This diversity is not so much an evil to be complained of, as an inevitable5 and in some degree a proper result of the imperfect state of those sciences. It is not to be expected that there should be agreement about the definition of anything, until there is agreement about the thing itself. To define, is to select from among all the properties of a thing, those which shall be understood to be designated and declared by its name; and the properties must be well known to us before we can be competent to determine which of them are fittest to be chosen for this purpose. Accordingly, in the case of so complex an aggregation6 of particulars as are comprehended in anything which can be called a science, the definition we set out with is seldom that which a more extensive knowledge of the subject shows to be the most appropriate. Until we know the particulars themselves, we cannot fix upon the most correct and compact mode of circumscribing7 them by a general description. It was not until after an extensive and accurate acquaintance with the details of chemical phenomena8, [Pg 2]that it was found possible to frame a rational definition of chemistry; and the definition of the science of life and organization is still a matter of dispute. So long as the sciences are imperfect, the definitions must partake of their imperfection; and if the former are progressive, the latter ought to be so too. As much, therefore, as is to be expected from a definition placed at the commencement of a subject, is that it should define the scope of our inquiries9: and the definition which I am about to offer of the science of logic, pretends to nothing more, than to be a statement of the question which I have put to myself, and which this book is an attempt to resolve. The reader is at liberty to object to it as a definition of logic; but it is at all events a correct definition of the subject of these volumes.
§ 2. Logic has often been called the Art of Reasoning. A writer[1] who has done more than any other person to restore this study to the rank from which it had fallen in the estimation of the cultivated class in our own country, has adopted the above definition with an amendment10; he has defined Logic to be the Science, as well as the Art, of reasoning; meaning by the former term, the analysis of the mental process which takes place whenever we reason, and by the latter, the rules, grounded on that analysis, for conducting the process correctly. There can be no doubt as to the propriety11 of the emendation. A right understanding of the mental process itself, of the conditions it depends on, and the steps of which it consists, is the only basis on which a system of rules, fitted for the direction of the process, can possibly be founded. Art necessarily presupposes knowledge; art, in any but its infant state, presupposes scientific knowledge: and if every art does not bear the name of a science, it is only because several sciences are often necessary to form the groundwork of a single art. So complicated are the conditions which govern our practical agency, that to enable one thing to be done, it is often requisite12 to know the nature and properties of many things.
[Pg 3]
Logic, then, comprises the science of reasoning, as well as an art, founded on that science. But the word Reasoning, again, like most other scientific terms in popular use, abounds13 in ambiguities14. In one of its acceptations, it means syllogizing; or the mode of inference which may be called (with sufficient accuracy for the present purpose) concluding from generals to particulars. In another of its senses, to reason is simply to infer any assertion, from assertions already admitted: and in this sense induction15 is as much entitled to be called reasoning as the demonstrations16 of geometry.
Writers on logic have generally preferred the former acceptation of the term: the latter, and more extensive signification is that in which I mean to use it. I do this by virtue17 of the right I claim for every author, to give whatever provisional definition he pleases of his own subject. But sufficient reasons will, I believe, unfold themselves as we advance, why this should be not only the provisional but the final definition. It involves, at all events, no arbitrary change in the meaning of the word; for, with the general usage of the English language, the wider signification, I believe, accords better than the more restricted one.
§ 3. But Reasoning, even in the widest sense of which the word is susceptible18, does not seem to comprehend all that is included, either in the best, or even in the most current, conception of the scope and province of our science. The employment of the word Logic to denote the theory of argumentation, is derived19 from the Aristotelian, or, as they are commonly termed, the scholastic20, logicians. Yet even with them, in their systematic22 treatises24, argumentation was the subject only of the third part: the two former treated of Terms, and of Propositions; under one or other of which heads were also included Definition and Division. By some, indeed, these previous topics were professedly introduced only on account of their connexion with reasoning, and as a preparation for the doctrine25 and rules of the syllogism26. Yet they were treated with greater minuteness, and dwelt on at greater length, than was required for that purpose alone. More recent [Pg 4]writers on logic have generally understood the term as it was employed by the able author of the Port Royal Logic; viz. as equivalent to the Art of Thinking. Nor is this acceptation confined to books, and scientific inquiries. Even in ordinary conversation, the ideas connected with the word Logic include at least precision of language, and accuracy of classification: and we perhaps oftener hear persons speak of a logical arrangement, or of expressions logically defined, than of conclusions logically deduced from premises27. Again, a man is often called a great logician21, or a man of powerful logic, not for the accuracy of his deductions28, but for the extent of his command over premises; because the general propositions required for explaining a difficulty or refuting a sophism29, copiously30 and promptly31 occur to him: because, in short, his knowledge, besides being ample, is well under his command for argumentative use. Whether, therefore, we conform to the practice of those who have made the subject their particular study, or to that of popular writers and common discourse32, the province of logic will include several operations of the intellect not usually considered to fall within the meaning of the terms Reasoning and Argumentation.
These various operations might be brought within the compass of the science, and the additional advantage be obtained of a very simple definition, if, by an extension of the term, sanctioned by high authorities, we were to define logic as the science which treats of the operations of the human understanding in the pursuit of truth. For to this ultimate end, naming, classification, definition, and all other operations over which logic has ever claimed jurisdiction33, are essentially34 subsidiary. They may all be regarded as contrivances for enabling a person to know the truths which are needful to him, and to know them at the precise moment at which they are needful. Other purposes, indeed, are also served by these operations; for instance, that of imparting our knowledge to others. But, viewed with regard to this purpose, they have never been considered as within the province of the logician. The sole object of Logic is the guidance of one's own thoughts: the communication of those thoughts to others falls under the consideration [Pg 5]of Rhetoric35, in the large sense in which that art was conceived by the ancients; or of the still more extensive art of Education. Logic takes cognizance of our intellectual operations, only as they conduce to our own knowledge, and to our command over that knowledge for our own uses. If there were but one rational being in the universe, that being might be a perfect logician; and the science and art of logic would be the same for that one person as for the whole human race.
§ 4. But, if the definition which we formerly36 examined included too little, that which is now suggested has the opposite fault of including too much.
Truths are known to us in two ways: some are known directly, and of themselves; some through the medium of other truths. The former are the subject of Intuition, or Consciousness;[2] the latter, of Inference. The truths known by intuition are the original premises from which all others are inferred. Our assent37 to the conclusion being grounded on the truth of the premises, we never could arrive at any knowledge by reasoning, unless something could be known antecedently to all reasoning.
Examples of truths known to us by immediate38 consciousness, are our own bodily sensations and mental feelings. I know directly, and of my own knowledge, that I was vexed39 yesterday, or that I am hungry to-day. Examples of truths which we know only by way of inference, are occurrences which took place while we were absent, the events recorded in history, or the theorems of mathematics. The two former we infer from the testimony40 adduced, or from the traces of those past occurrences which still exist; the latter, from the premises laid down in books of geometry, under the title of definitions and axioms. Whatever we are capable of knowing [Pg 6]must belong to the one class or to the other; must be in the number of the primitive41 data, or of the conclusions which can be drawn42 from these.
With the original data, or ultimate premises of our knowledge; with their number or nature, the mode in which they are obtained, or the tests by which they may be distinguished43; logic, in a direct way at least, has, in the sense in which I conceive the science, nothing to do. These questions are partly not a subject of science at all, partly that of a very different science.
Whatever is known to us by consciousness, is known beyond possibility of question. What one sees or feels, whether bodily or mentally, one cannot but be sure that one sees or feels. No science is required for the purpose of establishing such truths; no rules of art can render our knowledge of them more certain than it is in itself. There is no logic for this portion of our knowledge.
But we may fancy that we see or feel what we in reality infer. A truth, or supposed truth, which is really the result of a very rapid inference, may seem to be apprehended44 intuitively. It has long been agreed by thinkers of the most opposite schools, that this mistake is actually made in so familiar an instance as that of the eyesight. There is nothing of which we appear to ourselves to be more directly conscious, than the distance of an object from us. Yet it has long been ascertained46, that what is perceived by the eye, is at most nothing more than a variously coloured surface; that when we fancy we see distance, all we really see is certain variations of apparent size, and degrees of faintness of colour; that our estimate of the object's distance from us is the result partly of a rapid inference from the muscular sensations accompanying the adjustment of the focal distance of the eye to objects unequally remote from us, and partly of a comparison (made with so much rapidity that we are unconscious of making it) between the size and colour of the object as they appear at the time, and the size and colour of the same or of similar objects as they appeared when close at hand, or when their degree of remoteness was known by other evidence. The perception of distance by the [Pg 7]eye, which seems so like intuition, is thus, in reality, an inference grounded on experience; an inference, too, which we learn to make; and which we make with more and more correctness as our experience increases; though in familiar cases it takes place so rapidly as to appear exactly on a par3 with those perceptions of sight which are really intuitive, our perceptions of colour.[3]
Of the science, therefore, which expounds47 the operations of the human understanding in the pursuit of truth, one essential part is the inquiry48: What are the facts which are the objects of intuition or consciousness, and what are those which we merely infer? But this inquiry has never been considered a portion of logic. Its place is in another and a perfectly49 distinct department of science, to which the name metaphysics more particularly belongs: that portion of mental philosophy which attempts to determine what part of the furniture of the mind belongs to it originally, and what part is constructed out of materials furnished to it from without. To this science appertain the great and much debated questions of the existence of matter; the existence of spirit, and of a distinction between it and matter; the reality of time and space, as things without the mind, and distinguishable from the objects which are said to exist in them. For in the present state of the discussion on these topics, it is almost universally allowed that the existence of matter or of spirit, of space or of time, is in its nature unsusceptible of being proved; and that if anything is known of them, it must be by immediate intuition. To the same science belong the inquiries into the nature of Conception, Perception, Memory, and Belief; all of which are operations of the understanding in the pursuit of truth; but with which, as phenomena of the mind, or with the possibility which may or may not exist of analysing any of them into simpler phenomena, the [Pg 8]logician as such has no concern. To this science must also be referred the following, and all analogous50 questions: To what extent our intellectual faculties51 and our emotions are innate—to what extent the result of association: Whether God, and duty, are realities, the existence of which is manifest to us à priori by the constitution of our rational faculty52; or whether our ideas of them are acquired notions, the origin of which we are able to trace and explain; and the reality of the objects themselves a question not of consciousness or intuition, but of evidence and reasoning.
The province of logic must be restricted to that portion of our knowledge which consists of inferences from truths previously53 known; whether those antecedent data be general propositions, or particular observations and perceptions. Logic is not the science of Belief, but the science of Proof, or Evidence. In so far as belief professes54 to be founded on proof, the office of logic is to supply a test for ascertaining55 whether or not the belief is well grounded. With the claims which any proposition has to belief on the evidence of consciousness, that is, without evidence in the proper sense of the word, logic has nothing to do.
§ 5. By far the greatest portion of our knowledge, whether of general truths or of particular facts, being avowedly56 matter of inference, nearly the whole, not only of science, but of human conduct, is amenable57 to the authority of logic. To draw inferences has been said to be the great business of life. Every one has daily, hourly, and momentary58 need of ascertaining facts which he has not directly observed; not from any general purpose of adding to his stock of knowledge, but because the facts themselves are of importance to his interests or to his occupations. The business of the magistrate59, of the military commander, of the navigator, of the physician, of the agriculturist, is merely to judge of evidence, and to act accordingly. They all have to ascertain45 certain facts, in order that they may afterwards apply certain rules, either devised by themselves, or prescribed for their guidance by others; and as they do this well or ill, so they discharge well or ill the duties [Pg 9]of their several callings. It is the only occupation in which the mind never ceases to be engaged; and is the subject, not of logic, but of knowledge in general.
Logic, however, is not the same thing with knowledge, though the field of logic is coextensive with the field of knowledge. Logic is the common judge and arbiter60 of all particular investigations61. It does not undertake to find evidence, but to determine whether it has been found. Logic neither observes, nor invents, nor discovers; but judges. It is no part of the business of logic to inform the surgeon what appearances are found to accompany a violent death. This he must learn from his own experience and observation, or from that of others, his predecessors62 in his peculiar pursuit. But logic sits in judgment63 on the sufficiency of that observation and experience to justify64 his rules, and on the sufficiency of his rules to justify his conduct. It does not give him proofs, but teaches him what makes them proofs, and how he is to judge of them. It does not teach that any particular fact proves any other, but points out to what conditions all facts must conform, in order that they may prove other facts. To decide whether any given fact fulfils these conditions, or whether facts can be found which fulfil them in a given case, belongs exclusively to the particular art or science, or to our knowledge of the particular subject.
It is in this sense that logic is, what Bacon so expressively65 called it, ars artium; the science of science itself. All science consists of data and conclusions from those data, of proofs and what they prove: now logic points out what relations must subsist66 between data and whatever can be concluded from them, between proof and everything which it can prove. If there be any such indispensable relations, and if these can be precisely67 determined68, every particular branch of science, as well as every individual in the guidance of his conduct, is bound to conform to those relations, under the penalty of making false inferences, of drawing conclusions which are not grounded in the realities of things. Whatever has at any time been concluded justly, whatever knowledge has been acquired otherwise than by immediate intuition, depended on [Pg 10]the observance of the laws which it is the province of logic to investigate. If the conclusions are just, and the knowledge real, those laws, whether known or not, have been observed.
§ 6. We need not, therefore, seek any farther for a solution of the question, so often agitated69, respecting the utility of logic. If a science of logic exists, or is capable of existing, it must be useful. If there be rules to which every mind consciously or unconsciously conforms in every instance in which it infers rightly, there seems little necessity for discussing whether a person is more likely to observe those rules, when he knows the rules, than when he is unacquainted with them.
A science may undoubtedly70 be brought to a certain, not inconsiderable, stage of advancement71, without the application of any other logic to it than what all persons, who are said to have a sound understanding, acquire empirically in the course of their studies. Mankind judged of evidence, and often correctly, before logic was a science, or they never could have made it one. And they executed great mechanical works before they understood the laws of mechanics. But there are limits both to what mechanicians can do without principles of mechanics, and to what thinkers can do without principles of logic. A few individuals, by extraordinary genius, or by the accidental acquisition of a good set of intellectual habits, may work without principles in the same way, or nearly the same way, in which they would have worked if they had been in possession of principles. But the bulk of mankind require either to understand the theory of what they are doing, or to have rules laid down for them by those who have understood the theory. In the progress of science from its easiest to its more difficult problems, each great step in advance has usually had either as its precursor72, or as its accompaniment and necessary condition, a corresponding improvement in the notions and principles of logic received among the most advanced thinkers. And if several of the more difficult sciences are still in so defective73 a state; if not only so little is proved, but disputation has not terminated even about the little which [Pg 11]seemed to be so; the reason perhaps is, that men's logical notions have not yet acquired the degree of extension, or of accuracy, requisite for the estimation of the evidence proper to those particular departments of knowledge.
§ 7. Logic, then, is the science of the operations of the understanding which are subservient74 to the estimation of evidence: both the process itself of advancing from known truths to unknown, and all other intellectual operations in so far as auxiliary75 to this. It includes, therefore, the operation of Naming; for language is an instrument of thought, as well as a means of communicating our thoughts. It includes, also, Definition, and Classification. For, the use of these operations (putting all other minds than one's own out of consideration) is to serve not only for keeping our evidences and the conclusions from them permanent and readily accessible in the memory, but for so marshalling the facts which we may at any time be engaged in investigating, as to enable us to perceive more clearly what evidence there is, and to judge with fewer chances of error whether it be sufficient. These, therefore, are operations specially76 instrumental to the estimation of evidence, and, as such, are within the province of Logic. There are other more elementary processes, concerned in all thinking, such as Conception, Memory, and the like; but of these it is not necessary that Logic should take any peculiar cognizance, since they have no special connexion with the problem of Evidence, further than that, like all other problems addressed to the understanding, it presupposes them.
Our object, then, will be, to attempt a correct analysis of the intellectual process called Reasoning or Inference, and of such other mental operations as are intended to facilitate this; as well as, on the foundation of this analysis, and pari passu with it, to bring together or frame a set of rules or canons for testing the sufficiency of any given evidence to prove any given proposition.
With respect to the first part of this undertaking77, I do not attempt to decompose78 the mental operations in question into their ultimate elements. It is enough if the analysis as [Pg 12]far as it goes is correct, and if it goes far enough for the practical purposes of logic considered as an art. The separation of a complicated phenomenon into its component79 parts is not like a connected and interdependent chain of proof. If one link of an argument breaks, the whole drops to the ground; but one step towards an analysis holds good and has an independent value, though we should never be able to make a second. The results which have been obtained by analytical80 chemistry are not the less valuable, though it should be discovered that all which we now call simple substances are really compounds. All other things are at any rate compounded of those elements: whether the elements themselves admit of decomposition81, is an important inquiry, but does not affect the certainty of the science up to that point.
I shall, accordingly, attempt to analyse the process of inference, and the processes subordinate to inference, so far only as may be requisite for ascertaining the difference between a correct and an incorrect performance of those processes. The reason for thus limiting our design, is evident. It has been said by objectors to logic, that we do not learn to use our muscles by studying their anatomy82. The fact is not quite fairly stated; for if the action of any of our muscles were vitiated by local weakness, or other physical defect, a knowledge of their anatomy might be very necessary for effecting a cure. But we should be justly liable to the criticism involved in this objection, were we, in a treatise23 on logic, to carry the analysis of the reasoning process beyond the point at which any inaccuracy which may have crept into it must become visible. In learning bodily exercises (to carry on the same illustration) we do, and must, analyse the bodily motions so far as is necessary for distinguishing those which ought to be performed from those which ought not. To a similar extent, and no further, it is necessary that the logician should analyse the mental processes with which Logic is concerned. Logic has no interest in carrying the analysis beyond the point at which it becomes apparent whether the operations have in any individual case been rightly or wrongly performed: in the same manner as the science of music teaches us to discriminate83 [Pg 13]between musical notes, and to know the combinations of which they are susceptible, but not what number of vibrations84 in a second correspond to each; which, though useful to be known, is useful for totally different purposes. The extension of Logic as a Science is determined by its necessities as an Art: whatever it does not need for its practical ends, it leaves to the larger science which may be said to correspond, not to any particular art, but to art in general; the science which deals with the constitution of the human faculties; and to which, in the part of our mental nature which concerns Logic, as well as in all other parts, it belongs to decide what are ultimate facts, and what are resolvable into other facts. And I believe it will be found that most of the conclusions arrived at in this work have no necessary connexion with any particular views respecting the ulterior analysis. Logic is common ground on which the partisans85 of Hartley and of Reid, of Locke and of Kant, may meet and join hands. Particular and detached opinions of all these thinkers will no doubt occasionally be controverted86, since all of them were logicians as well as metaphysicians; but the field on which their principal battles have been fought, lies beyond the boundaries of our science.
It cannot, indeed, be pretended that logical principles can be altogether irrelevant87 to those more abstruse88 discussions; nor is it possible but that the view we are led to take of the problem which logic proposes, must have a tendency favourable89 to the adoption90 of some one opinion, on these controverted subjects, rather than another. For metaphysics, in endeavouring to solve its own peculiar problem, must employ means, the validity of which falls under the cognizance of logic. It proceeds, no doubt, as far as possible, merely by a closer and more attentive91 interrogation of our consciousness, or more properly speaking, of our memory; and so far is not amenable to logic. But wherever this method is insufficient92 to attain93 the end of its inquiries, it must proceed, like other sciences, by means of evidence. Now, the moment this science begins to draw inferences from evidence, logic becomes the sovereign judge whether its inferences are well grounded, or what other inferences would be so.
This, however, constitutes no nearer or other relation between logic and metaphysics, than that which exists between logic and every other science. And I can conscientiously94 affirm, that no one proposition laid down in this work has been adopted for the sake of establishing, or with any reference to its fitness for being employed in establishing, preconceived opinions in any department of knowledge or of inquiry on which the speculative95 world is still undecided.
点击收听单词发音
1 logic | |
n.逻辑(学);逻辑性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 ethics | |
n.伦理学;伦理观,道德标准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 par | |
n.标准,票面价值,平均数量;adj.票面的,平常的,标准的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 inevitable | |
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 aggregation | |
n.聚合,组合;凝聚 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 circumscribing | |
v.在…周围划线( circumscribe的现在分词 );划定…范围;限制;限定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 inquiries | |
n.调查( inquiry的名词复数 );疑问;探究;打听 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 amendment | |
n.改正,修正,改善,修正案 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 propriety | |
n.正当行为;正当;适当 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 requisite | |
adj.需要的,必不可少的;n.必需品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 abounds | |
v.大量存在,充满,富于( abound的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 ambiguities | |
n.歧义( ambiguity的名词复数 );意义不明确;模棱两可的意思;模棱两可的话 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 induction | |
n.感应,感应现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 demonstrations | |
证明( demonstration的名词复数 ); 表明; 表达; 游行示威 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 susceptible | |
adj.过敏的,敏感的;易动感情的,易受感动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 scholastic | |
adj.学校的,学院的,学术上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 logician | |
n.逻辑学家 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 systematic | |
adj.有系统的,有计划的,有方法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 treatise | |
n.专著;(专题)论文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 treatises | |
n.专题著作,专题论文,专著( treatise的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 syllogism | |
n.演绎法,三段论法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 premises | |
n.建筑物,房屋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 deductions | |
扣除( deduction的名词复数 ); 结论; 扣除的量; 推演 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 sophism | |
n.诡辩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 copiously | |
adv.丰富地,充裕地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 promptly | |
adv.及时地,敏捷地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 discourse | |
n.论文,演说;谈话;话语;vi.讲述,著述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 jurisdiction | |
n.司法权,审判权,管辖权,控制权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 rhetoric | |
n.修辞学,浮夸之言语 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 formerly | |
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 assent | |
v.批准,认可;n.批准,认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 vexed | |
adj.争论不休的;(指问题等)棘手的;争论不休的问题;烦恼的v.使烦恼( vex的过去式和过去分词 );使苦恼;使生气;详细讨论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 testimony | |
n.证词;见证,证明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 apprehended | |
逮捕,拘押( apprehend的过去式和过去分词 ); 理解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 ascertain | |
vt.发现,确定,查明,弄清 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 ascertained | |
v.弄清,确定,查明( ascertain的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 expounds | |
论述,详细讲解( expound的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 analogous | |
adj.相似的;类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 faculties | |
n.能力( faculty的名词复数 );全体教职员;技巧;院 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 faculty | |
n.才能;学院,系;(学院或系的)全体教学人员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 professes | |
声称( profess的第三人称单数 ); 宣称; 公开表明; 信奉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 ascertaining | |
v.弄清,确定,查明( ascertain的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 avowedly | |
adv.公然地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 amenable | |
adj.经得起检验的;顺从的;对负有义务的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 momentary | |
adj.片刻的,瞬息的;短暂的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 magistrate | |
n.地方行政官,地方法官,治安官 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 arbiter | |
n.仲裁人,公断人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 investigations | |
(正式的)调查( investigation的名词复数 ); 侦查; 科学研究; 学术研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 predecessors | |
n.前任( predecessor的名词复数 );前辈;(被取代的)原有事物;前身 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 judgment | |
n.审判;判断力,识别力,看法,意见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 justify | |
vt.证明…正当(或有理),为…辩护 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 expressively | |
ad.表示(某事物)地;表达地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 subsist | |
vi.生存,存在,供养 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 agitated | |
adj.被鼓动的,不安的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 undoubtedly | |
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 advancement | |
n.前进,促进,提升 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 precursor | |
n.先驱者;前辈;前任;预兆;先兆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 defective | |
adj.有毛病的,有问题的,有瑕疵的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 subservient | |
adj.卑屈的,阿谀的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 auxiliary | |
adj.辅助的,备用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 specially | |
adv.特定地;特殊地;明确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 undertaking | |
n.保证,许诺,事业 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 decompose | |
vi.分解;vt.(使)腐败,(使)腐烂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 component | |
n.组成部分,成分,元件;adj.组成的,合成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 analytical | |
adj.分析的;用分析法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 decomposition | |
n. 分解, 腐烂, 崩溃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 anatomy | |
n.解剖学,解剖;功能,结构,组织 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 discriminate | |
v.区别,辨别,区分;有区别地对待 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 vibrations | |
n.摆动( vibration的名词复数 );震动;感受;(偏离平衡位置的)一次性往复振动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 partisans | |
游击队员( partisan的名词复数 ); 党人; 党羽; 帮伙 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 controverted | |
v.争论,反驳,否定( controvert的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 irrelevant | |
adj.不恰当的,无关系的,不相干的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 abstruse | |
adj.深奥的,难解的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 favourable | |
adj.赞成的,称赞的,有利的,良好的,顺利的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 adoption | |
n.采用,采纳,通过;收养 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 attentive | |
adj.注意的,专心的;关心(别人)的,殷勤的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 insufficient | |
adj.(for,of)不足的,不够的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 conscientiously | |
adv.凭良心地;认真地,负责尽职地;老老实实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 speculative | |
adj.思索性的,暝想性的,推理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |