The duty of the parents, or failing them of the community, The duty of parents to provide for offspring now well recognised in regard to the provision of material necessities for offspring is now sufficiently6 recognised, so that there is little need to insist upon it here. We may perhaps only suggest in passing that the profound and complex nature of the satisfactions which parents have in their children, and which we had occasion to refer to in Chapter XIV, would very possibly make the communistic rearing of children on a large scale as unsatisfying and inadequate7 from the point of view of the parents as it would probably be from that of the children themselves.
The duty of the parents or their substitutes in the direction The necessity for the gradual loosening of the dependence tie is however not fully8 realised of gradually weaning the child from his initial condition of dependence has however received less adequate recognition nor has the difficult and delicate nature of this duty been sufficiently appreciated. On the economic and social sides indeed it is admitted that it is incumbent9 upon parents to[231] provide their children with the means of earning their living and of taking their place generally among their social equals; though with regard to girls the views as to what was necessary as regards education for these purposes has, up till comparatively recently, often been lamentably10 narrow. In this country there is even now in many quarters a failure to realise the full nature of parental11 responsibilities with regard to daughters; much less financial provision being frequently made in their case, both for higher and professional education and for the expenses incidental to marriage, than in the case of sons; lack of adequate provision in these respects inevitably12 tending of course to produce an undue13 degree of dependence—economical and moral—on the parents.
If, on the economic side, the duty of weaning children especially as regards the psychological aspect of this tie from their primitive14 dependence on the family is thus not yet always fully recognised, the recognition of the corresponding duties on the psychological side is still less complete. Parents are often unwilling15 to abandon the jurisdiction16 and control which they have been accustomed to exercise over their children and which may have become very pleasant to them, both as providing an agreeable source of interest and as ministering to their sense of power. Often too in the beginning it may be easier for them to help their children than to let the latter learn to help themselves. Not infrequently also they are directly or indirectly17 encouraged in this course by the children themselves, who, out of laziness or failure in initiative, prefer that their lives should be regulated by their parents rather than that they should make the effort and take on the responsibility of regulating it themselves. Sometimes, moreover, parents are unwilling to relinquish19 the management of their childrens' lives for fear of the disasters that may overtake these latter through ignorance and inexperience; or again because of an exaggerated tenderness which makes them loth to abandon those manifestations20 of affection which parental assistance may imply. It must be understood however that none of these motives—powerful though some of them may be—provide an adequate excuse for the omission21 to carry out the weaning process, which, as we have seen, is of such vast importance for the development of the full capacities of the individual. It can scarcely be too frequently emphasised that[232] parents who bring their children up without regard to the necessity of this emancipation22 are guilty of a very serious neglect of their childrens' welfare[270].
[233]
The danger is perhaps greatest in the case of strong The danger is greatest in the case of parents of strong personality willed, self-assertive and energetic parents, who in any case, as we have seen, are likely to exert a powerful influence over their children, and who, by an undue insistence23 on the authority which they possess, may easily cripple all initiative on the part of these latter. In parents who themselves are weak and averse24 from serious effort there is though there may be difficulties also in the case of weak parents naturally less likelihood of this occurring: in such cases the danger lies more frequently in the direction of their devoting too little time, trouble or guidance to their children: or else in their adoption25 of a changeable and inconsistent attitude—petting, indulging, spoiling and bribing26 one minute, bullying27, nagging28 and punishing the next; being now overstrict, now easy-going.
Here, as in the case of the love-weaning, it is difficult or Necessity of parental readjustment impossible for parents to carry out satisfactorily the steps necessary for the gradual emancipation of their children, except in so far as they are able to make a corresponding readjustment of their own emotions and tendencies. New interests and occupations must gradually take the place of those that formerly29 centred round the children; otherwise there is likely to arise a blank in the affective life, which may lead to much unhappiness and even to neurosis.
In considering the question of the emancipation of children Too prolonged parental jurisdiction is a cause of filio-parental hatred30 in later life from the authority and influence of their parents, it is well to bear in mind also that it is the exercise of this authority and influence which affords the principal occasion for the development or continuance of the hatred of children towards their parents in adolescent or adult life. The arousal of some hatred in the early years of childhood may indeed be inevitable31. Its continuance into later life, with all the misery32 that this is apt to entail33, may probably in nearly every case be avoided, provided that the stage of infantile jealousy34 has been successfully[234] surmounted35 and that the child is endowed with something approaching the usual degree of amenability36 and sympathy with the point of view and susceptibilities of others; the rest is very largely a matter of the careful relaxation37 of parental authority and of the granting of reasonable and ever increasing amounts of liberty and of opportunity for self-guidance and self-control.
What we have here said as regards the necessity for the The dependence of children upon parent-substitutes must also be gradually reduced gradual relaxation of parental control applies of course not only to the parents themselves but to their substitutes—guardians, nurses, teachers and others who are placed in similar positions of trust and authority. There is indeed reason to believe that in these quarters the necessity of emancipation is often more in need of emphasis than among actual parents. Particularly is this the case with regard to certain institutions, where children would seem to be brought up with but little freedom or opportunity to learn the nature and conditions of autonomy or to adapt themselves to the varied38 circumstances of the outer world. In many of our schools also there is to some extent a lack of proper understanding or application of the principles which demand the gradual relaxation of parental and quasi-parental authority. Though here, as a rule, the evil is in practice less serious than it would at first appear to be; the granting of autonomy and the cultivation39 of responsibility and self-control in some directions usually compensating40 in large measure for the petty and foolish restrictions41 to which adolescent boys and girls, or even fully grown young men and women, are subjected in some of our larger and better known educational establishments.
These last considerations point the way to certain wider The ethics42 of the family must however be brought into connection with wider social questions issues that are connected with the ethics of the family—issues with which we have already been brought face to face in Chapters XIII and XIV, and which we need therefore only refer to here by way of recapitulation. We have seen in these chapters that there exists a correlation43 between certain aspects or stages of development of the family on the one hand and certain forms of social or ethical44 institutions or organizations—particularly in the sphere of education, politics and religion—upon the other. Inasmuch as the attitude of the individual towards his teacher, his social or political superior, or his God, is to a very considerable extent derived45 from, and dependent[235] on, that of the child towards his parent (the former attitude being a displacement46 of the latter), it is obvious that moral considerations and decisions with regard to the relationship of parent and child cannot altogether be divorced from the wider questions involved in the relations of the individual to his religious, social, and educational environment.
Thus it would be, in the main, a foolish and useless proceeding47 to urge, as we have done, the desirability of a Our ethical conclusions in the two cases must harmonise with one another gradual emancipation of the growing child from the controlling and protecting influences of the parents, unless we are at the same time willing to permit a corresponding growth of autonomy in school and college. Again, if we were right in assuming a connection, on the one hand between a highly developed patria potestas and a relatively48 stable and unprogressive political condition, and on the other between the relaxation of parental authority and a state of rapid political development and loosening of governmental authority, then it would (in the absence of any counteracting49 influence) be absurd to demand the complete emancipation of the individual from his family, if at the same time we desired to uphold autocracy50 in government or to increase the stability of political and social forms. Nor, once more, would the encouragement of children to become independent of their fathers be logically compatible with the maintenance of a religion of the Judaic type, in which the severe and all-powerful Father-God is but a displacement of an earthly father whose stem authority is unquestioned within the bounds of his own family. It must be realised that our attitude in the one case must be brought into harmony with our views in the other. Our ultimate conclusions as to what is desirable within the family must be arrived at only after due consideration of their wider outside bearings; and again, our opinions on these wider issues may profitably be reviewed in the light of the knowledge that is gained by a biological and psychological study of the family.
In the present pages we have followed in the main the The extent of this harmony latter course. Nevertheless it would appear that on the whole the conclusions we have arrived at by this method are not in any way seriously incompatible51 with the general tendencies of contemporary thought. While recognising the necessity and desirability of the family influences in early life, we have for[236] the most part demanded emancipation of the individual from any such growth and retention52 of these influences as would be liable to hamper53 or delay his personal development. This is well in harmony with the tendencies which are manifested nowadays towards freedom in education, with the analogous54 tendencies aiming at the overthrow55 of autocracy and the establishment of democracy in politics and with the growing toleration and increasing abandonment of the Judaic attitude in religion.
In education there would seem to be almost complete in education agreement between the implications of our own conclusions and all the more modern and progressive tendencies in discipline and teaching; it is only with the antiquated56 remains57 of systems that are now universally condemned58 by all reformers that there remain any serious elements of conflict.
In religion the agreement is also very considerable, though in religion perhaps less thoroughgoing; there are perhaps many who would still retain the notion of a quasi-anthropomorphic Father-God as an extra-mental reality, even though the purely59 mental origin of such a God has become apparent.
It is in politics however that such discrepancy60 as there in politics exists is perhaps most apparent. Although the primitive political father—the autocrat—would seem to be rapidly disappearing, it is fairly clear that there exists a tendency to resurrect some of the parental attributes and give them a political application by bestowing61 them upon the State. The world-war has taught us the necessity of implicit63 obedience64 to the State and its representatives—military and civil; the right of independent thought, action and criticism being to a large extent suspended and the minute details of our lives being subject to order and inspection65 in much the same way as in our childhood they were subject to the supervision66 of our parents. Again, modern socialistic thought—especially in its cruder aspects—has produced a state of mind, as a result of which the individual becomes to a large extent absolved67 from the responsibility for his own education, progress and maintenance, or for those of his children. The adult individual is thus led to transfer on to the State that attitude of dependence which he originally adopted in relation to his parents, failing to this extent to attain68 that full degree of self-reliance and[237] independence which we have had in view in considering the gradual emancipation of children from their parents. In these respects it would seem that the conclusions arrived at in the course of our study of the family would point to a rather larger measure of Individualism than is contemplated69 by the great body of contemporary political thought. If our conclusions are correct, there is a danger in too wide a ramification70 of state provision and state control, inasmuch as it is liable to prevent that full development of individual power, initiative and self-reliance which can only be obtained by a high degree of emancipation from the primitive attitude of dependence on the parents. If, on the other hand, it is considered that the advantages of a far-reaching and complex state organization override71 those attending the full development of individuality, it is obvious that our ethical conclusions with regard to the family may have to be correspondingly revised.
There remains but one more set of ethical considerations The individual's relations to his family in later life to review before we finally take leave of the reader. Supposing that the relations of the individual to his family environment have successfully passed through the stages we have outlined and that the individual has at maturity attained72 the desirable degree of emancipation from, and independence of, the influences emanating73 from his family, there remains the problem of defining more precisely74 the nature of his relations to his family after he has reached maturity. It is evident enough from our previous considerations that these relations will be loose and far from binding75. It is also fairly clear that they must be such as to be capable of being broken altogether without causing any very considerable They must be capable of being broken altogether amount of distress76 or inconvenience to any of the parties concerned. Sooner or later these relations are necessarily broken by the great divider Death, and even before this final and inevitable separation, distance, diversity of occupation or other considerations may place the members of a once closely knit family entirely77 out of touch with one another. According to our principles it is obviously desirable that these unavoidable though it is natural that some relationship should be maintained separations should involve no element of bitter regret or paralysing sorrow.
Supposing however that circumstances are such as to make possible relations of some degree of intimacy78 between[238] the members of a family, all of whom have reached maturity, what will be the desirable extent and nature of this relationship? Presupposing always a satisfactory previous history on the lines we have considered, there would seem reason to think that some kind of relationship will, and should be, usually maintained. The common interests, affections and associations formed during a lengthy79 and highly important period of life will, in the absence of reasons to the contrary, usually constitute sufficient ground for the continuance throughout life of the intimacies80 that have been formed between those who lived so long together and have so long been subject in varying degree to each other's influence.
We must remember, however, that there very often are except where (as often happens) there are definite reasons to the contrary reasons to the contrary. In many cases, for instance, the love or dependence fixations in an individual's mind are such that continued intimacy with the parents will seriously detract from that individual's capacity to make the best of life. Frequent meeting with the parents may sap his energy or deprive him of initiative and self-reliance in the manner we have studied: or again, it may cause serious interference with his love life, as where the constant arousal of the not wholly outgrown81 love impulses to father or mother may appreciably82 diminish the affection available for husband or wife respectively, thus producing an unhappy marriage. For similar reasons frequent meetings between brothers and sisters may often be disadvantageous. Still more clearly is it undesirable83 to continue family intimacies where not love but hatred is the predominant tendency aroused and fostered by these intimacies. In such cases it is evident hypocrisy84 for the parties concerned to meet more often than is absolutely necessary: the frequent stirring up of conscious or unconscious hatred can only cause unhappiness, unprofitable and dangerous mental conflict or deterioration85 of character; and the more that relatives who are unable to "get on" with one another keep apart, the better it will be for all concerned.
With these wide and sweeping86 reservations however, it would probably seem to accord best with psychological and sociological considerations if at any rate some moderate degree of connection be maintained between relatives, whom circumstances have not definitely set apart. Given freedom[239] from all undesirable fixations (whether of hatred or of love), brothers and sisters have at least as good reasons for being permanently87 helpful and agreeable to one another as have friends who have been intimate with one another in the course of school, college, social or professional life. Still closer perhaps in some ways are the bonds that may permanently unite parents and children. The long period through which they have been bound to one another by ties that are biologically justifiable88 and necessary would seem to produce a psychological effect that inevitably tends to persist in some degree throughout the remainder of life. The relations of child to parent and of parent to child are so fundamental to all human existence and human intercourse89, that most, if not all, of our mental life, in so far as it has reference to our fellow creatures, is to some extent reminiscent of them, or affected90 by them. We can never root out from our mind the tendencies connected with this most intimate and essential of human connections; and this being so, it would only be in accordance with the most fundamental promptings of our nature to permit a certain proportion of the energy involved in these tendencies to continue to flow in its original direction.
This is not to say however that the manifestations of this But the relations between parents and children must undergo profound modification91 as time passes energy will not undergo considerable alteration as time passes. As children grow up and parents grow older, the former increase, the latter decrease in natural strength and ability of mind and body. In course of time therefore the attitude which parents and children naturally and reasonably adopt towards each other must gradually change to suit the varying conditions. At first children are dependent on the guidance and protection of their parents, who must make the necessary efforts to help and rear their offspring. Later on this differentiated92 relationship should give place to one in which parents and children are on equal terms. Finally, the original relationships may become to some extent reversed and, if parents and children are still within reach of one another, the former may come to look to the latter for some return of that help and protection that they themselves had previously93 afforded.
In this last situation, we see a form of the relationship, The care of the aged18 by their children which appears to be peculiar94 to human society. Throughout the animal world and even in many primitive human communities[240] there is no thought or care or tenderness devoted95 to old age. The increasing moralisation of human character (in which the relationship between parent and child has probably played a is culturally very desirable leading part) has brought it about that at least some degree of attention is given in all civilised societies to the needs—material and mental—of those who are no longer able fully to support themselves or to carry on their life without assistance. In any society in which the family is a permanent and firmly organised social unit, the duty of caring for the aged will naturally fall to some extent upon their children. This care of elderly, lonely or infirm parents by their children may perhaps legitimately96 be considered one of the most beautiful and touching97 expressions of specifically human morality—a point in which Man has definitely risen superior to the conditions of a brutal98 struggle for existence. As such it both deserves, and stands in need of, every encouragement and support which a developed and enlightened system of practical Ethics can afford.
It is not however free from certain ethical difficulties of its own. Thus, it might seem at first as though the care and though it has of necessity its limitations attention that a person of mature age may bestow62 upon his parents is but a just and reasonable return for the benefits which he himself received from these parents in his infancy99 and youth. Biologically however the cases are not similar. The care of parents for their young is necessary for the perpetuation100 of the race. The care bestowed101 upon the aged and infirm who are no longer able to provide adequately for themselves is of no direct value in the struggle for existence; it may even be a disadvantage in this struggle, a luxury that can only be afforded when the struggle is relaxed or when all competing individuals or races have adopted the practice. Further, from the point of view of the race, the real equivalent that is given in return for the benefits received from parents in early life lies in the corresponding benefits bestowed upon the next generation in its turn, and the double burden of maintaining and caring for both the young and the old may be definitely beyond the powers of many.
Fortunately, it but rarely happens, even at the extreme end of a long life, that the old are entirely dependent upon the care and efforts of others. In a civilised society they usually remain permanently able to provide for a considerable[241] Satisfactory family conditions conduce to happiness in old age part of their immediate102 needs, and the sounder and more stable is their own and the general economic condition, the more is this the case. On the whole it is perhaps rather on the psychological than on the strictly103 economic side that they will be in need of assistance, and here it is that the principles that have emerged from the study of the facts and tendencies with which we have been concerned in this book may prove of use. In so far as family life is able to proceed and develop on the lines which a true morality based on sound psychological principles and an adequate psychological knowledge would seem to indicate as most desirable, it should be possible for the older members of the family to participate freely in the joys and satisfactions which they may still find within the family circle and to escape the danger of being excluded from these satisfactions, by the disappointments and misunderstandings, or by the unhappiness and bitterness that the faulty development of the family so frequently, and so disastrously104, brings in its train. The old tend always to live to some extent vicariously: they find a great part of their interests and their pleasures in the contemplation of the doings of others who are younger than themselves: their own lives are projected into those of their children and their grandchildren, and by means of this projection105 they enjoy the most natural compensation for the decline of their own personal interests and capacities. If they have found this compensation, it may well be said that life's concluding chapter has shaped itself for them in a form as satisfactory as any which it is granted to human nature to enjoy.
With these considerations regarding old age we may Conclusion appropriately end. The subject of the human family is a mighty106 theme, of which no full treatment has been attempted here. If I have illumined certain aspects of the subject, if I have led the reader to realise something of the depth and complexity107 of the problems involved and of their vast importance for human weal and woe108, nay109, even for human existence, I shall have accomplished110 all, or more than all, that I set out to do. We have seen that, just as on the biological side the family is an essential factor in the development and preservation111 of the human race, so too on the psychological side, the thoughts, feelings and impulses that centre round the[242] family belong to the most intimate and fundamental part of Man's spiritual nature. If we are to understand this nature and to control and mould it wisely in order that we may achieve those ends in life which seem to us desirable, it is very necessary that we should have a full and accurate knowledge of the way in which the mind is influenced by, and in its turn reacts upon, the forms, circumstances and conditions of the human family. It is this which makes the subject of this little volume one of such supreme112 importance.
The End
The End
点击收听单词发音
1 dependence | |
n.依靠,依赖;信任,信赖;隶属 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 binds | |
v.约束( bind的第三人称单数 );装订;捆绑;(用长布条)缠绕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 alteration | |
n.变更,改变;蚀变 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 specially | |
adv.特定地;特殊地;明确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 maturity | |
n.成熟;完成;(支票、债券等)到期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 inadequate | |
adj.(for,to)不充足的,不适当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 incumbent | |
adj.成为责任的,有义务的;现任的,在职的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 lamentably | |
adv.哀伤地,拙劣地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 parental | |
adj.父母的;父的;母的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 inevitably | |
adv.不可避免地;必然发生地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 undue | |
adj.过分的;不适当的;未到期的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 unwilling | |
adj.不情愿的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 jurisdiction | |
n.司法权,审判权,管辖权,控制权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 indirectly | |
adv.间接地,不直接了当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 aged | |
adj.年老的,陈年的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 relinquish | |
v.放弃,撤回,让与,放手 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 manifestations | |
n.表示,显示(manifestation的复数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 omission | |
n.省略,删节;遗漏或省略的事物,冗长 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 emancipation | |
n.(从束缚、支配下)解放 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 insistence | |
n.坚持;强调;坚决主张 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 averse | |
adj.厌恶的;反对的,不乐意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 adoption | |
n.采用,采纳,通过;收养 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 bribing | |
贿赂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 bullying | |
v.恐吓,威逼( bully的现在分词 );豪;跋扈 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 nagging | |
adj.唠叨的,挑剔的;使人不得安宁的v.不断地挑剔或批评(某人)( nag的现在分词 );不断地烦扰或伤害(某人);无休止地抱怨;不断指责 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 formerly | |
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 hatred | |
n.憎恶,憎恨,仇恨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 inevitable | |
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 misery | |
n.痛苦,苦恼,苦难;悲惨的境遇,贫苦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 entail | |
vt.使承担,使成为必要,需要 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 jealousy | |
n.妒忌,嫉妒,猜忌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 surmounted | |
战胜( surmount的过去式和过去分词 ); 克服(困难); 居于…之上; 在…顶上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 amenability | |
n.服从的义务 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 relaxation | |
n.松弛,放松;休息;消遣;娱乐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 varied | |
adj.多样的,多变化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 cultivation | |
n.耕作,培养,栽培(法),养成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 compensating | |
补偿,补助,修正 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 restrictions | |
约束( restriction的名词复数 ); 管制; 制约因素; 带限制性的条件(或规则) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 ethics | |
n.伦理学;伦理观,道德标准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 correlation | |
n.相互关系,相关,关连 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 ethical | |
adj.伦理的,道德的,合乎道德的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 displacement | |
n.移置,取代,位移,排水量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 proceeding | |
n.行动,进行,(pl.)会议录,学报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 relatively | |
adv.比较...地,相对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 counteracting | |
对抗,抵消( counteract的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 autocracy | |
n.独裁政治,独裁政府 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 incompatible | |
adj.不相容的,不协调的,不相配的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 retention | |
n.保留,保持,保持力,记忆力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 hamper | |
vt.妨碍,束缚,限制;n.(有盖的)大篮子 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 analogous | |
adj.相似的;类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 overthrow | |
v.推翻,打倒,颠覆;n.推翻,瓦解,颠覆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 antiquated | |
adj.陈旧的,过时的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 condemned | |
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 purely | |
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 discrepancy | |
n.不同;不符;差异;矛盾 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 bestowing | |
砖窑中砖堆上层已烧透的砖 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 bestow | |
v.把…赠与,把…授予;花费 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 implicit | |
a.暗示的,含蓄的,不明晰的,绝对的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 obedience | |
n.服从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 inspection | |
n.检查,审查,检阅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 supervision | |
n.监督,管理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 absolved | |
宣告…无罪,赦免…的罪行,宽恕…的罪行( absolve的过去式和过去分词 ); 不受责难,免除责任 [义务] ,开脱(罪责) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 contemplated | |
adj. 预期的 动词contemplate的过去分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 ramification | |
n.分枝,分派,衍生物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 override | |
vt.不顾,不理睬,否决;压倒,优先于 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 emanating | |
v.从…处传出,传出( emanate的现在分词 );产生,表现,显示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 binding | |
有约束力的,有效的,应遵守的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 distress | |
n.苦恼,痛苦,不舒适;不幸;vt.使悲痛 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 intimacy | |
n.熟悉,亲密,密切关系,亲昵的言行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 lengthy | |
adj.漫长的,冗长的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 intimacies | |
亲密( intimacy的名词复数 ); 密切; 亲昵的言行; 性行为 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 outgrown | |
长[发展] 得超过(某物)的范围( outgrow的过去分词 ); 长[发展]得不能再要(某物); 长得比…快; 生长速度超过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 appreciably | |
adv.相当大地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 undesirable | |
adj.不受欢迎的,不良的,不合意的,讨厌的;n.不受欢迎的人,不良分子 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 hypocrisy | |
n.伪善,虚伪 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 deterioration | |
n.退化;恶化;变坏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 sweeping | |
adj.范围广大的,一扫无遗的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 permanently | |
adv.永恒地,永久地,固定不变地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 justifiable | |
adj.有理由的,无可非议的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 intercourse | |
n.性交;交流,交往,交际 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 affected | |
adj.不自然的,假装的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 modification | |
n.修改,改进,缓和,减轻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 differentiated | |
区分,区别,辨别( differentiate的过去式和过去分词 ); 区别对待; 表明…间的差别,构成…间差别的特征 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 devoted | |
adj.忠诚的,忠实的,热心的,献身于...的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 legitimately | |
ad.合法地;正当地,合理地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 touching | |
adj.动人的,使人感伤的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 brutal | |
adj.残忍的,野蛮的,不讲理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 infancy | |
n.婴儿期;幼年期;初期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 perpetuation | |
n.永存,不朽 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 bestowed | |
赠给,授予( bestow的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 disastrously | |
ad.灾难性地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 projection | |
n.发射,计划,突出部分 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 mighty | |
adj.强有力的;巨大的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 complexity | |
n.复杂(性),复杂的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 woe | |
n.悲哀,苦痛,不幸,困难;int.用来表达悲伤或惊慌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 nay | |
adv.不;n.反对票,投反对票者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 accomplished | |
adj.有才艺的;有造诣的;达到了的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 preservation | |
n.保护,维护,保存,保留,保持 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |