Questions about ends are, in other words, questions what things are desirable. The utilitarian5 doctrine6 is, that happiness is desirable, and the only thing desirable, as an end; all other things being only desirable as means to that end. What ought to be required of this doctrine—what conditions is it requisite7 that the doctrine should fulfil—to make good its claim to be believed?
The only proof capable of being given that an object is visible, is that people actually see it. The only proof that a sound is audible, is that people hear it: and so of the other sources of our experience. In like manner, I apprehend8, the sole evidence it is possible to produce that anything is desirable, is that people do actually desire it. If the end which the utilitarian doctrine proposes to itself were not, in theory and in practice, acknowledged to be an end, nothing could ever convince any person that it was so. No reason can be given why the general happiness is desirable, except that each person, so far as he believes it to be attainable9, desires his own happiness. This, however, being a fact, we have not only all the proof which the case admits of, but all which it is possible to require, that happiness is a good: that each person's happiness is a good to that person, and the general happiness, therefore, a good to the aggregate10 of all persons. Happiness has made out its title as one of the ends of conduct, and consequently one of the criteria11 of morality.
But it has not, by this alone, proved itself to be the sole criterion. To do that, it would seem, by the same rule, necessary to show, not only that people desire happiness, but that they never desire anything else. Now it is palpable that they do desire things which, in common language, are decidedly distinguished13 from happiness. They desire, for example, virtue14, and the absence of vice15, no less really than pleasure and the absence of pain. The desire of virtue is not as universal, but it is as authentic16 a fact, as the desire of happiness. And hence the opponents of the utilitarian standard deem that they have a right to infer that there are other ends of human action besides happiness, and that happiness is not the standard of approbation17 and disapprobation.
But does the utilitarian doctrine deny that people desire virtue, or maintain that virtue is not a thing to be desired? The very reverse. It maintains not only that virtue is to be desired, but that it is to be desired disinterestedly19, for itself. Whatever may be the opinion of utilitarian moralists as to the original conditions by which virtue is made virtue; however they may believe (as they do) that actions and dispositions20 are only virtuous21 because they promote another end than virtue; yet this being granted, and it having been decided12, from considerations of this description, what is virtuous, they not only place virtue at the very head of the things which are good as means to the ultimate end, but they also recognise as a psychological fact the possibility of its being, to the individual, a good in itself, without looking to any end beyond it; and hold, that the mind is not in a right state, not in a state conformable to Utility, not in the state most conducive22 to the general happiness, unless it does love virtue in this manner—as a thing desirable in itself, even although, in the individual instance, it should not produce those other desirable consequences which it tends to produce, and on account of which it is held to be virtue. This opinion is not, in the smallest degree, a departure from the Happiness principle. The ingredients of happiness are very various, and each of them is desirable in itself, and not merely when considered as swelling24 an aggregate. The principle of utility does not mean that any given pleasure, as music, for instance, or any given exemption25 from pain, as for example health, are to be looked upon as means to a collective something termed happiness, and to be desired on that account. They are desired and desirable in and for themselves; besides being means, they are a part of the end. Virtue, according to the utilitarian doctrine, is not naturally and originally part of the end, but it is capable of becoming so; and in those who love it disinterestedly it has become so, and is desired and cherished, not as a means to happiness, but as a part of their happiness.
To illustrate26 this farther, we may remember that virtue is not the only thing, originally a means, and which if it were not a means to anything else, would be and remain indifferent, but which by association with what it is a means to, comes to be desired for itself, and that too with the utmost intensity27. What, for example, shall we say of the love of money? There is nothing originally more desirable about money than about any heap of glittering pebbles28. Its worth is solely29 that of the things which it will buy; the desires for other things than itself, which it is a means of gratifying. Yet the love of money is not only one of the strongest moving forces of human life, but money is, in many cases, desired in and for itself; the desire to possess it is often stronger than the desire to use it, and goes on increasing when all the desires which point to ends beyond it, to be compassed by it, are falling off. It may be then said truly, that money is desired not for the sake of an end, but as part of the end. From being a means to happiness, it has come to be itself a principal ingredient of the individual's conception of happiness. The same may be said of the majority of the great objects of human life—power, for example, or fame; except that to each of these there is a certain amount of immediate30 pleasure annexed31, which has at least the semblance32 of being naturally inherent in them; a thing which cannot be said of money. Still, however, the strongest natural attraction, both of power and of fame, is the immense aid they give to the attainment33 of our other wishes; and it is the strong association thus generated between them and all our objects of desire, which gives to the direct desire of them the intensity it often assumes, so as in some characters to surpass in strength all other desires. In these cases the means have become a part of the end, and a more important part of it than any of the things which they are means to. What was once desired as an instrument for the attainment of happiness, has come to be desired for its own sake. In being desired for its own sake it is, however, desired as part of happiness. The person is made, or thinks he would be made, happy by its mere23 possession; and is made unhappy by failure to obtain it. The desire of it is not a different thing from the desire of happiness, any more than the love of music, or the desire of health. They are included in happiness. They are some of the elements of which the desire of happiness is made up. Happiness is not an abstract idea, but a concrete whole; and these are some of its parts. And the utilitarian standard sanctions and approves their being so. Life would be a poor thing, very ill provided with sources of happiness, if there were not this provision of nature, by which things originally indifferent, but conducive to, or otherwise associated with, the satisfaction of our primitive34 desires, become in themselves sources of pleasure more valuable than the primitive pleasures, both in permanency, in the space of human existence that they are capable of covering, and even in intensity. Virtue, according to the utilitarian conception, is a good of this description. There was no original desire of it, or motive35 to it, save its conduciveness to pleasure, and especially to protection from pain. But through the association thus formed, it may be felt a good in itself, and desired as such with as great intensity as any other good; and with this difference between it and the love of money, of power, or of fame, that all of these may, and often do, render the individual noxious36 to the other members of the society to which he belongs, whereas there is nothing which makes him so much a blessing37 to them as the cultivation38 of the disinterested18, love of virtue. And consequently, the utilitarian standard, while it tolerates and approves those other acquired desires, up to the point beyond which they would be more injurious to the general happiness than promotive of it, enjoins39 and requires the cultivation of the love of virtue up to the greatest strength possible, as being above all things important to the general happiness.
It results from the preceding considerations, that there is in reality nothing desired except happiness. Whatever is desired otherwise than as a means to some end beyond itself, and ultimately to happiness, is desired as itself a part of happiness, and is not desired for itself until it has become so. Those who desire virtue for its own sake, desire it either because the consciousness of it is a pleasure, or because the consciousness of being without it is a pain, or for both reasons united; as in truth the pleasure and pain seldom exist separately, but almost always together, the same person feeling pleasure in the degree of virtue attained40, and pain in not having attained more. If one of these gave him no pleasure, and the other no pain, he would not love or desire virtue, or would desire it only for the other benefits which it might produce to himself or to persons whom he cared for.
We have now, then, an answer to the question, of what sort of proof the principle of utility is susceptible41. If the opinion which I have now stated is psychologically true—if human nature is so constituted as to desire nothing which is not either a part of happiness or a means of happiness, we can have no other proof, and we require no other, that these are the only things desirable. If so, happiness is the sole end of human action, and the promotion42 of it the test by which to judge of all human conduct; from whence it necessarily follows that it must be the criterion of morality, since a part is included in the whole.
And now to decide whether this is really so; whether mankind do desire nothing for itself but that which is a pleasure to them, or of which the absence is a pain; we have evidently arrived at a question of fact and experience, dependent, like all similar questions, upon evidence. It can only be determined43 by practised self-consciousness and self-observation, assisted by observation of others. I believe that these sources of evidence, impartially44 consulted, will declare that desiring a thing and finding it pleasant, aversion to it and thinking of it as painful, are phenomena45 entirely46 inseparable, or rather two parts of the same phenomenon; in strictness of language, two different modes of naming the same psychological fact: that to think of an object as desirable (unless for the sake of its consequences), and to think of it as pleasant, are one and the same thing; and that to desire anything, except in proportion as the idea of it is pleasant, is a physical and metaphysical impossibility.
So obvious does this appear to me, that I expect it will hardly be disputed: and the objection made will be, not that desire can possibly be directed to anything ultimately except pleasure and exemption from pain, but that the will is a different thing from desire; that a person of confirmed virtue, or any other person whose purposes are fixed47, carries out his purposes without any thought of the pleasure he has in contemplating48 them, or expects to derive49 from their fulfilment; and persists in acting50 on them, even though these pleasures are much diminished, by changes in his character or decay of his passive sensibilities, or are outweighed51 by the pains which the pursuit of the purposes may bring upon him. All this I fully52 admit, and have stated it elsewhere, as positively53 and emphatically as any one. Will, the active phenomenon, is a different thing from desire, the state of passive sensibility, and though originally an offshoot from it, may in time take root and detach itself from the parent stock; so much so, that in the case of an habitual54 purpose, instead of willing the thing because we desire it, we often desire it only because we will it. This, however, is but an instance of that familiar fact, the power of habit, and is nowise confined to the case of virtuous actions. Many indifferent things, which men originally did from a motive of some sort, they continue to do from habit. Sometimes this is done unconsciously, the consciousness coming only after the action: at other times with conscious volition55, but volition which has become habitual, and is put into operation by the force of habit, in opposition56 perhaps to the deliberate preference, as often happens with those who have contracted habits of vicious or hurtful indulgence. Third and last comes the case in which the habitual act of will in the individual instance is not in contradiction to the general intention prevailing57 at other times, but in fulfilment of it; as in the case of the person of confirmed virtue, and of all who pursue deliberately58 and consistently any determinate end. The distinction between will and desire thus understood, is an authentic and highly important psychological fact; but the fact consists solely in this—that will, like all other parts of our constitution, is amenable59 to habit, and that we may will from habit what we no longer desire for itself, or desire only because we will it. It is not the less true that will, in the beginning, is entirely produced by desire; including in that term the repelling60 influence of pain as well as the attractive one of pleasure. Let us take into consideration, no longer the person who has a confirmed will to do right, but him in whom that virtuous will is still feeble, conquerable by temptation, and not to be fully relied on; by what means can it be strengthened? How can the will to be virtuous, where it does not exist in sufficient force, be implanted or awakened61? Only by making the person desire virtue—by making him think of it in a pleasurable light, or of its absence in a painful one. It is by associating the doing right with pleasure, or the doing wrong with pain, or by eliciting62 and impressing and bringing home to the person's experience the pleasure naturally involved in the one or the pain in the other, that it is possible to call forth63 that will to be virtuous, which, when confirmed, acts without any thought of either pleasure or pain. Will is the child of desire, and passes out of the dominion64 of its parent only to come under that of habit. That which is the result of habit affords no presumption65 of being intrinsically good; and there would be no reason for wishing that the purpose of virtue should become independent of pleasure and pain, were it not that the influence of the pleasurable and painful associations which prompt to virtue is not sufficiently66 to be depended on for unerring constancy of action until it has acquired the support of habit. Both in feeling and in conduct, habit is the only thing which imparts certainty; and it is because of the importance to others of being able to rely absolutely on one's feelings and conduct, and to oneself of being able to rely on one's own, that the will to do right ought to be cultivated into this habitual independence. In other words, this state of the will is a means to good, not intrinsically a good; and does not contradict the doctrine that nothing is a good to human beings but in so far as it is either itself pleasurable, or a means of attaining67 pleasure or averting68 pain.
But if this doctrine be true, the principle of utility is proved. Whether it is so or not, must now be left to the consideration of the thoughtful reader.
点击收听单词发音
1 incapable | |
adj.无能力的,不能做某事的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 premises | |
n.建筑物,房屋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 faculties | |
n.能力( faculty的名词复数 );全体教职员;技巧;院 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 faculty | |
n.才能;学院,系;(学院或系的)全体教学人员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 utilitarian | |
adj.实用的,功利的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 requisite | |
adj.需要的,必不可少的;n.必需品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 apprehend | |
vt.理解,领悟,逮捕,拘捕,忧虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 attainable | |
a.可达到的,可获得的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 aggregate | |
adj.总计的,集合的;n.总数;v.合计;集合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 criteria | |
n.标准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 decided | |
adj.决定了的,坚决的;明显的,明确的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 authentic | |
a.真的,真正的;可靠的,可信的,有根据的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 approbation | |
n.称赞;认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 disinterested | |
adj.不关心的,不感兴趣的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 disinterestedly | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 dispositions | |
安排( disposition的名词复数 ); 倾向; (财产、金钱的)处置; 气质 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 virtuous | |
adj.有品德的,善良的,贞洁的,有效力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 conducive | |
adj.有益的,有助的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 swelling | |
n.肿胀 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 exemption | |
n.豁免,免税额,免除 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 illustrate | |
v.举例说明,阐明;图解,加插图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 intensity | |
n.强烈,剧烈;强度;烈度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 pebbles | |
[复数]鹅卵石; 沙砾; 卵石,小圆石( pebble的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 annexed | |
[法] 附加的,附属的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 semblance | |
n.外貌,外表 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 attainment | |
n.达到,到达;[常pl.]成就,造诣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 noxious | |
adj.有害的,有毒的;使道德败坏的,讨厌的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 blessing | |
n.祈神赐福;祷告;祝福,祝愿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 cultivation | |
n.耕作,培养,栽培(法),养成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 enjoins | |
v.命令( enjoin的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 susceptible | |
adj.过敏的,敏感的;易动感情的,易受感动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 promotion | |
n.提升,晋级;促销,宣传 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 impartially | |
adv.公平地,无私地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 contemplating | |
深思,细想,仔细考虑( contemplate的现在分词 ); 注视,凝视; 考虑接受(发生某事的可能性); 深思熟虑,沉思,苦思冥想 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 derive | |
v.取得;导出;引申;来自;源自;出自 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 acting | |
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 outweighed | |
v.在重量上超过( outweigh的过去式和过去分词 );在重要性或价值方面超过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 positively | |
adv.明确地,断然,坚决地;实在,确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 habitual | |
adj.习惯性的;通常的,惯常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 volition | |
n.意志;决意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 prevailing | |
adj.盛行的;占优势的;主要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 deliberately | |
adv.审慎地;蓄意地;故意地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 amenable | |
adj.经得起检验的;顺从的;对负有义务的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 repelling | |
v.击退( repel的现在分词 );使厌恶;排斥;推开 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 awakened | |
v.(使)醒( awaken的过去式和过去分词 );(使)觉醒;弄醒;(使)意识到 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 eliciting | |
n. 诱发, 引出 动词elicit的现在分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 dominion | |
n.统治,管辖,支配权;领土,版图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 presumption | |
n.推测,可能性,冒昧,放肆,[法律]推定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 attaining | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的现在分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 averting | |
防止,避免( avert的现在分词 ); 转移 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |