |
制定(法律),通过(法案)( enact的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 sublime | |
adj.崇高的,伟大的;极度的,不顾后果的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 awe | |
n.敬畏,惊惧;vt.使敬畏,使惊惧 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 expressive | |
adj.表现的,表达…的,富于表情的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 impelled | |
v.推动、推进或敦促某人做某事( impel的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 conjecture | |
n./v.推测,猜测 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 venting | |
消除; 泄去; 排去; 通风 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 attains | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的第三人称单数 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 artistic | |
adj.艺术(家)的,美术(家)的;善于艺术创作的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 dealer | |
n.商人,贩子 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 ornaments | |
n.装饰( ornament的名词复数 );点缀;装饰品;首饰v.装饰,点缀,美化( ornament的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 vistas | |
长条形景色( vista的名词复数 ); 回顾; 展望; (未来可能发生的)一系列情景 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 edible | |
n.食品,食物;adj.可食用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 disinterested | |
adj.不关心的,不感兴趣的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |