I call the first step in the process an inductive operation, because there must be a direct induction as the basis of the whole; though in many particular investigations8 the place of the induction may be supplied by a prior deduction9; but the premises10 of this prior deduction must have been derived11 from induction.
The problem of the Deductive Method is, to find the law of an effect, from the laws of the different tendencies of which it is the joint12 result. The first requisite13, therefore, is to know the laws of those tendencies; the law of each of the concurrent14 causes: and this supposes a previous process of observation or experiment upon each cause separately; or else a previous deduction, which also must depend for its ultimate premises on observation or experiment. Thus, if the subject be social or historical phenomena, the premises of the Deductive Method must be the laws of the causes which determine that class of phenomena; and those causes are human actions, together with the general outward circumstances under the influence of which mankind are placed, and which constitute man's position on the earth. The Deductive Method, applied15 to social phenomena, must begin, therefore, by investigating, or must suppose to have been already investigated, the laws of human [Pg 508]action, and those properties of outward things by which the actions of human beings in society are determined16. Some of these general truths will naturally be obtained by observation and experiment, others by deduction: the more complex laws of human action, for example, may be deduced from the simpler ones; but the simple or elementary laws will always, and necessarily, have been obtained by a directly inductive process.
To ascertain17, then, the laws of each separate cause which takes a share in producing the effect, is the first desideratum of the Deductive Method. To know what the causes are, which must be subjected to this process of study, may or may not be difficult. In the case last mentioned, this first condition is of easy fulfilment. That social phenomena depend on the acts and mental impressions of human beings, never could have been a matter of any doubt, however imperfectly it may have been known either by what laws those impressions and actions are governed, or to what social consequences their laws naturally lead. Neither, again, after physical science had attained18 a certain development, could there be any real doubt where to look for the laws on which the phenomena of life depend, since they must be the mechanical and chemical laws of the solid and fluid substances composing the organized body and the medium in which it subsists19, together with the peculiar20 vital laws of the different tissues constituting the organic structure. In other cases, really far more simple than these, it was much less obvious in what quarter the causes were to be looked for: as in the case of the celestial21 phenomena. Until, by combining the laws of certain causes, it was found that those laws explained all the facts which experience had proved concerning the heavenly motions, and led to predictions which it always verified, mankind never knew that those were the causes. But whether we are able to put the question before, or not until after, we have become capable of answering it, in either case it must be answered; the laws of the different causes must be ascertained22, before we can proceed to deduce from them the conditions of the effect.
The mode of ascertaining23 those laws neither is, nor can be, [Pg 509]any other than the fourfold method of experimental inquiry24, already discussed. A few remarks on the application of that method to cases of the Composition of Causes, are all that is requisite.
It is obvious that we cannot expect to find the law of a tendency, by an induction from cases in which the tendency is counteracted25. The laws of motion could never have been brought to light from the observation of bodies kept at rest by the equilibrium26 of opposing forces. Even where the tendency is not, in the ordinary sense of the word, counteracted, but only modified, by having its effects compounded with the effects arising from some other tendency or tendencies, we are still in an unfavourable position for tracing, by means of such cases, the law of the tendency itself. It would have been scarcely possible to discover the law that every body in motion tends to continue moving in a straight line, by an induction from instances in which the motion is deflected27 into a curve, by being compounded with the effect of an accelerating force. Notwithstanding the resources afforded in this description of cases by the Method of Concomitant Variations, the principles of a judicious28 experimentation29 prescribe that the law of each of the tendencies should be studied, if possible, in cases in which that tendency operates alone, or in combination with no agencies but those of which the effect can, from previous knowledge, be calculated and allowed for.
Accordingly, in the cases, unfortunately very numerous and important, in which the causes do not suffer themselves to be separated and observed apart, there is much difficulty in laying down with due certainty the inductive foundation necessary to support the deductive method. This difficulty is most of all conspicuous30 in the case of physiological31 phenomena; it being seldom possible to separate the different agencies which collectively compose an organized body, without destroying the very phenomena which it is our object to investigate:
We lose it, in the moment we detect.
And for this reason I am inclined to the opinion, that physiology33 [Pg 510](greatly and rapidly progressive as it now is) is embarrassed by greater natural difficulties, and is probably susceptible34 of a less degree of ultimate perfection, than even the social science; inasmuch as it is possible to study the laws and operations of one human mind apart from other minds, much less imperfectly than we can study the laws of one organ or tissue of the human body apart from the other organs or tissues.
It has been judiciously35 remarked that pathological facts, or, to speak in common language, diseases in their different forms and degrees, afford in the case of physiological investigation the most valuable equivalent to experimentation properly so called; inasmuch as they often exhibit to us a definite disturbance36 in some one organ or organic function, the remaining organs and functions being, in the first instance at least, unaffected. It is true that from the perpetual actions and reactions which are going on among all parts of the organic economy, there can be no prolonged disturbance in any one function without ultimately involving many of the others; and when once it has done so, the experiment for the most part loses its scientific value. All depends on observing the early stages of the derangement38; which, unfortunately, are of necessity the least marked. If, however, the organs and functions not disturbed in the first instance, become affected37 in a fixed39 order of succession, some light is thereby40 thrown upon the action which one organ exercises over another: and we occasionally obtain a series of effects which we can refer with some confidence to the original local derangement; but for this it is necessary that we should know that the original derangement was local. If it was what is termed constitutional, that is, if we do not know in what part of the animal economy it took its rise, or the precise nature of the disturbance which took place in that part, we are unable to determine which of the various derangements was cause and which effect; which of them were produced by one another, and which by the direct, though perhaps tardy41, action of the original cause.
Besides natural pathological facts, we can produce pathological facts artificially; we can try experiments, even in the [Pg 511]popular sense of the term, by subjecting the living being to some external agent, such as the mercury of our former example, or the section of a nerve to ascertain the functions of different parts of the nervous system. As this experimentation is not intended to obtain a direct solution of any practical question, but to discover general laws, from which afterwards the conditions of any particular effect may be obtained by deduction; the best cases to select are those of which the circumstances can be best ascertained: and such are generally not those in which there is any practical object in view. The experiments are best tried, not in a state of disease, which is essentially42 a changeable state, but in the condition of health, comparatively a fixed state. In the one, unusual agencies are at work, the results of which we have no means of predicting; in the other, the course of the accustomed physiological phenomena would, it may generally be presumed, remain undisturbed, were it not for the disturbing cause which we introduce.
Such, with the occasional aid of the Method of Concomitant Variations, (the latter not less incumbered than the more elementary methods by the peculiar difficulties of the subject,) are our inductive resources for ascertaining the laws of the causes considered separately, when we have it not in our power to make trial of them in a state of actual separation. The insufficiency of these resources is so glaring, that no one can be surprised at the backward state of the science of physiology; in which indeed our knowledge of causes is so imperfect, that we can neither explain, nor could without specific experience have predicted, many of the facts which are certified43 to us by the most ordinary observation. Fortunately, we are much better informed as to the empirical laws of the phenomena, that is, the uniformities respecting which we cannot yet decide whether they are cases of causation, or mere44 results of it. Not only has the order in which the facts of organization and life successively manifest themselves, from the first germ of existence to death, been found to be uniform, and very accurately45 ascertainable46; but, by a great application of the Method of Concomitant Variations to the entire facts of [Pg 512]comparative anatomy47 and physiology, the characteristic organic structure corresponding to each class of functions has been determined with considerable precision. Whether these organic conditions are the whole of the conditions, and in many cases whether they are conditions at all, or mere collateral48 effects of some common cause, we are quite ignorant: nor are we ever likely to know, unless we could construct an organized body, and try whether it would live.
Under such disadvantages do we, in cases of this description, attempt the initial, or inductive step, in the application of the Deductive Method to complex phenomena. But such, fortunately, is not the common case. In general, the laws of the causes on which the effect depends may be obtained by an induction from comparatively simple instances, or, at the worst, by deduction from the laws of simpler causes, so obtained. By simple instances are meant, of course, those in which the action of each cause was not intermixed or interfered49 with, or not to any great extent, by other causes whose laws were unknown. And only when the induction which furnished the premises to the Deductive method rested on such instances, has the application of such a method to the ascertainment50 of the laws of a complex effect, been attended with brilliant results.
§ 2. When the laws of the causes have been ascertained, and the first stage of the great logical operation now under discussion satisfactorily accomplished51, the second part follows; that of determining from the laws of the causes, what effect any given combination of those causes will produce. This is a process of calculation, in the wider sense of the term; and very often involves processes of calculation in the narrowest sense. It is a ratiocination; and when our knowledge of the causes is so perfect, as to extend to the exact numerical laws which they observe in producing their effects, the ratiocination may reckon among its premises the theorems of the science of number, in the whole immense extent of that science. Not only are the most advanced truths of mathematics often required to enable us to compute52 an effect, the numerical law [Pg 513]of which we already know; but, even by the aid of those most advanced truths, we can go but a little way. In so simple a case as the common problem of three bodies gravitating towards one another, with a force directly as their mass and inversely53 as the square of the distance, all the resources of the calculus54 have not hitherto sufficed to obtain any general solution but an approximate one. In a case a little more complex, but still one of the simplest which arise in practice, that of the motion of a projectile55, the causes which affect the velocity56 and range (for example) of a cannon-ball may be all known and estimated; the force of the gunpowder57, the angle of elevation58, the density59 of the air, the strength and direction of the wind; but it is one of the most difficult of mathematical problems to combine all these, so as to determine the effect resulting from their collective action.
Besides the theorems of number, those of geometry also come in as premises, where the effects take place in space, and involve motion and extension, as in mechanics, optics, acoustics60, astronomy. But when the complication increases, and the effects are under the influence of so many and such shifting causes as to give no room either for fixed numbers, or for straight lines and regular curves, (as in the case of physiological, to say nothing of mental and social phenomena,) the laws of number and extension are applicable, if at all, only on that large scale on which precision of details becomes unimportant. Although these laws play a conspicuous part in the most striking examples of the investigation of nature by the Deductive Method, as for example in the Newtonian theory of the celestial motions, they are by no means an indispensable part of every such process. All that is essential in it is reasoning from a general law to a particular case, that is, determining by means of the particular circumstances of that case, what result is required in that instance to fulfil the law. Thus in the Torricellian experiment, if the fact that air has weight had been previously61 known, it would have been easy, without any numerical data, to deduce from the general law of equilibrium, that the mercury would stand in the tube at such a height that the column of mercury would exactly [Pg 514]balance a column of the atmosphere of equal diameter; because, otherwise, equilibrium would not exist.
By such ratiocinations from the separate laws of the causes, we may, to a certain extent, succeed in answering either of the following questions: Given a certain combination of causes, what effect will follow? and, What combination of causes, if it existed, would produce a given effect? In the one case, we determine the effect to be expected in any complex circumstances of which the different elements are known: in the other case we learn, according to what law—under what antecedent conditions—a given complex effect will occur.
§ 3. But (it may here be asked) are not the same arguments by which the methods of direct observation and experiment were set aside as illusory when applied to the laws of complex phenomena, applicable with equal force against the Method of Deduction? When in every single instance a multitude, often an unknown multitude, of agencies, are clashing and combining, what security have we that in our computation à priori we have taken all these into our reckoning? How many must we not generally be ignorant of? Among those which we know, how probable that some have been overlooked; and, even were all included, how vain the pretence62 of summing up the effects of many causes, unless we know accurately the numerical law of each,—a condition in most cases not to be fulfilled; and even when fulfilled, to make the calculation transcends63, in any but very simple cases, the utmost power of mathematical science with all its most modern improvements.
These objections have real weight, and would be altogether unanswerable, if there were no test by which, when we employ the Deductive Method, we might judge whether an error of any of the above descriptions had been committed or not. Such a test however there is: and its application forms, under the name of Verification, the third essential component64 part of the Deductive Method; without which all the results it can give have little other value than that of conjecture65. To [Pg 515]warrant reliance on the general conclusions arrived at by deduction, these conclusions must be found, on careful comparison, to accord with the results of direct observation wherever it can be had. If, when we have experience to compare with them, this experience confirms them, we may safely trust to them in other cases of which our specific experience is yet to come. But if our deductions66 have led to the conclusion that from a particular combination of causes a given effect would result, then in all known cases where that combination can be shown to have existed, and where the effect has not followed, we must be able to show (or at least to make a probable surmise) what frustrated67 it: if we cannot, the theory is imperfect, and not yet to be relied upon. Nor is the verification complete, unless some of the cases in which the theory is borne out by the observed result, are of at least equal complexity68 with any other cases in which its application could be called for.
If direct observation and collation69 of instances have furnished us with any empirical laws of the effect (whether true in all observed cases, or only true for the most part), the most effectual verification of which the theory could be susceptible would be, that it led deductively to those empirical laws; that the uniformities, whether complete or incomplete, which were observed to exist among the phenomena, were accounted for by the laws of the causes—were such as could not but exist if those be really the causes by which the phenomena are produced. Thus it was very reasonably deemed an essential requisite of any true theory of the causes of the celestial motions, that it should lead by deduction to Kepler's laws: which, accordingly, the Newtonian theory did.
In order, therefore, to facilitate the verification of theories obtained by deduction, it is important that as many as possible of the empirical laws of the phenomena should be ascertained, by a comparison of instances, conformably to the Method of Agreement: as well as (it must be added) that the phenomena themselves should be described, in the most comprehensive as well as accurate manner possible; by collecting from the observation of parts, the simplest possible [Pg 516]correct expressions for the corresponding wholes: as when the series of the observed places of a planet was first expressed by a circle, then by a system of epicycles, and subsequently by an ellipse.
It is worth remarking, that complex instances which would have been of no use for the discovery of the simple laws into which we ultimately analyse their phenomena, nevertheless, when they have served to verify the analysis, become additional evidence of the laws themselves. Although we could not have got at the law from complex cases, still when the law, got at otherwise, is found to be in accordance with the result of a complex case, that case becomes a new experiment on the law, and helps to confirm what it did not assist to discover. It is a new trial of the principle in a different set of circumstances; and occasionally serves to eliminate some circumstance not previously excluded, and the exclusion70 of which might require an experiment impossible to be executed. This was strikingly conspicuous in the example formerly71 quoted, in which the difference between the observed and the calculated velocity of sound was ascertained to result from the heat extricated72 by the condensation73 which takes place in each sonorous74 vibration75. This was a trial, in new circumstances, of the law of the development of heat by compression; and it added materially to the proof of the universality of that law. Accordingly any law of nature is deemed to have gained in point of certainty, by being found to explain some complex case which had not previously been thought of in connexion with it; and this indeed is a consideration to which it is the habit of scientific inquirers to attach rather too much value than too little.
To the Deductive Method, thus characterized in its three constituent76 parts, Induction, Ratiocination, and Verification, the human mind is indebted for its most conspicuous triumphs in the investigation of nature. To it we owe all the theories by which vast and complicated phenomena are embraced under a few simple laws, which, considered as the laws of those great phenomena, could never have been detected by their direct study. We may form some conception of [Pg 517]what the method has done for us, from the case of the celestial motions; one of the simplest among the greater instances of the Composition of Causes, since (except in a few cases not of primary importance) each of the heavenly bodies may be considered, without material inaccuracy, to be never at one time influenced by the attraction of more than two bodies, the sun and one other planet or satellite; making, with the reaction of the body itself, and the force generated by the body's own motion and acting77 in the direction of the tangent, only four different agents on the concurrence78 of which the motions of that body depend; a much smaller number, no doubt, than that by which any other of the great phenomena of nature is determined or modified. Yet how could we ever have ascertained the combination of forces on which the motions of the earth and planets are dependent, by merely comparing the orbits or velocities79 of different planets, or the different velocities or positions of the same planet? Notwithstanding the regularity80 which manifests itself in those motions, in a degree so rare among the effects of a concurrence of causes; and although the periodical recurrence of exactly the same effect, affords positive proof that all the combinations of causes which occur at all, recur4 periodically; we should not have known what the causes were, if the existence of agencies precisely81 similar on our own earth had not, fortunately, brought the causes themselves within the reach of experimentation under simple circumstances. As we shall have occasion to analyse, further on, this great example of the Method of Deduction, we shall not occupy any time with it here, but shall proceed to that secondary application of the Deductive Method, the result of which is not to prove laws of phenomena, but to explain them.
点击收听单词发音
1 investigation | |
n.调查,调查研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 recurrence | |
n.复发,反复,重现 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 recur | |
vi.复发,重现,再发生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 induction | |
n.感应,感应现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 ratiocination | |
n.推理;推断 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 investigations | |
(正式的)调查( investigation的名词复数 ); 侦查; 科学研究; 学术研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 deduction | |
n.减除,扣除,减除额;推论,推理,演绎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 premises | |
n.建筑物,房屋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 joint | |
adj.联合的,共同的;n.关节,接合处;v.连接,贴合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 requisite | |
adj.需要的,必不可少的;n.必需品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 concurrent | |
adj.同时发生的,一致的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 ascertain | |
vt.发现,确定,查明,弄清 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 subsists | |
v.(靠很少的钱或食物)维持生活,生存下去( subsist的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 celestial | |
adj.天体的;天上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 ascertained | |
v.弄清,确定,查明( ascertain的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 ascertaining | |
v.弄清,确定,查明( ascertain的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 counteracted | |
对抗,抵消( counteract的过去式 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 equilibrium | |
n.平衡,均衡,相称,均势,平静 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 deflected | |
偏离的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 judicious | |
adj.明智的,明断的,能作出明智决定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 experimentation | |
n.实验,试验,实验法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 conspicuous | |
adj.明眼的,惹人注目的;炫耀的,摆阔气的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 physiological | |
adj.生理学的,生理学上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 dissect | |
v.分割;解剖 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 physiology | |
n.生理学,生理机能 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 susceptible | |
adj.过敏的,敏感的;易动感情的,易受感动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 judiciously | |
adv.明断地,明智而审慎地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 disturbance | |
n.动乱,骚动;打扰,干扰;(身心)失调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 affected | |
adj.不自然的,假装的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 derangement | |
n.精神错乱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 tardy | |
adj.缓慢的,迟缓的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 certified | |
a.经证明合格的;具有证明文件的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 accurately | |
adv.准确地,精确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 ascertainable | |
adj.可确定(探知),可发现的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 anatomy | |
n.解剖学,解剖;功能,结构,组织 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 collateral | |
adj.平行的;旁系的;n.担保品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 interfered | |
v.干预( interfere的过去式和过去分词 );调停;妨碍;干涉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 ascertainment | |
n.探查,发现,确认 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 accomplished | |
adj.有才艺的;有造诣的;达到了的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 compute | |
v./n.计算,估计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 inversely | |
adj.相反的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 calculus | |
n.微积分;结石 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 projectile | |
n.投射物,发射体;adj.向前开进的;推进的;抛掷的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 velocity | |
n.速度,速率 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 gunpowder | |
n.火药 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 elevation | |
n.高度;海拔;高地;上升;提高 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 density | |
n.密集,密度,浓度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 acoustics | |
n.声学,(复)音响效果,音响装置 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 pretence | |
n.假装,作假;借口,口实;虚伪;虚饰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 transcends | |
超出或超越(经验、信念、描写能力等)的范围( transcend的第三人称单数 ); 优于或胜过… | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 component | |
n.组成部分,成分,元件;adj.组成的,合成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 conjecture | |
n./v.推测,猜测 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 deductions | |
扣除( deduction的名词复数 ); 结论; 扣除的量; 推演 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 frustrated | |
adj.挫败的,失意的,泄气的v.使不成功( frustrate的过去式和过去分词 );挫败;使受挫折;令人沮丧 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 complexity | |
n.复杂(性),复杂的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 collation | |
n.便餐;整理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 exclusion | |
n.拒绝,排除,排斥,远足,远途旅行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 formerly | |
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 extricated | |
v.使摆脱困难,脱身( extricate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 condensation | |
n.压缩,浓缩;凝结的水珠 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 sonorous | |
adj.响亮的,回响的;adv.圆润低沉地;感人地;n.感人,堂皇 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 vibration | |
n.颤动,振动;摆动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 constituent | |
n.选民;成分,组分;adj.组成的,构成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 acting | |
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 concurrence | |
n.同意;并发 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 velocities | |
n.速度( velocity的名词复数 );高速,快速 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 regularity | |
n.规律性,规则性;匀称,整齐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |