We may start from the distinction between facts and our knowledge of them, for it is clear that whatever the character of the facts may be, our knowledge of them, at least, is progressive. The past is dead and gone. It is something over and done with, so that any change in it is forever impossible. We should then, if we would be precise, say, not that it is the past[Pg 29] which grows and enlarges, but only our knowledge of it. We recover and conserve5 it in memory and imagination only, and as we recover it more and more completely and relate it more and more successfully, we know and understand it better. Plato is dead, and not one feature, circumstance, or action of his life can now be changed. He lives only in the memory of man; and because he lives there and stimulates7 the imagination, there is born a Plato of the imagination. There are thus two Platos, the one real and the other historical. The one lived and died long ago; the other still lives in human history. The real Plato has produced the historical Plato and affords a check upon historians in their representation of him. That representation may approach progressively nearer to what the real Plato was like, but it can never be the man who has passed away. History would be thus a branch of human knowledge, and grow with the growth of knowledge, while its objects remain unchanged. That is why history has constantly to be rewritten. Furthermore, in the rewriting, new types of history appear with new or altered emphases. The moral and religious type is supplemented by the political, and the political by the economic and social. For with the growth[Pg 30] of knowledge the past looks different to us and we discover that what appeared once adequate has to be revised.
We may admit, therefore, that history, whatever else it may be, is at any rate a kind of human knowledge. Like all knowledge it leads us to recognize that there is a distinction between knowledge itself and its objects, and that the progressive character of knowledge indicates an approximation to an adequate representation of the objects and not changes in their own character. This distinction in its application to history is evidently not a distinction between literature and its subject-matter. For the past, if we now take the past to be the proper subject-matter of written history, appears to have a twofold character. It is all that has happened precisely8 as it happened, and it is all that is remembered and known, precisely as it is remembered and known. There are, we may say, a real past and an historical past. The latter never is the former, but always a progressively more adequate representation of the former.
Now this distinction between the real past and the historical past may be fruitful. It may also be treacherous9, for the terms in which it is expressed are treacherous terms. For it is very[Pg 31] easy to claim that the real past is after all only the historical past, because the past itself being dead and gone is now real only as it is preserved in history. Yet properly understood, the distinction is essential to any philosophical10 comprehension of what history is. It points out that history is not the past, but is its recovery and conservation. Events begin and end; men are born and die; events and men disappear into the past in a manner and an order which are unalterable. But it is not their disappearance11 which constitutes their existence in time a history. Their historical existence is a kind of continuing life. It may be that it continues only in human knowledge, but, even so, it clearly illustrates13 the nature of history as a process in time. In other words the life of knowledge, of memory and imagination, is itself a continual recording14 of what has happened, a continual understanding of it, and a continual putting of it in a new and enlarged perspective. Here, too, within the narrow limits of man's perceiving and comprehending life to which we have now restricted history, events begin and end, men are born and die, and events and men disappear into the past in a manner and an order which are unalterable. Yet even as they disappear never[Pg 32] to return in the precise and identical manner of their first existence, they are conserved15, and continue the process of dying as occurrences in order to live as a history. Yesterday as yesterday is gone forever. Its opportunities are over and its incidents dead. As an historical yesterday it lives as material for to-day's employment. It becomes an experience to profit by, a mistake to remedy, or a success to enjoy. History is thus the great destroyer and the great preserver. We must speak of it in apparent paradoxes16. The child becomes a man only by ceasing to be a child; Plato becomes an historical figure only by dying; whatever happens is conserved only by being first destroyed.
But the conservation of what happens is obviously not a perpetuation17. History is not the staying of events, for time forbids that they stay. The conservation is rather a utilization18, a kind of employment or working over of material. Through it discriminations and selections are made and connections discovered; the moving panorama19 is converted into an order of events which can be understood, because consequences are seen in the light of their antecedents and antecedents are seen in the light of the consequences to which they lead. There is thus a[Pg 33] genuine incorporation20 of what has happened into what does happen, of yesterday into to-day, so that yesterday becomes a vital part of to-day and finds its enlargement and fulfilment there. We can thus write our own biographies. It is possible for us to discover what mistakes we have made and what ends we have attained21. Our history appears thus to be a utilization of material, a realization23 of ends, a movement with purpose in it. Selection is characteristic of it very profoundly. Other histories, of other men, of times, of peoples, of institutions, we write in the same way because in the same way we discover and understand what has happened in their case. Such a destroying, conserving24, utilizing25, selective, and purposeful movement in time, history appears to be when we restrict it to the domain26 of human knowledge.
It seems, however, idle so to restrict it. For other things besides our knowledge grow—animals and plants, and the stars even. They, too, have a history, and it may be that their history, being also an affair in time, is not unlike in character to our own growth in knowledge. Or perhaps it were even better to say that both they and our knowledge illustrate12 equally what history is, discovering time itself to be the great[Pg 34] historian. All time-processes, that is, appear to be, when we attentively27 consider them, processes which supplement, complete, or transform what has gone before. They are active conservations and utilizations of the past as material. They save what has happened from being utterly28 destroyed, and, in saving it, complete and develop it. Time is, thus, constantly rounding out things, so to speak, or bringing them to some end or fulfilment. That is why we call its movement purposeful.
Yet there have been philosophies which have tried to make of time a magical device by which man might represent to himself in succession that which in itself is never in succession. They picture his journey through life as a journey through space where all that he sees, one thing after another, comes successively into view like the houses on a street along which he may walk. But as the houses do not exist in succession, neither do the facts he discovers. They, too, come into view as he moves along. These philosophies, consequently, would have us think of a world in itself, absolute and complete, to which nothing can be added and from which nothing can be subtracted. It is somehow fixed and finished now; but our human experience,[Pg 35] being incomplete and unfinished, gives to it the appearance of a process in time and discloses to us what it would be like if all its factors and the laws which hold them in perfect equilibrium30 were experienced in succession. History would thus be a kind of temporal revelation of the absolute and we should read it as we read a book, from cover to cover, discovering page by page a story which is itself finished when we begin.
Or philosophy, when it has not conceived the world to be thus finished and complete in itself and only appearing to us as a temporal revelation, has often thought of movements in time as only the results of preceding movements. Whatever happens is thus conceived to be the effect of what has already happened, rather than the active conservation and working over of what has already happened. The past is made the cause and producer of the present, so that the state of the world at any moment is only the result or outcome of what it was in the preceding moment. To-day is thought to be the effect of yesterday and the cause of to-morrow, and is thus but a transition from one day to another. Time-processes are thus robbed of any genuine activity or productivity, and time itself[Pg 36] is made to be nothing but the sequential order in which events occur. Purpose, conservation, utilization, and all that active supplementing and working over of the past on which we have dwelt, become illusions when applied to the world at large. They represent our way of conceiving things, but not nature's way of doing things.
But these philosophies, as Professor Bergson especially among recent philosophers has pointed31 out,[4] gain whatever force they have principally from the fact that they think of time in terms of space. They picture it as a line already drawn32, when they should picture it as a line in the process of being drawn. As already drawn, the line has a beginning, an end, and consequently, a middle point. Let us call the middle point the present. All the line to the left of that point we will call the past and all to the right of it the future. We thus behold33 time spatially34 with all its parts coexistent as the points on the line. Events are then conceived to move from the past through the present into the future, just[Pg 37] as a pencil point may pass from the beginning of the line through its middle point to the end. But, unlike the pencil point, they can not go backward. This fact gives us a characteristic by which we may distinguish time from space even if we have represented time spatially. The spatial35 order is reversible, the temporal is not. Time is like a line on which you can go forward, but on which you can not go backward. But you can go forward. Everything goes from the past to the future. The present is but the transition point of their going.
There are, undoubtedly36, advantages in thinking of time in this spatial way. Thereby37 we are able to make calendars and have a science of mechanics. It affords a basis for many successful predictions. But, quite evidently, time is neither such a line nor anything like it. Nothing whatever goes from the past through the present into the future. We can not make such a statement intelligible38. For "to go" from the past to the future is not like going from New York to Boston. Boston is already there to go to, but the future is not anywhere to go to. And New York is there to leave, but the past is not anywhere to leave. What then is this mysterious "going" if its starting-point and its end are[Pg 38] both non-existent now? Clearly it is a "going" only in a metaphorical39 sense. We call it a "going" because we can so represent it by dates and places. We can say that here we have been going from Friday through Saturday to Sunday. But it is quite clear that to-day is neither past nor future, that it is neither yesterday nor to-morrow, and that if we go anywhere we must start to-day. When Sunday comes, Saturday will be yesterday. But note now the strange situation into which we have fallen—only in the future is this day ever in the past! And that is true of every day in the world's history. It becomes a past day only in its own future.
Clearly then time is not like a line already drawn. It is more like a line in the drawing. You take the pencil and the line is left behind it as the pencil moves. New points are being constantly added to what has gone before. The line is being manufactured. Let us call so much of it as has now been drawn the past and that which has not yet been drawn the future. It is clear then that the present is not the middle point of the line nor any point whatever upon it, for all of the line that has been drawn belongs to the past and all the rest of it to the future. Its past has already been done; its future is not[Pg 39] yet done, but only possible. Furthermore, it is clear that no point moves from the past into the future. Such a movement is unintelligible40. If there is any movement of points at all, it is a movement into the past. That is, the line, instead of growing into the future, grows into the past—continually more and more of it is drawn. For remember that the future of the line is not the place on the paper or in the air which by and by the line may occupy. Its future is a genuine future, a possibility as yet nowhere realized. It is the part of the line which always will be, but never is; or, better, it is that part of the line which will have a place and a date if the line continues to be drawn. The movement of time is thus not a movement from the past to the future, but from the possible to the actual, from what may be to what has been. The present is not the vanishing point between past and future; it is not, so to speak, in the same line or dimension with them. It is something quite different. It is all that we mean by activity or eventuality. It is the concrete, definite, and effective transforming of the possible into the actual. It is the drawing of the line, but in no sense is it a part or point of the line itself.
There are, doubtless, difficulties in thinking[Pg 40] of time in this way, for it is not entirely41 free from spatial reminiscences. But it serves to point out that past, present, and future are not like parts of a whole into which an absolute or complete time is divided. They are more like derivatives42 of the time process itself in the concrete instances of its activity. They are what every growing or changing thing involves, whether it be the knowledge of man or the crust of the earth, for everything that grows or changes manufactures a past by realizing a future. It leaves behind it the record of what it has done conserved by memory or by nature, and in leaving that record behind constantly enlarges or transforms it. The growth moves in a manner and an order which when once performed are unalterable, but there is growth none the less. Since time is like this, it seems evidently unintelligible to restrict it and history to human experience and make the world in itself absolute. It would be better to say that it is history in the large sense applicable to the world itself that makes human experience possible. Yet it would be more advisable not to make such a distinction at all, but to recognize that human experience is one kind of history, namely, history conscious of itself, the time process deliberately43 at work.
[Pg 41]
Now it is evident that history in this latter sense is purposive and selective. That which has happened is not remembered as a whole or understood as a whole. Not only are details forgotten or neglected, but things and events otherwise important are omitted for the sake of securing emphasis and distinction among the things remembered. Herodotus spoke44 of "wonderful deeds" and others following this example have regarded history as concerned only with great men and great events. It is true that the little men and the little events tend to disappear, but we should remember that it is the selective character of history which makes them little. Speaking absolutely, we may say that no item, however apparently45 insignificant46, is really insignificant in the historical development of any people or any institution, for in some measure every item is material to that development. But all are not equally material. The absence of any one of them might undoubtedly have changed the whole history, but given the presence of them all, some are of greater significance than others.
The history of the English people may be regarded as a development of personal liberty. It is doubtless more than that, but it is that.[Pg 42] As such a development, it is evident that there are many things which an historian of personal liberty will disregard in order that the particular movement he is studying may be emphasized and distinguished47. It will be that particular movement which will determine for him what is great and what little. So it comes about that histories are diversified48 even when they are histories of the same thing. There are many histories of England which differ from one another not only in accuracy, philosophical grasp, and brilliancy, but also in the purpose they discover England to be fulfilling. By purpose here is not meant a predestined end which England is bound to reach, but the fact that her history can be construed49 as a development of a specific kind. In other words her past can be understood only when it is seen to be relevant to some particular career which has its termination in her existing institutions. Her past has contributed through time to definite results which are now apparent. The things that have happened have not all contributed to these results in the same measure. Some have contributed more, some less. What is true in this illustration appears to be true generally. Every history is a particular career in the [Pg 43]development of which some facts, persons, and events have been more significant than others, so that the termination of the career at any time is like an end that has been reached or a consequence to which its antecedents are peculiarly appropriate. That is the sense in which history is purposeful and selective.
The selection is twofold. First, there is selection of the type of career, and secondly52, there is selection of the items especially relevant to its progress. We may have the military, the political, the social, the industrial, the economic, or the religious history of England, for instance, and although these histories will overlap53 and involve one another, each of them will exhibit a career which is peculiar51 and distinct from its fellows. When reading the industrial history we shall not be reading the religious history. In the one we shall find circumstances and events recorded which we do not find in the other, because all circumstances and events do not have significance equally for the development of industry and religion. Historical selection is, therefore, twofold,—the selection of a career to be depicted54 and of events and circumstances peculiarly relevant to that career.
Is this selection, we may ask, only a device[Pg 44] on the historian's part to facilitate our comprehension, or is it a genuine characteristic of the time process itself? Does the historian read purpose into history or does he find it there? It may assist in answering such questions to observe that if selection is a device of the historian, it is one to which he is compelled. Without it history is unintelligible. Unless we understand events and circumstances as contributing to a definite result and contributing in different measures, we do not understand them at all. The Magna Charta, the British Constitution, the Tower of London, the River Thames, the mines of Wales, the plays of Shakespeare—all these things and things like them are for us quite unintelligible if they illuminate55 no career or illustrate no specific movements to which they have particularly contributed. Selection is, consequently, not a device which the historian has invented; it is imposed upon him by his own purpose to preserve the memory and promote the understanding of what has happened. The procedure of the historian is not arbitrary, but necessary. It is imposed upon him by the character of the facts with which he deals. These facts are movements from the possible to the actual and are helped and hindered[Pg 45] by other such movements. An historical fact is not only spread out in space and exists equally with all its contemporaries at an assignable place in reference to them, it also persists in time, comes before and after other persisting facts, and persists along with others in a continuance equal to, or more or less than, theirs. In a figure we may say, facts march on in time, but not all at the same speed or with the same endurance; they help or impede56 one another's movement; they do not all reach the goal; some of them turn out to be leaders, others followers57; their careers overlap and interfere58; so that the result is a failure for some and a success for others. The march is their history.
This is figure, but it looks like the fact. Simple illustrations may enforce it. The seeds which we buy and sow in the spring are not simply so many ounces of chemical substances. They are also so many possible histories or careers in time, so many days of growth, so much promise of fruit or flower. Each seed has its own peculiar history with its own peculiar career. The seeds are planted. Then in the course of time, soil and moisture and atmosphere and food operate in unequal ways in the development of each career. Each is furthered or[Pg 46] hindered as events fall out. Some careers are cut short, others prosper59. Everywhere there is selection. Everywhere there is adaptation of means to ends. The history of the garden can be written because there is a history there to write.
Such an illustration can be generalized. Our world is indubitably a world in time. That means much more than the fact that its events can be placed in accordance with a map or dated in accordance with a calendar. It means that they are events in genuine careers, each with its own particular character and its own possibility of a future, like the seeds in the garden. Things with histories have not only structures in space and are, accordingly, related geometrically to one another; they have not only chemical structures and are thus analyzable into component60 parts; they have also structures in time. They are not now what they will be, but what they will be is always continuous with what they are, so that we must think of them stretched out, so to speak, in time as well as in space, or as being so many moments as well as so much volume. What they become, however, depends not only on their own time structures, but also on their interplay with one[Pg 47] another. They are helped and hindered in their development. The results reached at any time are such as complete those which have gone before, for each career is the producer, but not the product of its past.
It seems clear, therefore, that there is purpose in history. But "purpose" is a troublesome word. It connotes design, intention, foresight61, as well as the converging62 of means upon a specific end. Only in the latter sense is it here used, but with this addition: the end is to be conceived not in terms of any goal ultimately reached, but in terms of the career of which it is the termination; and in this career, the present is continually adding to and completing the past. The growing seeds end each in its own specific flower or fruit. They are each of its own kind and named accordingly. It is only because each of them has its specific structure in time that their growth presents that convergence of means toward an end by which we distinguish them and for which we value them. In purpose construed in this way there is evidently no need of design or intention or foresight. In making a garden there is such need. The purposes of nature may be deliberately employed to attain22 the purposes of men. But apart from beings[Pg 48] who foresee and plan there appears to be no evidence of intention in the world. When we speak of nature's designs, we speak figuratively, and impute64 to her rational and deliberate powers. But we can not clearly affirm that the rain falls in order that the garden may be watered, or that the eye was framed in order that we might see. The evidence for design of that character has been proved inadequate65 again and again with every careful examination of it. To say, therefore, that nature is full of purpose does not mean that nature has been framed in accordance with some preconceived plan, but rather that nature is discovered to be an historical process, the conversion66 of the possible into the actual in such a way that there is conserved a progressive record of that conversion.
From the selective character of history it follows that a single complete history of anything is impossible—certainly a single complete history of the world at large. History is pluralistic. This conclusion might be reached as others have already been reached by pointing out how it follows from the purpose of writing history, and how this purpose indicates the character of movements in time. Indeed this[Pg 49] has already been done in pointing out that the history of England is its many histories and the history of a garden the history of its many seeds. Always there is a particular career and particular incidents appropriate to it. Any career may be as comprehensive as desired, but the more inclusive it is the more restricted it becomes. The history of Milton contains details which the history of English literature will omit; and the history of the cosmos67 shrinks to nothing when we try to write it. The only universal history is the exposition of what history itself is, the time process stripped of all its variety and specific interests. Consequently, a single purpose is not discoverable; there are many purposes. When we try to reduce them all to some show of singleness we again do no more than try to tell what a temporal order is like. It is metaphysics and not history we are writing.
To affirm that history is pluralistic is, however, only to reaffirm the selective character of history generally. A history of the world in order to be single, definite, and coherent, must exhibit a single, definite, and coherent purpose or time process. That means, of course, that it is distinguished from other purposes equally single, definite, and coherent. There are thus many[Pg 50] histories of the world distinguished from one another by the incidence of choice or emphasis. The flower in the crannied wall with its history fully6 recorded and understood would, consequently, illustrate the universe. All that has ever happened might be interpreted in illumination of its career. Yet it would be absurd to maintain that either nature or Tennyson intended that the little flower should be exclusively illustrative. The wall would do as well, or its crannies, or the poet. Nature exhibits no preference either in the choice of a history or in the extent of its comprehensiveness. Man may be thought to be, and man is, an incident in the universe, and the universe may be thought to be, and the universe is, the theater of man's career.
The same principle may be illustrated68 from human history exclusively. We who are of European ancestry69 and largely Anglo-Saxon by inheritance are pleased to write history as the development of our own civilization with its institutions, customs, and laws; and we regard China and Japan, for example, as incidental and contributory to our own continuation in time. Because our heritage is Christian70 we date all events from the birth of Christ. Yet we gain[Pg 51] some wisdom by pausing to reflect how our procedure might impress an enlightened historian from China or Japan. Would he begin with the cradle of European civilization, pass through Greece and Rome, and then from Europe to America, remarking that in 1852 A.D. Commodore Perry opened Japan to the world? Surely he would begin otherwise, and not unlike ourselves would construe50 the history of the world in a manner relevant to the progress of his own civilization. Europe and America and Christianity would contribute to that development, but would not constitute its essential or distinctively71 significant factors. The historian is himself an historical fact indicating a selection, a distinction, and an emphasis in the course of time. His history is naturally colored by that fact. Other histories he can write only with an effort at detachment from his own career. He must forget himself if he would understand others; but he must understand himself first, if he is successfully to forget what he is. He must know what history is, recognize its pluralistic character, and try to do it justice.
To do justice to the pluralistic character of history is not, however, simply to write other histories than one's own with commendable[Pg 52] impartiality72. It is also to be keenly alive to the philosophical implications of this pluralism. The most significant of them is doubtless this: since philosophically74 considered history is a thing not written, but evolved and acted, to no one history can absolute superiority or preference be assigned. Absolutely considered the history of man can not claim pre?minence over the history of the stars. He is no more the darling of the universe than is the remotest nebula75. It is just as intelligible and just as true to say that man exists as an illustration of stellar evolution as to say that the sun exists to divide light from darkness for the good of man. Absolutely considered the cosmos is impartial73 to its many histories. But even that is not well said, for it implies that the cosmos might be partial if it chose. We should rather say that there is no considering of history absolutely at all. For history is just the denial of absolute considerations. It is the affirmation of relative considerations, of considerations which are relative to a selected career. There is no other kind of history possible.
The recognition of this fact does not, however, imply the futility76 of all history. It does not imply that any history is good enough for men[Pg 53] since all histories are good enough for the cosmos. So to conclude is to disregard completely the implications of pluralism. If no history can claim absolute distinction, all histories are distinguished, nevertheless, from one another. If no history can claim pre?minence over any other, it is true also that none can be robbed by any other of its own distinction and character. The fact that the morning stars do not sing together is not the universe's estimate of the value of poetry. The fact that the rain falls equally upon the just and the unjust is evidence neither of the impartial dispensations of deity77 nor of the equal issue of vice29 and virtue78. Each event in its own history and illustrative of its own career is the law.
Yet men have been prone79 to write their own history as if it were something else than a human enterprise, as if it were something else than the history of humanity. Those who seek to read their destiny from the constellations80 ascendant at their birth are generally called superstitious81; but those who seek to read it from the constitution of matter, or from the mechanism82 of the physical world, or from the composition of chemical substances, although no less superstitious, are too frequently called scientists. But "dust thou art and unto dust thou shalt[Pg 54] return" is an essential truth only about the history of dust; it is only an incidental truth about the history of man. One learns nothing peculiarly characteristic of humanity from it. It affords no measure of the appreciation83 of poetry, of the constitution of a state, or of the passion for happiness. Human history is human history only. The hopes and fears, the aspirations84, the wisdom and the folly86 of man are to be understood only in the light of his career. They are to be understood in terms of that into which they may and do eventuate for him, by the way in which they are incorporated into his past to make it more fully remembered and more adequately understood, and by the way they are used for his future to make his past more satisfactory to remember and more satisfying to understand.
Yet some there are who stop worshipping the stars when they discover that the stars neither ask for worship nor respond to it, and who dismiss reverence87 and piety88 when they discover that a god did not create the world. Perhaps they should not worship the stars nor believe in God, but neither astronomy nor geology affords good reasons for putting an end to human reverence and faith. If the stars have not begged man to[Pg 55] worship them, he has begged them to be an inspiration to a steadfast89 purpose. It is in his history, not in theirs, that they have been divine. How stupid of him therefore, and how traitorous90 to his own history, if he shames his capacity for reverence, when once he has found that the stars have a different history from his own.
The inevitable91 failure of astronomy and geology to afford man gods suitable for his worship is not a recommendation that he should vigorously embrace the superstitions92 of his ancestors. To counsel that would be an infamy93 equal to that which has just been condemned94. The counsel is rather that what is not human should not be taken as the standard and measure of what is human. Human history can not be wholly resolved into physical processes nor the enterprises of men be construed solely96 as the by-product97 of material forces. Such resolution of it appears to be unwarranted in view of the conclusions to which a consideration of what history is, leads. The obverse error has long since been sufficiently98 condemned. We have been warned often enough that water does not seek its own level or nature abhor99 a vacuum. Even literary criticism warns us against the pathetic fallacy. But in refusing to [Pg 56]anthropomorphize matter, we ought not to be led to materialize man. We should rather be led to recognize that the reasons which condemn95 anthropomorphic science are precisely the reasons which commend humanistic philosophy. It is just because history is pluralistic that it is unpardonable to confound different histories with one another. So we may conclude that the pluralism of history which makes all histories, when absolutely considered, of equal rank and of indifferent importance, does not rob them, therefore, of their specific characters, nor make human history a presumptuous100 enterprise for them that write it not in the language of nature, but in the language of man.
This conclusion needs greater refinement101 of statement if it is to be freed from ambiguity102. For the distinction between nature and man is an artifice103. It is not a distinction which philosophy can ultimately justify104. Undoubtedly man is a part or instance of nature, governed by nature's laws and intimately involved in her processes. But he is so governed and involved not as matter without imagination, but as a being whose distinction is the historical exercise of his intelligence. Nature is not what she would be without him and that is why his [Pg 57]history can never be remembered or understood if he is forgotten. He can not be taken out of nature and nature be then called upon to explain him. As a part or instance of nature man is to be remembered and understood, but as the part or instance which he himself is, and not another. His history, consequently, can never be adequately written solely in terms of physics or chemistry, or even of biology; it must be written also in terms of aspiration85.
All time processes are histories, but man only is the writer of them, so that historical comprehension becomes the significant trait of human history. To live in the light of a past remembered and understood is to live, not the life of instinct and emotion, but the life of intelligence. It is to see how means converge63 upon ends, and so to discover means for the attainment105 of ends desired. Human history becomes thus the record of human progress. From it we may learn how that progress is to be defined and so discover the purpose of man in history. For him the study of his own history is his congenial task to which all his knowledge of other histories is contributory; and for him the conscious, reflective, and intelligent living of his own history is his congenial purpose.
点击收听单词发音
1 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 conserve | |
vt.保存,保护,节约,节省,守恒,不灭 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 stimulates | |
v.刺激( stimulate的第三人称单数 );激励;使兴奋;起兴奋作用,起刺激作用,起促进作用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 treacherous | |
adj.不可靠的,有暗藏的危险的;adj.背叛的,背信弃义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 disappearance | |
n.消失,消散,失踪 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 illustrate | |
v.举例说明,阐明;图解,加插图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 illustrates | |
给…加插图( illustrate的第三人称单数 ); 说明; 表明; (用示例、图画等)说明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 recording | |
n.录音,记录 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 conserved | |
v.保护,保藏,保存( conserve的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 paradoxes | |
n.似非而是的隽语,看似矛盾而实际却可能正确的说法( paradox的名词复数 );用于语言文学中的上述隽语;有矛盾特点的人[事物,情况] | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 perpetuation | |
n.永存,不朽 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 utilization | |
n.利用,效用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 panorama | |
n.全景,全景画,全景摄影,全景照片[装置] | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 incorporation | |
n.设立,合并,法人组织 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 realization | |
n.实现;认识到,深刻了解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 conserving | |
v.保护,保藏,保存( conserve的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 utilizing | |
v.利用,使用( utilize的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 domain | |
n.(活动等)领域,范围;领地,势力范围 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 attentively | |
adv.聚精会神地;周到地;谛;凝神 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 utterly | |
adv.完全地,绝对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 equilibrium | |
n.平衡,均衡,相称,均势,平静 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 pointed | |
adj.尖的,直截了当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 behold | |
v.看,注视,看到 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 spatially | |
空间地,存在于空间地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 spatial | |
adj.空间的,占据空间的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 undoubtedly | |
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 intelligible | |
adj.可理解的,明白易懂的,清楚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 metaphorical | |
a.隐喻的,比喻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 unintelligible | |
adj.无法了解的,难解的,莫明其妙的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 derivatives | |
n.衍生性金融商品;派生物,引出物( derivative的名词复数 );导数 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 deliberately | |
adv.审慎地;蓄意地;故意地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 spoke | |
n.(车轮的)辐条;轮辐;破坏某人的计划;阻挠某人的行动 v.讲,谈(speak的过去式);说;演说;从某种观点来说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 apparently | |
adv.显然地;表面上,似乎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 insignificant | |
adj.无关紧要的,可忽略的,无意义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 diversified | |
adj.多样化的,多种经营的v.使多样化,多样化( diversify的过去式和过去分词 );进入新的商业领域 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 construed | |
v.解释(陈述、行为等)( construe的过去式和过去分词 );翻译,作句法分析 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 construe | |
v.翻译,解释 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 secondly | |
adv.第二,其次 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 overlap | |
v.重叠,与…交叠;n.重叠 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 depicted | |
描绘,描画( depict的过去式和过去分词 ); 描述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 illuminate | |
vt.照亮,照明;用灯光装饰;说明,阐释 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 impede | |
v.妨碍,阻碍,阻止 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 followers | |
追随者( follower的名词复数 ); 用户; 契据的附面; 从动件 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 interfere | |
v.(in)干涉,干预;(with)妨碍,打扰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 prosper | |
v.成功,兴隆,昌盛;使成功,使昌隆,繁荣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 component | |
n.组成部分,成分,元件;adj.组成的,合成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 foresight | |
n.先见之明,深谋远虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 converging | |
adj.收敛[缩]的,会聚的,趋同的v.(线条、运动的物体等)会于一点( converge的现在分词 );(趋于)相似或相同;人或车辆汇集;聚集 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 converge | |
vi.会合;聚集,集中;(思想、观点等)趋近 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 impute | |
v.归咎于 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 inadequate | |
adj.(for,to)不充足的,不适当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 conversion | |
n.转化,转换,转变 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 cosmos | |
n.宇宙;秩序,和谐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 illustrated | |
adj. 有插图的,列举的 动词illustrate的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 ancestry | |
n.祖先,家世 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 Christian | |
adj.基督教徒的;n.基督教徒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 distinctively | |
adv.特殊地,区别地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 impartiality | |
n. 公平, 无私, 不偏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 impartial | |
adj.(in,to)公正的,无偏见的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 philosophically | |
adv.哲学上;富有哲理性地;贤明地;冷静地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 nebula | |
n.星云,喷雾剂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 futility | |
n.无用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 deity | |
n.神,神性;被奉若神明的人(或物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 prone | |
adj.(to)易于…的,很可能…的;俯卧的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 constellations | |
n.星座( constellation的名词复数 );一群杰出人物;一系列(相关的想法、事物);一群(相关的人) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 superstitious | |
adj.迷信的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 mechanism | |
n.机械装置;机构,结构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 appreciation | |
n.评价;欣赏;感谢;领会,理解;价格上涨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 aspirations | |
强烈的愿望( aspiration的名词复数 ); 志向; 发送气音; 发 h 音 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 aspiration | |
n.志向,志趣抱负;渴望;(语)送气音;吸出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 folly | |
n.愚笨,愚蠢,蠢事,蠢行,傻话 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 reverence | |
n.敬畏,尊敬,尊严;Reverence:对某些基督教神职人员的尊称;v.尊敬,敬畏,崇敬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 piety | |
n.虔诚,虔敬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 steadfast | |
adj.固定的,不变的,不动摇的;忠实的;坚贞不移的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 traitorous | |
adj. 叛国的, 不忠的, 背信弃义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 inevitable | |
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 superstitions | |
迷信,迷信行为( superstition的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 infamy | |
n.声名狼藉,出丑,恶行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 condemned | |
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 condemn | |
vt.谴责,指责;宣判(罪犯),判刑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 by-product | |
n.副产品,附带产生的结果 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 abhor | |
v.憎恶;痛恨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 presumptuous | |
adj.胆大妄为的,放肆的,冒昧的,冒失的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 refinement | |
n.文雅;高尚;精美;精制;精炼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 ambiguity | |
n.模棱两可;意义不明确 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 artifice | |
n.妙计,高明的手段;狡诈,诡计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 justify | |
vt.证明…正当(或有理),为…辩护 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 attainment | |
n.达到,到达;[常pl.]成就,造诣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |