We hold from God the gift which, as far as we are concerned, contains all others, Life--physical, intellectual, and moral life.
But life cannot support itself. He who has bestowed6 it, has entrusted7 us with the care of supporting it, of developing it, and of perfecting it. To that end, He has provided us with a collection of wonderful faculties8; He has plunged9 us into the midst of a variety of elements. It is by the application of our faculties to these elements, that the phenomena11 of assimilation and of appropriation12, by which life pursues the circle which has been assigned to it, are realized.
Existence, faculties, assimilation--in other words, personality, liberty, property--this is man. It is of these three things that it may be said, apart from all demagogue subtlety13, that they are anterior14 and superior to all human legislation.
It is not because men have made laws, that personality, liberty, and property exist. On the contrary, it is because personality, liberty, and property exist beforehand, that men make laws.
What, then, is law? As I have said elsewhere, it is the collective organization of the individual right to lawful15 defence.
Nature, or rather God, has bestowed upon every one of us the right to defend his person, his liberty, and his property, since these are the three constituent16 or preserving elements of life; elements, each of which is rendered complete by the others, and cannot be understood without them. For what are our faculties, but the extension of our personality? and what is property, but an extension of our faculties?
If every man has the right of defending, even by force, his person, his liberty, and his property, a number of men have the right to combine together, to extend, to organize a common force, to provide regularly for this defence.
Collective right, then, has its principle, its reason for existing, its lawfulness17, in individual right; and the common force cannot rationally have any other end, or any other mission, than that of the isolated18 forces for which it is substituted. Thus, as the force of an individual cannot lawfully19 touch the person, the liberty, or the property of another individual--for the same reason, the common force cannot lawfully be used to destroy the person, the liberty, or the property of individuals or of classes.
For this perversion21 of force would be, in one case as in the other, in contradiction to our premises22. For who will dare to say that force has been given to us, not to defend our rights, but to annihilate23 the equal rights of our brethren? And if this be not true of every individual force, acting24 independently, how can it be true of the collective force, which is only the organized union of isolated forces?
Nothing, therefore, can be more evident than this:--The law is the organization of the natural right of lawful defence; it is the substitution of collective for individual forces, for the purpose of acting in the sphere in which they have a right to act, of doing what they have a right to do, to secure persons, liberties, and properties, and to maintain each in its right, so as to cause justice to reign25 over all.
And if a people established upon this basis were to exist, it seems to me that order would prevail among them in their acts as well as in their ideas. It seems to me that such a people would have the most simple, the most economical, the least oppressive, the least to be felt, the least responsible, the most just, and, consequently, the most solid Government which could be imagined, whatever its political form might be.
For, under such an administration, every one would feel that he possessed26 all the fulness, as well as all the responsibility of his existence. So long as personal safety was ensured, so long as labour was free, and the fruits of labour secured against all unjust attacks, no one would have any difficulties to contend with in the State. When prosperous, we should not, it is true, have to thank the State for our success; but when unfortunate, we should no more think of taxing it with our disasters, than our peasants think of attributing to it the arrival of hail or of frost. We should know it only by the inestimable blessing28 of Safety.
It may further be affirmed, that, thanks to the non-intervention29 of the State in private affairs, our wants and their satisfactions would develop themselves in their natural order. We should not see poor families seeking for literary instruction before they were supplied with bread. We should not see towns peopled at the expense of rural districts, nor rural districts at the expense of towns. We should not see those great displacements32 of capital, of labour, and of population, which legislative33 measures occasion; displacements, which render so uncertain and precarious34 the very sources of existence, and thus aggravate35 to such an extent the responsibility of Governments.
Unhappily, law is by no means confined to its own department. Nor is it merely in some indifferent and debateable views that it has left its proper sphere. It has done more than this. It has acted in direct opposition37 to its proper end; it has destroyed its own object; it has been employed in annihilating38 that justice which it ought to have established, in effacing39 amongst Rights, that limit which was its true mission to respect; it has placed the collective force in the service of those who wish to traffic, without risk, and without scruple41, in the persons, the liberty, and the property of others; it has converted plunder42 into a right, that it may protect it, and lawful defence into a crime, that it may punish it.
How has this perversion of law been accomplished43? And what has resulted from it?
The law has been perverted through the influence of two very different causes--bare egotism and false philanthropy.
Let us speak of the former.
Self-preservation44 and development is the common aspiration45 of all men, in such a way that if every one enjoyed the free exercise of his faculties and the free disposition46 of their fruits, social progress would be incessant47, uninterrupted, inevitable49.
But there is also another disposition which is common to them. This is, to live and to develop, when they can, at the expense of one another. This is no rash imputation50, emanating51 from a gloomy, uncharitable spirit. History bears witness to the truth of it, by the incessant wars, the migrations52 of races, sacerdotal oppressions, the universality of slavery, the frauds in trade, and the monopolies with which its annals abound53. This fatal disposition has its origin in the very constitution of man--in that primitive54, and universal, and invincible55 sentiment which urges it towards its well-being56, and makes it seek to escape pain.
Man can only derive57 life and enjoyment58 from a perpetual search and appropriation; that is, from a perpetual application of his faculties to objects, or from labour. This is the origin of property.
But yet he may live and enjoy, by seizing and appropriating the productions of the faculties of his fellow-men. This is the origin of plunder.
Now, labour being in itself a pain, and man being naturally inclined to avoid pain, it follows, and history proves it, that wherever plunder is less burdensome than labour, it prevails; and neither religion nor morality can, in this case, prevent it from prevailing59.
When does plunder cease, then? When it becomes less burdensome and more dangerous than labour. It is very evident that the proper aim of law is to oppose the powerful obstacle of collective force to this fatal tendency; that all its measures should be in favour of property, and against plunder.
But the law is made, generally, by one man, or by one class of men. And as law cannot exist without the sanction and the support of a preponderating60 force, it must finally place this force in the hands of those who legislate61.
This inevitable phenomenon, combined with the fatal tendency which, we have said, exists in the heart of man, explains the almost universal perversion of law. It is easy to conceive that, instead of being a check upon injustice62, it becomes its most invincible instrument. It is easy to conceive that, according to the power of the legislator, it destroys for its own profit, and in different degrees, amongst the rest of the community, personal independence by slavery, liberty by oppression, and property by plunder.
It is in the nature of men to rise against the injustice of which they are the victims. When, therefore, plunder is organised by law, for the profit of those who perpetrate it, all the plundered64 classes tend, either by peaceful or revolutionary means, to enter in some way into the manufacturing of laws. These classes, according to the degree of enlightenment at which they have arrived, may propose to themselves two very different ends, when they thus attempt the attainment66 of their political rights; either they may wish to put an end to lawful plunder, or they may desire to take part in it.
Woe67 to the nation where this latter thought prevails amongst the masses, at the moment when they, in their turn, seize upon the legislative power!
Up to that time, lawful plunder has been exercised by the few upon the many, as is the case in countries where the right of legislating68 is confined to a few hands. But now it has become universal, and the equilibrium69 is sought in universal plunder. The injustice which society contains, instead of being rooted out of it, is generalised. As soon as the injured classes have recovered their political rights, their first thought is, not to abolish plunder (this would suppose them to possess enlightenment, which they cannot have), but to organise63 against the other classes, and to their own detriment70, a system of reprisals71,--as if it was necessary, before the reign of justice arrives, that all should undergo a cruel retribution,--some for their iniquity and some for their ignorance.
It would be impossible, therefore, to introduce into society a greater change and a greater evil than this--the conversion72 of the law into an instrument of plunder.
What would be the consequences of such a perversion? It would require volumes to describe them all. We must content ourselves with pointing out the most striking.
In the first place, it would efface73 from everybody's conscience the distinction between justice and injustice.
No society can exist unless the laws are respected to a certain degree, but the safest way to make them respected is to make them respectable. When law and morality are in contradiction to each other, the citizen finds himself in the cruel alternative of either losing his moral sense, or of losing his respect for the law--two evils of equal magnitude, between which it would be difficult to choose.
It is so much in the nature of law to support justice, that in the minds of the masses they are one and the same. There is in all of us a strong disposition to regard what is lawful as legitimate74, so much so, that many falsely derive all justice from law. It is sufficient, then, for the law to order and sanction plunder, that it may appear to many consciences just and sacred. Slavery, protection, and monopoly find defenders75, not only in those who profit by them, but in those who suffer by them. If you suggest a doubt as to the morality of these institutions, it is said directly--"You are a dangerous innovator76, a utopian, a theorist, a despiser of the laws; you would shake the basis upon which society rests."
If you lecture upon morality, or political economy, official bodies will be found to make this request to the Government:--
"That henceforth science be taught not only with sole reference to free exchange (to liberty, property, and justice), as has been the case up to the present time, but also, and especially, with reference to the facts and legislation (contrary to liberty, property, and justice) which regulate French industry.
"That, in public pulpits salaried by the treasury77, the professor abstain78 rigorously from endangering in the slightest degree the respect due to the laws now in force."7
So that if a law exists which sanctions slavery or monopoly, oppression or plunder, in any form whatever, it must not even be mentioned--for how can it be mentioned without damaging the respect which it inspires? Still further, morality and political economy must be taught in connexion with this law--that is, under the supposition that it must be just, only because it is law.
Another effect of this deplorable perversion of the law is, that it gives to human passions and to political struggles, and, in general, to politics, properly so called, an exaggerated preponderance.
I could prove this assertion in a thousand ways. But I shall confine myself, by way of illustration, to bringing it to bear upon a subject which has of late occupied everybody's mind--universal suffrage79.
Whatever may be thought of it by the adepts80 of the school of Rousseau, which professes81 to be very far advanced, but which I consider twenty centuries behind, universal suffrage (taking the word in its strictest sense) is not one of those sacred dogmas with respect to which examination and doubt are crimes.
Serious objections may be made to it.
In the first place, the word universal conceals82 a gross sophism83. There are, in France, 36,000,000 of inhabitants. To make the right of suffrage universal, 36,000,000 of electors should be reckoned. The most extended system reckons only 9,000,000. Three persons out of four, then, are excluded; and more than this, they are excluded by the fourth. Upon what principle is this exclusion84 founded? Upon the principle of incapacity. Universal suffrage, then, means--universal suffrage of those who are capable. In point of fact, who are the capable? Are age, sex, and judicial85 condemnations the only conditions to which incapacity is to be attached?
On taking a nearer view of the subject, we may soon perceive the motive86 which causes the right of suffrage to depend upon the presumption87 of incapacity; the most extended system differing only in this respect from the most restricted, by the appreciation88 of those conditions on which this incapacity depends, and which constitutes, not a difference in principle, but in degree.
If, as the republicans of the Greek and Roman tone pretend, the right of suffrage had fallen to the lot of every one at his birth, it would be an injustice to adults to prevent women and children from voting. Why are they prevented? Because they are presumed to be incapable90. And why is incapacity a motive for exclusion? Because the elector does not reap alone the responsibility of his vote; because every vote engages and affects the community at large; because the community has a right to demand some securities, as regards the acts upon which his well-being and his existence depend.
I know what might be said in answer to this. I know what might be objected. But this is not the place to exhaust a controversy91 of this kind. What I wish to observe is this, that this same controversy (in common with the greater part of political questions) which agitates92, excites, and unsettles the nations, would lose almost all its importance if the law had always been what it ought to be.
In fact, if law were confined to causing all persons, all liberties, and all properties to be respected--if it were merely the organisation94 of individual right and individual defence--if it were the obstacle, the check, the chastisement95 opposed to all oppression, to all plunder--is it likely that we should dispute much, as citizens, on the subject of the greater or less universality of suffrage? Is it likely that it would compromise that greatest of advantages, the public peace? Is it likely that the excluded classes would not quietly wait for their turn? Is it likely that the enfranchised96 classes would be very jealous of their privilege? And is it not clear, that the interest of all being one and the same, some would act without much inconvenience to the others?
But if the fatal principle should come to be introduced, that, under pretence97 of organisation, regulation, protection, or encouragement, the law may take from one party in order to give to another, help itself to the wealth acquired by all the classes that it may increase that of one class, whether that of the agriculturists, the manufacturers, the shipowners, or artists and comedians98; then certainly, in this case, there is no class which may not pretend, and with reason, to place its hand upon the law, which would not demand with fury its right of election and eligibility99, and which would overturn society rather than not obtain it. Even beggars and vagabonds will prove to you that they have an incontestable title to it. They will say--"We never buy wine, tobacco, or salt, without paying the tax, and a part of this tax is given by law in perquisites100 and gratuities101 to men who are richer than we are. Others make use of the law to create an artificial rise in the price of bread, meat, iron, or cloth. Since everybody traffics in law for his own profit, we should like to do the same. We should like to make it produce the right to assistance, which is the poor man's plunder. To effect this, we ought to be electors and legislators, that we may organise, on a large scale, alms for our own class, as you have organised, on a large scale, protection for yours. Don't tell us that you will take our cause upon yourselves, and throw to us 600,000 francs to keep us quiet, like giving us a bone to pick. We have other claims, and, at any rate, we wish to stipulate for ourselves, as other classes have stipulated102 for themselves!" How is this argument to be answered? Yes, as long as it is admitted that the law may be diverted from its true mission, that it may violate property instead of securing it, everybody will be wanting to manufacture law, either to defend himself against plunder, or to organise it for his own profit. The political question will always be prejudicial, predominant, and absorbing; in a word, there will be fighting around the door of the Legislative Palace. The struggle will be no less furious within it. To be convinced of this, it is hardly necessary to look at what passes in the Chambers103 in France and in England; it is enough to know how the question stands.
Is there any need to prove that this odious104 perversion of law is a perpetual source of hatred105 and discord,--that it even tends to social disorganisation? Look at the United States. There is no country in the world where the law is kept more within its proper domain106--which is, to secure to every one his liberty and his property. Therefore, there is no country in the world where social order appears to rest upon a more solid basis. Nevertheless, even in the United States, there are two questions, and only two, which from the beginning have endangered political order. And what are these two questions? That of slavery and that of tariffs107; that is, precisely109 the only two questions in which, contrary to the general spirit of this republic, law has taken the character of a plunderer110. Slavery is a violation111, sanctioned by law, of the rights of the person. Protection is a violation perpetrated by the law upon the rights of property; and certainly it is very remarkable112 that, in the midst of so many other debates, this double legal scourge113, the sorrowful inheritance of the Old World, should be the only one which can, and perhaps will, cause the rupture114 of the union. Indeed, a more astounding115 fact, in the heart of society, cannot be conceived than this:--That law should have become an instrument of injustice. And if this fact occasions consequences so formidable to the United States, where there is but one exception, what must it be with us in Europe, where it is a principle--a system?
M. Montalembert, adopting the thought of a famous proclamation of M. Carlier, said, "We must make war against socialism." And by socialism, according to the definition of M. Charles Dupin, he meant plunder.
But what plunder did he mean? For there are two sorts--extra-legal and legal plunder.
As to extra-legal plunder, such as theft, or swindling, which is defined, foreseen, and punished by the penal116 code, I do not think it can be adorned117 by the name of socialism. It is not this which systematically119 threatens the foundations of society. Besides, the war against this kind of plunder has not waited for the signal of M. Montalembert or M. Carlier. It has gone on since the beginning of the world; France was carrying it on long before the revolution of February--long before the appearance of socialism--with all the ceremonies of magistracy, police, gendarmerie, prisons, dungeons120, and scaffolds. It is the law itself which is conducting this war, and it is to be wished, in my opinion, that the law should always maintain this attitude with respect to plunder.
But this is not the case. The law sometimes takes its own part. Sometimes it accomplishes it with its own hands, in order to save the parties benefited the shame, the danger, and the scruple. Sometimes it places all this ceremony of magistracy, police, gendarmerie, and prisons, at the service of the plunderer, and treats the plundered party, when he defends himself, as the criminal. In a word, there is a legal plunder, and it is, no doubt, this which is meant by M. Montalembert.
This plunder may be only an exceptional blemish121 in the legislation of a people, and in this case, the best thing that can be done is, without so many speeches and lamentations, to do away with it as soon as possible, notwithstanding the clamours of interested parties. But how is it to be distinguished122? Very easily. See whether the law takes from some persons that which belongs to them, to give to others what does not belong to them. See whether the law performs, for the profit of one citizen, and, to the injury of others, an act which this citizen cannot perform without committing a crime. Abolish this law without delay; it is not merely an iniquity--it is a fertile source of iniquities123, for it invites reprisals; and if you do not take care, the exceptional case will extend, multiply, and become systematic118. No doubt the party benefited will exclaim loudly; he will assert his acquired rights. He will say that the State is bound to protect and encourage his industry; he will plead that it is a good thing for the State to be enriched, that it may spend the more, and thus shower down salaries upon the poor workmen. Take care not to listen to this sophistry124, for it is just by the systematising of these arguments that legal plunder becomes systematised.
And this is what has taken place. The delusion125 of the day is to enrich all classes at the expense of each other; it is to generalise plunder under pretence of organising it. Now, legal plunder may be exercised in an infinite multitude of ways. Hence come an infinite multitude of plans for organisation; tariffs, protection, perquisites, gratuities, encouragements, progressive taxation126, gratuitous127 instruction, right to labour, right to profit, right to wages, right to assistance, right to instruments of labour, gratuity128 of credit, &c., &c. And it is all these plans, taken as a whole, with what they have in common, legal, plunder, which takes the name of socialism.
Now socialism, thus defined, and forming a doctrinal body, what other war would you make against it than a war of doctrine129? You find this doctrine false, absurd, abominable130. Refute it. This will be all the more easy, the more false, the more absurd and the more abominable it is. Above all, if you wish to be strong, begin by rooting out of your legislation every particle of socialism which may have crept into it,--and this will be no light work.
M. Montalembert has been reproached with wishing to turn brute131 force against socialism. He ought to be exonerated132 from this reproach, for he has plainly said:--"The war which we must make against socialism must be one which is compatible with the law, honour, and justice."
But how is it that M. Montalembert does not see that he is placing himself in a vicious circle? You would oppose law to socialism. But it is the law which socialism invokes133. It aspires134 to legal, not extra-legal plunder. It is of the law itself, like monopolists of all kinds, that it wants to make an instrument; and when once it has the law on its side, how will you be able to turn the law against it? How will you place it under the power of your tribunals, your gendarmes136, and of your prisons? What will you do then? You wish to prevent it from taking any part in the making of laws. You would keep it outside the Legislative Palace. In this you will not succeed, I venture to prophesy137, so long as legal plunder is the basis of the legislation within.
It is absolutely necessary that this question of legal plunder should be determined138, and there are only three solutions of it:--
1. When the few plunder the many.
3. When nobody plunders anybody.
Partial plunder, universal plunder, absence of plunder, amongst these we have to make our choice. The law can only produce one of these results.
Partial plunder.--This is the system which prevailed so long as the elective privilege was partial--a system which is resorted to to avoid the invasion of socialism.
Universal plunder.--We have been threatened by this system when the elective privilege has become universal; the masses having conceived the idea of making law, on the principle of legislators who had preceded them.
Absence of plunder.--This is the principle of justice, peace, order, stability, conciliation140, and of good sense, which I shall proclaim with all the force of my lungs (which is very inadequate141, alas142!) till the day of my death.
And, in all sincerity143, can anything more be required at the hands of the law? Can the law, whose necessary sanction is force, be reasonably employed upon anything beyond securing to every one his right? I defy any one to remove it from this circle without perverting144 it, and consequently turning force against right. And as this is the most fatal, the most illogical social perversion which can possibly be imagined, it must be admitted that the true solution, so much sought after, of the social problem, is contained in these simple words--Law is organised Justice.
Now it is important to remark, that to organise justice by law, that is to say by force, excludes the idea of organising by law, or by force any manifestation145 whatever of human activity--labour, charity, agriculture, commerce, industry, instruction, the fine arts, or religion; for any one of these organisations would inevitably146 destroy the essential organisation. How, in fact, can we imagine force encroaching upon the liberty of citizens without infringing147 upon justice, and so acting against its proper aim?
Here I am encountering the most popular prejudice of our time. It is not considered enough that law should be just, it must be philanthropic. It is not sufficient that it should guarantee to every citizen the free and inoffensive exercise of his faculties, applied148 to his physical, intellectual, and moral development; it is required to extend well-being, instruction, and morality, directly over the nation. This is the fascinating side of socialism.
But, I repeat it, these two missions of the law contradict each other. We have to choose between them. A citizen cannot at the same time be free and not free. M. de Lamartine wrote to me one day thus:--"Your doctrine is only the half of my programme; you have stopped at liberty, I go on to fraternity." I answered him:--"The second part of your programme will destroy the first." And in fact it is impossible for me to separate the word fraternity from the word voluntary. I cannot possibly conceive fraternity legally enforced, without liberty being legally destroyed, and justice legally trampled149 under foot. Legal plunder has two roots: one of them, as we have already seen, is in human egotism; the other is in false philanthropy.
Before I proceed, I think I ought to explain myself upon the word plunder.8
I do not take it, as it often is taken, in a vague, undefined, relative, or metaphorical150 sense. I use it in its scientific acceptation, and as expressing the opposite idea to property. When a portion of wealth passes out of the hands of him who has acquired it, without his consent, and without compensation, to him who has not created it, whether by force or by artifice151, I say that property is violated, that plunder is perpetrated. I say that this is exactly what the law ought to repress always and everywhere. If the law itself performs the action it ought to repress, I say that plunder is still perpetrated, and even, in a social point of view, under aggravated152 circumstances. In this case, however, he who profits from the plunder is not responsible for it; it is the law, the lawgiver, society itself, and this is where the political danger lies.
It is to be regretted that there is something offensive in the word. I have sought in vain for another, for I would not wish at any time, and especially just now, to add an irritating word to our dissensions; therefore, whether I am believed or not, I declare that I do not mean to accuse the intentions nor the morality of anybody. I am attacking an idea which I believe to be false--a system which appears to me to be unjust; and this is so independent of intentions, that each of us profits by it without wishing it, and suffers from it without being aware of the cause. Any person must write under the influence of party spirit or of fear, who would call in question the sincerity of protectionism, of socialism, and even of communism, which are one and the same plant, in three different periods of its growth. All that can be said is, that plunder is more visible by its partiality in protectionism,9 and by its universality in communism; whence it follows that, of the three systems, socialism is still the most vague, the most undefined, and consequently the most sincere.
Be it as it may, to conclude that legal plunder has one of its roots in false philanthropy, is evidently to put intentions out of the question.
With this understanding, let us examine the value, the origin, and the tendency of this popular aspiration, which pretends to realise the general good by general plunder.
The Socialists153 say, since the law organises justice, why should it not organise labour, instruction, and religion?
Why? Because it could not organise labour, instruction, and religion, without disorganising justice.
For, remember, that law is force, and that consequently the domain of the law cannot lawfully extend beyond the domain of force.
When law and force keep a man within the bounds of justice, they impose nothing upon him but a mere36 negation155. They only oblige him to abstain from doing harm. They violate neither his personality, his liberty, nor his property. They only guard the personality, the liberty, the property of others. They hold themselves on the defensive156; they defend the equal right of all. They fulfil a mission whose harmlessness is evident, whose utility is palpable, and whose legitimacy157 is not to be disputed. This is so true that, as a friend of mine once remarked to me, to say that the aim of the law is to cause justice to reign, is to use an expression which is not rigorously exact. It ought to be said, the aim of the law is to prevent injustice from reigning158. In fact, it is not justice which has an existence of its own, it is injustice. The one results from the absence of the other.
But when the law, through the medium of its necessary agent--force, imposes a form of labour, a method or a subject of instruction, a creed159, or a worship, it is no longer negative; it acts positively160 upon men. It substitutes the will of the legislator for their own will, the initiative of the legislator for their own initiative. They have no need to consult, to compare, or to foresee; the law does all that for them. The intellect is for them a useless lumber161; they cease to be men; they lose their personality, their liberty, their property.
Endeavour to imagine a form of labour imposed by force, which is not a violation of liberty; a transmission of wealth imposed by force, which is not a violation of property. If you cannot succeed in reconciling this, you are bound to conclude that the law cannot organise labour and industry without organising injustice.
When, from the seclusion162 of his cabinet, a politician takes a view of society, he is struck with the spectacle of inequality which presents itself. He mourns over the sufferings which are the lot of so many of our brethren, sufferings whose aspect is rendered yet more sorrowful by the contrast of luxury and wealth.
He ought, perhaps, to ask himself, whether such a social state has not been caused by the plunder of ancient times, exercised in the way of conquests; and by plunder of later times, effected through the medium of the laws? He ought to ask himself whether, granting the aspiration of all men after well-being and perfection, the reign of justice would not suffice to realise the greatest activity of progress, and the greatest amount of equality compatible with that individual responsibility which God has awarded as a just retribution of virtue163 and vice40?
He never gives this a thought. His mind turns towards combinations, arrangements, legal or factitious organisations. He seeks the remedy in perpetuating164 and exaggerating what has produced the evil.
For, justice apart, which we have seen is only a negation, is there any one of these legal arrangements which does not contain the principle of plunder?
You say, "There are men who have no money," and you apply to the law. But the law is not a self-supplied fountain, whence every stream may obtain supplies independently of society. Nothing can enter the public treasury, in favour of one citizen or one class, but what other citizens and other classes have been forced to send to it. If every one draws from it only the equivalent of what he has contributed to it, your law, it is true, is no plunderer, but it does nothing for men who want money--it does not promote equality. It can only be an instrument of equalisation as far as it takes from one party to give to another, and then it is an instrument of plunder. Examine, in this light, the protection of tariffs, prizes for encouragement, right to profit, right to labour, right to assistance, right to instruction, progressive taxation, gratuitousness165 of credit, social workshops, and you will always find at the bottom legal plunder, organised injustice.
You say, "There are men who want knowledge," and you apply to the law. But the law is not a torch which sheds light abroad which is peculiar166 to itself. It extends over a society where there are men who have knowledge, and others who have not; citizens who want to learn, and others who are disposed to teach. It can only do one of two things: either allow a free operation to this kind of transaction, i.e., let this kind of want satisfy itself freely; or else force the will of the people in the matter, and take from some of them sufficient to pay professors commissioned to instruct others gratuitously167. But, in this second case, there cannot fail to be a violation of liberty and property,--legal plunder.
You say, "Here are men who are wanting in morality or religion," and you apply to the law; but law is force, and need I say how far it is a violent and absurd enterprise to introduce force in these matters?
As the result of its systems and of its efforts, it would seem that socialism, notwithstanding all its self-complacency, can scarcely help perceiving the monster of legal plunder. But what does it do? It disguises it cleverly from others, and even from itself, under the seductive names of fraternity, solidarity168, organisation, association. And because we do not ask so much at the hands of the law, because we only ask it for justice, it supposes that we reject fraternity, solidarity, organisation, and association; and they brand us with the name of individualists.
It is not free association, but the forms of association which they would impose upon us.
It is not spontaneous fraternity, but legal fraternity.
It is not providential solidarity, but artificial solidarity, which is only an unjust displacement31 of responsibility.
Socialism, like the old policy from which it emanates170, confounds Government and society. And so, every time we object to a thing being done by Government, it concludes that we object to its being done at all. We disapprove171 of education by the State--then we are against education altogether. We object to a State religion--then we would have no religion at all. We object to an equality which is brought about by the State--then we are against equality, &c., &c. They might as well accuse us of wishing men not to eat, because we object to the cultivation172 of corn by the State.
How is it that the strange idea of making the law produce what it does not contain--prosperity, in a positive sense, wealth, science, religion--should ever have gained ground in the political world? The modern politicians, particularly those of the Socialist154 school, found their different theories upon one common hypothesis; and surely a more strange, a more presumptuous173 notion, could never have entered a human brain.
They divide mankind into two parts. Men in general, except one, form the first; the politician himself forms the second, which is by far the most important.
In fact, they begin by supposing that men are devoid174 of any principle of action, and of any means of discernment in themselves; that they have no moving spring in them; that they are inert175 matter, passive particles, atoms without impulse; at best a vegetation indifferent to its own mode of existence, susceptible176 of receiving, from an exterior177 will and hand, an infinite number of forms, more or less symmetrical, artistic178, and perfected.
Moreover, every one of these politicians does not scruple to imagine that he himself is, under the names of organiser, discoverer, legislator, institutor or founder179, this will and hand, this universal spring, this creative power, whose sublime180 mission it is to gather together these scattered181 materials, that is, men, into society.
Starting from these data, as a gardener, according to his caprice, shapes his trees into pyramids, parasols, cubes, cones182, vases, espaliers, distaffs, or fans; so the Socialist, following his chimera183, shapes poor humanity into groups, series, circles, sub-circles, honeycombs, or social workshops, with all kinds of variations. And as the gardener, to bring his trees into shape, wants hatchets184, pruning-hooks, saws, and shears185, so the politician, to bring society into shape, wants the forces which he can only find in the laws; the law of customs, the law of taxation, the law of assistance, and the law of instruction.
It is so true, that the Socialists look upon mankind as a subject for social combinations, that if, by chance, they are not quite certain of the success of these combinations, they will request a portion of mankind, as a subject to experiment upon. It is well known how popular the idea of trying all systems is, and one of their chiefs has been known seriously to demand of the Constituent Assembly a parish, with all its inhabitants, upon which to make his experiments.
It is thus that an inventor will make a small machine before he makes one of the regular size. Thus the chemist sacrifices some substances, the agriculturist some seed and a corner of his field, to make trial of an idea.
But, then, think of the immeasurable distance between the gardener and his trees, between the inventor and his machine, between the chemist and his substances, between the agriculturist and his seed! The Socialist thinks, in all sincerity, that there is the same distance between himself and mankind.
It is not to be wondered at that the politicians of the nineteenth century look upon society as an artificial production of the legislator's genius. This idea, the result of a classical education, has taken possession of all the thinkers and great writers of our country.
To all these persons, the relations between mankind and the legislator appear to be the same as those which exist between the clay and the potter.
Moreover, if they have consented to recognise in the heart of man a principle of action, and in his intellect a principle of discernment, they have looked upon this gift of God as a fatal one, and thought that mankind, under these two impulses, tended fatally towards ruin. They have taken it for granted, that if abandoned to their own inclinations186, men would only occupy themselves with religion to arrive at atheism187, with instruction to come to ignorance, and with labour and exchange to be extinguished in misery188.
Happily, according to these writers, there are some men, termed governors and legislators, upon whom Heaven has bestowed opposite tendencies, not for their own sake only, but for the sake of the rest of the world.
Whilst mankind tends to evil, they incline to good; whilst mankind is advancing towards darkness, they are aspiring189 to enlightenment; whilst mankind is drawn190 towards vice, they are attracted by virtue. And, this granted, they demand the assistance of force, by means of which they are to substitute their own tendencies for those of the human race.
It is only needful to open, almost at random191, a book on philosophy, polities, or history, to see how strongly this idea--the child of classical studies and the mother of socialism--is rooted in our country; that mankind is merely inert matter, receiving life, organisation, morality, and wealth from power; or, rather, and still worse--that mankind itself tends towards degradation192, and is only arrested in its tendency by the mysterious hand of the legislator. Classical conventionalism shows us everywhere, behind passive society, a hidden power, under the names of Law, or Legislator (or, by a mode of expression which refers to some person or persons of undisputed weight and authority, but not named), which moves, animates193, enriches, and regenerates194 mankind.
"One of the things which was the most strongly impressed (by whom?) upon the mind of the Egyptians, was the love of their country.... Nobody was allowed to be useless to the State; the law assigned to every one his employment, which descended196 from father to son. No one was permitted to have two professions, nor to adopt another.... But there was one occupation which was obliged to be common to all,--this was the study of the laws and of wisdom; ignorance of religion and the political regulations of the country was excused in no condition of life. Moreover, every profession had a district assigned to it (by whom?).... Amongst good laws, one of the best things was, that everybody was taught to observe them (by whom?). Egypt abounded198 with wonderful inventions, and nothing was neglected which could render life comfortable and tranquil199."
Thus men, according to Bossuet, derive nothing from themselves; patriotism200, wealth, inventions, husbandry, science--all come to them by the operation of the laws, or by kings. All they have to do is to be passive. It is on this ground that Bossuet takes exception, when Diodorus accuses the Egyptians of rejecting wrestling and music. "How is that possible," says he, "since these arts were invented by Trismegistus?"
It is the same with the Persians:--
"One of the first cares of the prince was to encourage agriculture.... As there were posts established for the regulation of the armies, so there were offices for the superintending of rural works.... The respect with which the Persians were inspired for royal authority was excessive."
The Greeks, although full of mind, were no less strangers to their own responsibilities; so much so, that of themselves, like dogs and horses, they would not have ventured upon the most simple games. In a classical sense, it is an undisputed thing that everything comes to the people from without.
"The Greeks, naturally full of spirit and courage, had been early cultivated by kings and colonies who had come from Egypt. From them they had learned the exercises of the body, foot races, and horse and chariot races.... The best thing that the Egyptians had taught them was to become docile201, and to allow themselves to be formed by the laws for the public good."
Fenelon.--Reared in the study and admiration202 of antiquity203, and a witness of the power of Louis XIV., Fenelon naturally adopted the idea that mankind should be passive, and that its misfortunes and its prosperities, its virtues204 and its vices205, are caused by the external influence which is exercised upon it by the law, or by the makers206 of the law. Thus, in his Utopia of Salentum, he brings the men, with their interests, their faculties, their desires, and their possessions, under the absolute direction of the legislator. Whatever the subject may be, they themselves have no voice in it--the prince judges for them. The nation is just a shapeless mass, of which the prince is the soul. In him resides the thought, the foresight207, the principle of all organisation, of all progress; on him, therefore, rests all the responsibility.
In proof of this assertion, I might transcribe208 the whole of the tenth book of "Telemachus." I refer the reader to it, and shall content myself with quoting some passages taken at random from this celebrated209 work, to which, in every other respect, I am the first to render justice.
With the astonishing credulity which characterizes the classics, Fenelon, against the authority of reason and of facts, admits the general felicity of the Egyptians, and attributes it, not to their own wisdom, but to that of their kings:--
"We could not turn our eyes to the two shores, without perceiving rich towns and country seats, agreeably situated210; fields which were covered every year, without intermission, with golden crops; meadows full of flocks; labourers bending under the weight of fruits which the earth lavished211 on its cultivators; and shepherds who made the echoes around repeat the soft sounds of their pipes and flutes212. 'Happy,' said Mentor213, 'is that people which is governed by a wise king.'.... Mentor afterwards desired me to remark the happiness and abundance which was spread over all the country of Egypt, where twenty-two thousand cities might be counted. He admired the excellent police regulations of the cities; the justice administered in favour of the poor against the rich; the good education of the children, who were accustomed to obedience214, labour, and the love of arts and letters; the exactness with which all the ceremonies of religion were performed; the disinterestedness215, the desire of honour, the fidelity216 to men, and the fear of the gods, with which every father inspired his children. He could not sufficiently217 admire the prosperous state of the country. 'Happy,' said he, 'is the people whom a wise king rules in such a manner.'"
Fenelon's idyl on Crete is still more fascinating. Mentor is made to say:--
"All that you will see in this wonderful island is the result of the laws of Minos. The education which the children receive renders the body healthy and robust218. They are accustomed, from the first, to a frugal219 and laborious220 life; it is supposed that all the pleasures of sense enervate221 the body and the mind; no other pleasure is presented to them but that of being invincible by virtue, that of acquiring much glory.... there they punish three vices which go unpunished amongst other people--ingratitude, dissimulation223, and avarice. As to pomp and dissipation, there is no need to punish these, for they are unknown in Crete...... No costly224 furniture, no magnificent clothing, no delicious feasts, no gilded225 palaces are allowed."
It is thus that Mentor prepares his scholar to mould and manipulate, doubtless with the most philanthropic intentions, the people of Ithaca, and, to confirm him in these ideas, he gives him the example of Salentum.
It is thus that we receive our first political notions. We are taught to treat men very much as Oliver de Serres teaches farmers to manage and to mix the soil.
Montesquieu.--"To sustain the spirit of commerce, it is necessary that all the laws should favour it; that these same laws, by their regulations in dividing the fortunes in proportion as commerce enlarges them, should place every poor citizen in sufficiently easy circumstances to enable him to work like the others, and every rich citizen in such mediocrity that he must work, in order to retain or to acquire."
Thus the laws are to dispose of all fortunes.
"Although, in a democracy, real equality be the soul of the State, yet it is so difficult to establish, that an extreme exactness in this matter would not always be desirable. It is sufficient that a census226 be established to reduce or fix the differences to a certain point. After which, it is for particular laws to equalise, as it were, the inequality, by burdens imposed upon the rich, and reliefs granted to the poor."
Here, again, we see the equalisation of fortunes by law, that is, by force.
"There were, in Greece, two kinds of republics. One was military, as Laced?mon; the other commercial, as Athens. In the one it was wished (by whom?) that the citizens should be idle: in the other, the love of labour was encouraged.
"It is worth our while to pay a little attention to the extent of genius required by these legislators, that we may see how, by confounding all the virtues, they showed their wisdom to the world. Lycurgus, blending theft with the spirit of justice, the hardest slavery with extreme liberty, the most atrocious sentiments with the greatest moderation, gave stability to his city. He seemed to deprive it of all its resources, arts, commerce, money, and walls; there Was ambition without the hope of rising; there were natural sentiments where the individual was neither child, nor husband, nor father. Chastity even was deprived of modesty227. By this road Sparta was led on to grandeur228 and to glory.
"The phenomenon which we observe in the institutions of Greece has been seen in the midst of the degeneracy and corruption229 of our modern times. An honest legislator has formed a people where probity230 has appeared as natural as bravery among the Spartans232. Mr. Penn is a true Lycurgus, and although the former had peace for his object, and the latter war, they resemble each other in the singular path along which they have led their people, in their influence over free men, in the prejudices which they have overcome, the passions they have subdued233.
"Paraguay furnishes us with another example. Society has been accused of the crime of regarding the pleasure of commanding as the only good of life; but it will always be a noble thing to govern men by making them happy.
"Those who desire to form similar institutions, will establish community of property, as in the republic of Plato, the same reverence234 which he enjoined235 for the gods, separation from strangers for the preservation of morality, and make the city and not the citizens create commerce: they should give our arts without our luxury, our wants without our desires."
Vulgar infatuation may exclaim, if it likes:--"It is Montesquieu! magnificent! sublime!" I am not afraid to express my opinion, and to say:--"What! you have the face to call that fine? It is frightful236! it is abominable! and these extracts, which I might multiply, show that, according to Montesquieu, the persons, the liberties, the property, mankind itself, are nothing but materials to exercise the sagacity of lawgivers."
Rousseau.--Although this politician, the paramount237 authority of the Democrats238, makes the social edifice239 rest upon the general will, no one has so completely admitted the hypothesis of the entire passiveness of human nature in the presence of the lawgiver:--
"If it is true that a great prince is a rare thing, how much more so must a great lawgiver be? The former has only to follow the pattern proposed to him by the latter. This latter is the mechanician who invents the machine; the former is merely the workman who sets it in motion."
And what part have men to act in all this? That of the machine, which is set in motion; or rather, are they not the brute matter of which the machine is made? Thus, between the legislator and the prince, between the prince and his subjects, there are the same relations as those which exist between the agricultural writer and the agriculturist, the agriculturist and the clod. At what a vast height, then, is the politician placed, who rules over legislators themselves, and teaches them their trade in such imperative240 terms as the following:--
"Would you give consistency241 to the State? Bring the extremes together as much as possible. Suffer neither wealthy persons nor beggars.
"If the soil is poor and barren, or the country too much confined for the inhabitants, turn to industry and the arts, whose productions you will exchange for the provisions which you require.... On a good soil, if you are short of inhabitants, give all your attention to agriculture, which multiplies men, and banish242 the arts, which only serve to depopulate the country.... Pay attention to extensive and convenient coasts. Cover the sea with vessels243, and you will have a brilliant and short existence. If your seas wash only inaccessible244 rocks, let the people be barbarous, and eat fish; they will live more quietly, perhaps better, and, most certainly, more happily. In short, besides those maxims245 which are common to all, every people has its own particular circumstances, which demand a legislation peculiar to itself.
"It was thus that the Hebrews formerly246, and the Arabs more recently, had religion for their principal object; that of the Athenians was literature; that of Carthage and Tyre, commerce; of Rhodes, naval247 affairs; of Sparta, war; and of Rome, virtue. The author of the 'Spirit of Laws' has shown the art by which the legislator should frame his institutions towards each of these objects.... But if the legislator, mistaking his object, should take up a principle different from that which arises from the nature of things; if one should tend to slavery, and the other to liberty; if one to wealth, and the other to population; one to peace, and the other to conquests; the laws will insensibly become enfeebled, the Constitution will be impaired248, and the State will be subject to incessant agitations249 until it is destroyed, or becomes changed, and invincible Nature regains250 her empire."
But if Nature is sufficiently invincible to regain251 its empire, why does not Kousseau admit that it had no need of the legislator to gain its empire from the beginning? Why does he not allow that, by obeying their own impulse, men would, of themselves, apply agriculture to a fertile district, and commerce to extensive and commodious252 coasts, without the interference of a Lycurgus, a Solon, or a Rousseau, who would undertake it at the risk of deceiving themselves?
Be that as it may, we see with what a terrible responsibility Rousseau invests inventors, institutors, conductors, and manipulators of societies. He is, therefore, very exacting254 with regard to them.
"He who dares to undertake the institutions of a people, ought to feel that he can, as it were, transform every individual, who is by himself a perfect and solitary255 whole, receiving his life and being from a larger whole of which he forms a part; he must feel that he can change the constitution of man, to fortify256 it, and substitute a partial and moral existence for the physical and independent one which we have all received from nature. In a word, he must deprive man of his own powers, to give him others which are foreign to him."
Poor human nature! What would become of its dignity if it were entrusted to the disciples257 of Rousseau?
Raynal.--"The climate, that is, the air and the soil, is the first element for the legislator. His resources prescribe to him his duties. First, he must consult his local position. A population dwelling258 upon maritime259 shores must have laws fitted for navigation.... If the colony is located in an inland region, a legislator must provide for the nature of the soil, and for its degree of fertility....
"It is more especially in the distribution of property that the wisdom of legislation will appear. As a general rule, and in every country, when a new colony is founded, land should be given to each man, sufficient for the support of his family....
"In an uncultivated island, which you are colonizing260 with children, it will only be needful to let the germs of truth expand in the developments of reason! But when you establish old people in a new country, the skill consists in only allowing it those injurious opinions and customs which it is impossible to cure and correct. If you wish to prevent them from being perpetuated261, you will act upon the rising generation by a general and public education of the children. A prince, or legislator, ought never to found a colony without previously262 sending wise men there to instruct the youth.... In a new colony, every facility is open to the precautions of the legislator who desires to purify the tone and the manners of the people. If he has genius and virtue, the lands and the men which are at his disposal will inspire his soul with a plan of society which a writer can only vaguely263 trace, and in a way which would be subject to the instability of all hypotheses, which are varied264 and complicated by an infinity265 of circumstances too difficult to foresee and to combine."
One would think it was a professor of agriculture who was saying to his pupils--"The climate is the only rule for the agriculturist. His resources dictate266 to him his duties. The first thing he has to consider is his local position. If he is on a clayey soil, he must do so and so. If he has to contend with sand, this is the way in which he must set about it. Every facility is open to the agriculturist who wishes to clear and improve his soil. If he only has the skill, the manure267 which he has at his disposal will suggest to him a plan of operation, which a professor can only vaguely trace, and in a way that would be subject to the uncertainty268 of all hypotheses, which vary and are complicated by an infinity of circumstances too difficult to foresee and to combine."
But, oh! sublime writers, deign269 to remember sometimes that this clay, this sand, this manure, of which you are disposing in so arbitrary a manner, are men, your equals, intelligent and free beings like yourselves, who have received from God, as you have, the faculty270 of seeing, of foreseeing, of thinking, and of judging for themselves!
Mably. (He is supposing the laws to be worn out by time and by the neglect of security, and continues thus):--
"Under these circumstances, we must be convinced that the springs of Government are relaxed. Give them a new tension (it is the reader who is addressed), and the evil will be remedied.... Think lees of punishing the faults than of encouraging the virtues which you want. By this method you will bestow5 upon your republic the vigour271 of youth. Through ignorance of this, a free people has lost its liberty! But if the evil has made so much way that the ordinary magistrates272 are unable to remedy it effectually, have recourse to an extraordinary magistracy, whose time should be short, and its power considerable. The imagination of the citizens requires to be impressed."
In this style he goes on through twenty volumes.
There was a time when, under the influence of teaching like this, which is the root of classical education, every one was for placing himself beyond and above mankind, for the sake of arranging, organising, and instituting it in his own way.
Condillac.--"Take upon yourself, my lord, the character of Lycurgus or of Solon. Before you finish reading this essay, amuse yourself with giving laws to some wild people in America or in Africa. Establish these roving men in fixed273 dwellings274; teach them to keep flocks.... Endeavour to develop the social qualities which nature has implanted in them.... Make them begin to practise the duties of humanity.... Cause the pleasures of the passions to become distasteful to them by punishments, and you will see these barbarians275, with every plan of your legislation, lose a vice and gain a virtue.
"All these people have had laws. But few among them have been happy. Why is this? Because legislators have almost always been ignorant of the object of society, which is, to unite families by a common interest.
"Impartiality276 in law consists in two things:--in establishing equality in the fortunes and in the dignity of the citizens.... In proportion to the degree of equality established by the laws, the dearer will they become to every citizen.... How can avarice, ambition, dissipation, idleness, sloth277, envy, hatred, or jealousy278, agitate93 men who are equal in fortune and dignity, and to whom the laws leave no hope of disturbing their equality?
"What has been told you of the republic of Sparta ought to enlighten you on this question. No other State has had laws more in accordance with the order of nature or of equality."
It is not to be wondered at that the 17th and 18th centuries should have looked upon the human race as inert matter, ready to receive everything, form, figure, impulse, movement, and life, from a great prince, or a great legislator, or a great genius. These ages were reared in the study of antiquity, and antiquity presents everywhere, in Egypt, Persia, Greece, and Rome, the spectacle of a few men moulding mankind according to their fancy, and mankind to this end enslaved by force or by imposture279. And what does this prove? That because men and society are improvable, error, ignorance, despotism, slavery, and superstition280 must be more prevalent in early times. The mistake of the writers quoted above, is not that they have asserted this fact, but that they have proposed it, as a rule, for the admiration and imitation of future generations. Their mistake has been, with an inconceivable absence of discernment, and upon the faith of a puerile281 conventionalism, that they have admitted what is inadmissible, viz., the grandeur, dignity, morality, and well-being of the artificial societies of the ancient world; they have not understood that time produces and spreads enlightenment; and that in proportion to the increase of enlightenment, right ceases to be upheld by force, and society regains possession of herself.
And, in fact, what is the political work which we are endeavouring to promote? It is no other than the instinctive282 effort of every people towards liberty. And what is liberty, whose name can make every heart beat, and which can agitate the world, but the union of all liberties, the liberty of conscience, of instruction, of association, of the press, of locomotion283, of labour, and of exchange; in other words, the free exercise, for all, of all the inoffensive faculties; and again, in other words, the destruction of all despotisms, even of legal despotism, and the reduction of law to its only rational sphere, which is to regulate the individual right of legitimate defence, or to repress injustice?
This tendency of the human race, it must be admitted, is greatly thwarted284, particularly in our country, by the fatal disposition, resulting from classical teaching, and common to all politicians, of placing themselves beyond mankind, to arrange, organise, and regulate it, according to their fancy.
For whilst society is struggling to realise liberty, the great men who place themselves at its head, imbued285 with the principles of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, think only of subjecting it to the philanthropic despotism of their social inventions, and making it bear with docility286, according to the expression of Rousseau, the yoke287 of public felicity, as pictured in their own imaginations.
This was particularly the case in 1789. No sooner was the old system destroyed, than society was to be submitted to other artificial arrangements, always with the same starting-point--the omnipotence288 of the law.
Saint Just.--"The legislator commands the future. It is for him to will for the good of mankind. It is for him to make men what he wishes them to be."
Robespierre.--"The function of Government is to direct the physical and moral powers of the nation towards the object of its institution."
Billaud Varennes.--"A people who are to be restored to liberty must be formed anew. Ancient prejudices must be destroyed, antiquated289 customs changed, depraved affections corrected, inveterate290 vices eradicated291. For this, a strong force and a vehement292 impulse will be necessary.... Citizens, the inflexible293 austerity of Lycurgus created the firm basis of the Spartan231 republic. The feeble and trusting disposition of Solon plunged Athens into slavery. This parallel contains the whole science of Government."
Lepelletier.--"Considering the extent of human degradation, I am convinced of the necessity of effecting an entire regeneration of the race, and, if I may so express myself, of creating a new people."
Men, therefore, are nothing but raw material. It is not for them to will their own improvement. They are not capable of it; according to Saint Just, it is only the legislator who is. Men are merely to be what he wills that they should be. According to Robespierre, who copies Rousseau literally294, the legislator is to begin by assigning the aim of the institutions of the nation. After this, the Government has only to direct all its physical and moral forces towards this end. All this time the nation itself is to remain perfectly295 passive; and Billaud Varennes would teach us that it ought to have no prejudices, affections, nor wants, but such as are authorised by the legislator. He even goes so far as to say that the inflexible austerity of a man is the basis of a republic.
We have seen that, in cases where the evil is so great that the ordinary magistrates are unable to remedy it, Mably recommends a dictatorship, to promote virtue. "Have recourse," says he, "to an extraordinary magistracy, whose time shall be short, and his power considerable. The imagination of the people requires to be impressed." This doctrine has not been neglected. Listen to Robespierre:--
"The principle of the Republican Government is virtue, and the means to be adopted, during its establishment, is terror. We want to substitute, in our country, morality for egotism, probity for honour, principles for customs, duties for decorum, the empire of reason for the tyranny of fashion, contempt of vice for contempt of misfortune, pride for insolence296, greatness of soul for vanity, love of glory for love of money, good people for good company, merit for intrigue297, genius for wit, truth for glitter, the charm of happiness for the weariness of pleasure, the greatness of man for the littleness of the great, a magnanimous, powerful, happy people, for one that is easy, frivolous298, degraded; that is to say, we would substitute all the virtues and miracles of a republic for all the vices and absurdities299 of monarchy300."
At what a vast height above the rest of mankind does Robespierre place himself here! And observe the arrogance301 with which he speaks. He is not content with expressing a desire for a great renovation302 of the human heart, he does not even expect such a result from a regular Government. No; he intends to effect it himself, and by means of terror. The object of the discourse303 from which this puerile and laborious mass of antithesis304 is extracted, was to exhibit the principles of morality which ought to direct a revolutionary Government. Moreover, when Robespierre asks for a dictatorship, it is not merely for the purpose of repelling305 a foreign enemy, or of putting down factions30; it is that he may establish, by means of terror, and as a preliminary to the game of the Constitution, his own principles of morality. He pretends to nothing short of extirpating306 from the country, by means of terror, egotism, honour, customs, decorum, fashion, vanity, the love of money, good company, intrigue, wit, luxury, and misery. It is not until after he, Robespierre, shall have accomplished these miracles, as he rightly calls them, that he will allow the law to regain her empire. Truly, it would be well if these visionaries, who think so much of themselves and so little of mankind, who want to renew everything, would only be content with trying to reform themselves, the task would be arduous307 enough for them. In general, however, these gentlemen, the reformers, legislators, and politicians, do not desire to exercise an immediate308 despotism over mankind. No, they are too moderate and too philanthropic for that. They only contend for the despotism, the absolutism, the omnipotence of the law. They aspire135 only to make the law.
To show how universal this strange disposition has been in France, I had need not only to have copied the whole of the works of Mably, Raynal, Rousseau, Fenelon, and to have made long extracts from Bossuet and Montesquieu, but to have given the entire transactions of the sittings of the Convention, I shall do no such thing, however, but merely refer the reader to them.
It is not to be wondered at that this idea should have suited Buonaparte exceedingly well. He embraced it with ardour, and put it in practice with energy. Playing the part of a chemist, Europe was to him the material for his experiments. But this material reacted against him. More than half undeceived, Buonaparte, at St. Helena, seemed to admit that there is an initiative in every people, and he became less hostile to liberty. Yet this did not prevent him from giving this lesson to his son in his will:--"To govern, is to diffuse309 morality, education, and well-being."
After all this, I hardly need show, by fastidious quotations310, the opinions of Morelly, Babeuf, Owen, Saint Simon, and Fourier. I shall confine myself to a few extracts from Louis Blanc's book on the organisation of labour.
"In our project, society receives the impulse of power." (Page 126.)
In what does the impulse which power gives to society consist? In imposing311 upon it the project of M. Louis Blanc.
On the other hand, society is the human race. The human race, then, is to receive its impulse from M. Louis Blanc.
It is at liberty to do so or not, it will be said. Of course the human race is at liberty to take advice from anybody, whoever it may be. But this is not the way in which M. Louis Blanc understands the thing. He means that his project should be converted into law, and, consequently, forcibly imposed by power.
"In our project, the State has only to give a legislation to labour, by means of which the industrial movement may and ought to be accomplished in all liberty. It (the State) merely places society on an incline (that is all) that it may descend197, when once it is placed there, by the mere force of things, and by the natural course of the established mechanism312."
But what is this incline? One indicated by M. Louis Blanc. Does it not lead to an abyss? No, it leads to happiness. Why, then, does not society go there of itself? Because it does not know what it wants, and it requires an impulse. What is to give it this impulse? Power. And who is to give the impulse to power? The inventor of the machine, M. Louis Blanc.
We shall never get out of this circle--mankind passive, and a great man moving it by the intervention of the law.
Once on this incline, will society enjoy something like liberty? Without a doubt. And what is liberty?
"Once for all: liberty consists, not only in the right granted, but in the power given to man, to exercise, to develop his faculties under the empire of justice, and under the protection of the law.
"And this is no vain distinction; there is a deep meaning in it, and its consequences are not to be estimated. For when once it is admitted that man, to be truly free, must have the power to exercise and develop his faculties, it follows that every member of society has a claim upon it for such instruction as shall enable it to display itself, and for the instruments of labour, without which human activity can find no scope. Now, by whose intervention is society to give to each of its members the requisite313 instruction and the necessary instruments of labour, unless by that of the State?"
Thus, liberty is power. In what does this power consist? In possessing instruction and instruments of labour. Who is to give instruction and instruments of labour? Society, who owes them. By whose intervention is society to give instruments of labour to those who do not possess them?
By the intervention of the State. From whom is the State to obtain them?
It is for the reader to answer this question, and to notice whither all this tends.
One of the strangest phenomena of our time, and one which will probably be a matter of astonishment314 to our descendants, is the doctrine which is founded upon this triple hypothesis: the radical315 passiveness of mankind,--the omnipotence of the law,--the infallibility of the legislator:--this is the sacred symbol of the party which proclaims itself exclusively democratic.
It is true that it professes also to be social.
So far as it is social, it places it beneath the mud.
Are political rights under discussion? Is a legislator to be chosen? Oh! then the people possess science by instinct: they are gifted with an admirable tact317; their will is always right; the general will cannot err48. Suffrage cannot be too universal. Nobody is under any responsibility to society. The will and the capacity to choose well are taken for granted. Can the people be mistaken? Are we not living in an age of enlightenment? What! are the people to be always kept in leading strings318? Have they not acquired their rights at the cost of effort and sacrifice? Have they not given sufficient proof of intelligence and wisdom? Are they not arrived at maturity319? Are they not in a state to judge for themselves? Do they not know their own interest? Is there a man or a class who would dare to claim the right of putting himself in the place of the people, of deciding and of acting for them? No, no; the people would be free, and they shall be so. They wish to conduct their own affairs, and they shall do so.
But when once the legislator is duly elected, then indeed the style of his speech alters. The nation is sent back into passiveness, inertness320, nothingness, and the legislator takes possession of omnipotence. It is for him to invent, for him to direct, for him to impel321, for him to organise. Mankind has nothing to do but to submit; the hour of despotism has struck. And we must observe that this is decisive; for the people, just before so enlightened, so moral, so perfect, have no inclinations at all, or, if they have any, they all lead them downwards322 towards degradation. And yet they ought to have a little liberty! But are we not assured, by M. Considerant, that liberty leads fatally to monopoly? Are we not told that liberty is competition? and that competition, according to M. Louis Blanc, is a system of extermination323 for the people, and of ruination for trade? For that reason people are exterminated325 and ruined in proportion as they are free--take, for example, Switzerland, Holland, England, and the United States? Does not M. Louis Blanc tell us again, that competition leads to monopoly, and that, for the same reason, cheapness leads to exorbitant326 prices? That competition tends to drain the sources of consumption, and urges production to a destructive activity? That competition forces production to increase, and consumption to decrease;--whence it follows that free people produce for the sake of not consuming; that there is nothing but oppression and madness among them; and that it is absolutely necessary for M. Louis Blanc to see to it?
What sort of liberty should be allowed to men? Liberty of conscience?--But we should see them all profiting by the permission to become atheists. Liberty of education?--But parents would be paying professors to teach their sons immorality327 and error; besides, if we are to believe M. Thiers, education, if left to the national liberty, would cease to be national, and we should be educating our children in the ideas of the Turks or Hindoos, instead of which, thanks to the legal despotism of the universities, they have the good fortune to be educated in the noble ideas of the Romans. Liberty of labour?--But this is only competition, whose effect is to leave all productions unconsumed, to exterminate324 the people, and to ruin the tradesmen. The liberty of exchange?--But it is well known that the protectionists have shown, over and over again, that a man must be ruined when he exchanges freely, and that to become rich it is necessary to exchange without liberty. Liberty of association?--But, according to the socialist doctrine, liberty and association exclude each other, for the liberty of men is attacked just to force them to associate.
You must see, then, that the socialist democrats cannot in conscience allow men any liberty, because, by their own nature, they tend in every instance to all kinds of degradation and demoralisation.
We are therefore left to conjecture328, in this case, upon what foundation universal suffrage is claimed for them with so much importunity329.
The pretensions330 of organisers suggest another question, which I have often asked them, and to which I am not aware that I ever received an answer:--Since the natural tendencies of mankind are so bad that it is not safe to allow them liberty, how comes it to pass that the tendencies of organisers are always good? Do not the legislators and their agents form a part of the human race? Do they consider that they are composed of different materials from the rest of mankind? They say that society, when left to itself, rushes to inevitable destruction, because its instincts are perverse331. They pretend, to stop it in its downward course, and to give it a better direction. They have, therefore, received from heaven, intelligence and virtues which place them beyond and above mankind: let them show their title to this superiority. They would be our shepherds, and we are to be their flock. This arrangement presupposes in them a natural superiority, the right to which we are fully20 justified332 in calling upon them to prove.
You must observe that I am not contending against their right to invent social combinations, to propagate them, to recommend them, and to try them upon themselves, at their own expense and risk; but I do dispute their right to impose them upon us through the medium of the law, that is, by force and by public taxes.
I would not insist upon the Cabetists, the Fourierists, the Proudhonians, the Universitaries, and the Protectionists renouncing333 their own particular ideas; I would only have them renounce334 that idea which is common to them all,--viz., that of subjecting us by force to their own groups and series to their social workshops, to their gratuitous bank to their Gr?co-Romano morality, and to their commercial restrictions335. I would ask them to allow us the faculty of judging of their plans, and not to oblige us to adopt them, if we find that they hurt our interests or are repugnant to our consciences.
To presume to have recourse to power and taxation, besides being oppressive and unjust, implies further, the injurious supposition that the organiser is infallible, and mankind incompetent336.
And if mankind is not competent to judge for itself, why do they talk so much about universal suffrage?
This contradiction in ideas is unhappily to be found also in facts; and whilst the French nation has preceded all others in obtaining its rights, or rather its political claims, this has by no means prevented it from being more governed, and directed, and imposed upon, and fettered337, and cheated, than any other nation. It is also the one, of all others, where revolutions are constantly to be dreaded338, and it is perfectly natural that it should be so.
So long as this idea is retained, which is admitted by all our politicians, and so energetically expressed by M. Louis Blanc in these words--"Society receives its impulse from power;" so long as men consider themselves as capable of feeling, yet passive--incapable of raising themselves by their own discernment and by their own energy to any morality, or well-being, and while they expect everything from the law; in a word, while they admit that their relations with the State are the same as those of the flock with the shepherd, it is clear that the responsibility of power is immense. Fortune and misfortune, wealth and destitution339, equality and inequality, all proceed from it. It is charged with everything, it undertakes everything, it does everything; therefore it has to answer for everything. If we are happy, it has a right to claim our gratitude222; but if we are miserable340, it alone must bear the blame. Are not our persons and property, in fact, at its disposal? Is not the law omnipotent341? In creating the universitary monopoly, it has engaged to answer the expectations of fathers of families who have been deprived of liberty; and if these expectations are disappointed, whose fault is it? In regulating industry, it has engaged to make it prosper27, otherwise it would have been absurd to deprive it of its liberty; and if it suffers, whose fault is it? In pretending to adjust the balance of commerce by the game of tariffs, it engages to make it prosper; and if, so far from prospering342, it is destroyed, whose fault is it? In granting its protection to maritime armaments in exchange for their liberty, it has engaged to render them lucrative343; if they become burdensome, whose fault is it?
Thus, there is not a grievance344 in the nation for which the Government does not voluntarily make itself responsible. Is it to be wondered at that every failure threatens to cause a revolution?
And what is the remedy proposed? To extend indefinitely the dominion345 of the law, i.e., the responsibility of Government. But if the Government engages to raise and to regulate wages, and is not able to do it; if it engages to assist all those who are in want, and is not able to do it; if it engages to provide an asylum346 for every labourer, and is not able to do it; if it engages to offer to all such as are eager to borrow, gratuitous credit, and is not able to do it; if, in words which we regret should have escaped the pen of M. de Lamartine, "the State considers that its mission is to enlighten, to develop, to enlarge, to strengthen, to spiritualize, and to sanctify the soul of the people,"--if it fails in this, is it not evident that after every disappointment, which, alas! is more than probable, there will be a no less inevitable revolution?
I shall now resume the subject by remarking, that immediately after the economical part10 of the question, and at the entrance of the political part, a leading question presents itself? It is the following:--
What is law? What ought it to be? What is its domain? What are its limits? Where, in fact, does the prerogative347 of the legislator stop?
I have no hesitation348 in answering, Law is common force organised to prevent injustice;--in short, Law is Justice.
It is not true that the legislator has absolute power over our persons and property, since they pre-exist, and his work is only to secure them from injury.
It is not true that the mission of the law is to regulate our consciences, our ideas, our will, our education, our sentiments, our works, our exchanges, our gifts, our enjoyments349. Its mission is to prevent the rights of one from interfering350 with those of another, in any one of these things.
Law, because it has force for its necessary sanction, can only have as its lawful domain the domain of force, which is justice.
And as every individual has a right to have recourse to force only in cases of lawful defence, so collective force, which is only the union of individual forces, cannot be rationally used for any other end.
The law, then, is solely351 the organisation of individual rights, which existed before legitimate defence.
Law is justice.
So far from being able to oppress the persons of the people, or to plunder their property, even for a philanthropic end, its mission is to protect the former, and to secure to them the possession of the latter.
It must not be said, either, that it may be philanthropic, so long as it abstains352 from all oppression; for this is a contradiction. The law cannot avoid acting upon our persons and property; if it does not secure them, it violates them if it touches them.
The law is justice.
Nothing can be more clear and simple, more perfectly defined and bounded, or more visible to every eye; for justice is a given quantity, immutable353 and unchangeable, and which admits of neither increase or diminution354.
Depart from this point, make the law religious, fraternal, equalising, industrial, literary, or artistic, and you will be lost in vagueness and uncertainty; you will be upon unknown ground, in a forced Utopia, or, which is worse, in the midst of a multitude of Utopias, striving to gain possession of the law, and to impose it upon you; for fraternity and philanthropy have no fixed limits, like justice. Where will you stop? Where is the law to stop? One person, as M. de Saint Cricq, will only extend his philanthropy to some of the industrial classes, and will require the law to dispose of the consumers in favour of the producers. Another, like M. Considerant, will take up the cause of the working classes, and claim for them by means of the law, at a fixed rate, clothing, lodging355, food, and everything necessary for the support of life. A third, as, M. Louis Blanc, will say, and with reason, that this would be an incomplete fraternity, and that the law ought to provide them with instruments of labour and the means of instruction. A fourth will observe that such an arrangement still leaves room for inequality, and that the law ought to introduce into the most remote hamlets luxury, literature, and the arts. This is the high road to communism; in other words, legislation will be--what it now is--the battle-field for everybody's dreams and everybody's covetousness356.
Law is justice.
In this proposition we represent to ourselves a simple, immovable Government. And I defy any one to tell me whence the thought of a revolution, an insurrection, or a simple disturbance357 could arise against a public force confined to the repression358 of injustice. Under such a system, there would be more well-being, and this well-being would be more equally distributed; and as to the sufferings inseparable from humanity, no one would think of accusing the Government of them, for it would be as innocent of them as it is of the variations of the temperature. Have the people ever been known to rise against the court of repeals359, or assail360 the justices of the peace, for the sake of claiming the rate of wages, gratuitous credit, instruments of labour, the advantages of the tariff108, or the social workshop? They know perfectly well that these combinations are beyond the jurisdiction361 of the justices of the peace, and they would soon learn that they are not within the jurisdiction of the law.
But if the law were to be made upon the principle of fraternity, if it were to be proclaimed that from it proceed all benefits and all evils--that it is responsible for every individual grievance and for every social inequality--then you open the door to an endless succession of complaints, irritations362, troubles, and revolutions.
Law is justice.
And it would be very strange if it could properly be anything else! Is not justice right? Are not rights equal? With what show of right can the law interfere253 to subject me to the social plans of MM. Mimerel, de Melun, Thiers, or Louis Blanc, rather than to subject these gentlemen to my plans? Is it to be supposed that Nature has not bestowed upon me sufficient imagination to invent a Utopia too? Is it for the law to make choice of one amongst so many fancies, and to make use of the public force in its service?
Law is justice.
And let it not be said, as it continually is, that the law, in this sense, would be atheistic363, individual, and heartless, and that it would make mankind wear its own image. This is an absurd conclusion, quite worthy364 of the governmental infatuation which sees mankind in the law.
What then? Does it follow that, if we are free, we shall cease to act? Does it follow, that if we do not receive an impulse from the law, we shall receive no impulse at all? Does it follow, that if the law confines itself to securing to us the free exercise of our faculties, our faculties will be paralyzed? Does it follow, that if the law does not impose upon us forms of religion, modes of association, methods of instruction, rules for labour, directions for exchange, and plans for charity, we shall plunge10 eagerly into atheism, isolation365, ignorance, misery, and egotism? Does it follow, that we shall no longer recognise the power and goodness of God; that we shall cease to associate together, to help each other, to love and assist our unfortunate brethren, to study the secrets of nature, and to aspire after perfection in our existence?
Law is justice.
And it is under the law of justice, under the reign of right, under the influence of liberty, security, stability, and responsibility, that every man will attain65 to the measure of his worth, to all the dignity of his being, and that mankind will accomplish, with order and with calmness--slowly, it is true, but with certainty--the progress decreed to it.
I believe that my theory is correct; for whatever be the question upon which I am arguing, whether it be religious, philosophical366, political, or economical; whether it affects well-being, morality, equality, right, justice, progress, responsibility, property, labour, exchange, capital, wages, taxes, population, credit, or Government; at whatever point of the scientific horizon I start from, I invariably come to the same thing--the solution of the social problem is in liberty.
And have I not experience on my side? Cast your eye over the globe. Which are the happiest, the most moral, and the most peaceable nations? Those where the law interferes367 the least with private activity; where the Government is the least felt; where individuality has the most scope, and public opinion the most influence; where the machinery368 of the administration is the least important and the least complicated; where taxation is lightest and least unequal, popular discontent the least excited and the least justifiable369; where the responsibility of individuals and classes is the most active, and where, consequently, if morals are not in a perfect state, at any rate they tend incessantly370 to correct themselves; where transactions, meetings, and associations are the least fettered; where labour, capital, and production suffer the least from artificial displacements; where mankind follows most completely its own natural course; where the thought of God prevails the most over the inventions of men; those, in short, who realise the most nearly this idea--That within the limits of right, all should flow from the free, perfectible, and voluntary action of man; nothing be attempted by the law or by force, except the administration of universal justice.
I cannot avoid coming to this conclusion--that there are too many great men in the world; there are too many legislators, organisers, institutors of society, conductors of the people, fathers of nations, &c., &c. Too many persons place themselves above mankind, to rule and patronize it; too many persons make a trade of attending to it. It will be answered:--"You yourself are occupied upon it all this time." Very true. But it must be admitted that it is in another sense entirely that I am speaking; and if I join the reformers it is solely for the purpose of inducing them to relax their hold.
I am not doing as Vaucauson did with his automaton371, but as a physiologist372 does with the organisation of the human frame; I would study and admire it.
I am acting with regard to it in the spirit which animated373 a celebrated traveller. He found himself in the midst of a savage374 tribe. A child had just been born, and a crowd of soothsayers, magicians, and quacks375 were around it, armed with rings, hooks, and bandages. One said--"This child will never smell the perfume of a calumet, unless I stretch his nostrils376." Another said--"He will be without the sense of hearing, unless I draw his ears down to his shoulders." A third said--"He will never see the light of the sun, unless I give his eyes an oblique377 direction." A fourth said--"He will never be upright, unless I bend his legs." A fifth said--"He will not be able to think, unless I press his brain." "Stop!" said the traveller. "Whatever God does, is well done; do not pretend to know more than He; and as He has given organs to this frail378 creature, allow those organs to develop themselves, to strengthen themselves by exercise, use, experience, and liberty."
God has implanted in mankind, also, all that is necessary to enable it to accomplish its destinies. There is a providential social physiology379, as well as a providential human physiology. The social organs are constituted so as to enable them to develop harmoniously380 in the grand air of liberty. Away, then, with quacks and organisers! Away with their rings, and their chains, and their hooks, and their pincers! Away with their artificial methods! Away with their social workshops, their governmental whims381, their centralization, their tariffs, their universities, their State religions, their gratuitous or monopolising banks, their limitations, their restrictions, their moralisations, and their equalisation by taxation! And now, after having vainly inflicted382 upon the social body so many systems, let them end where they ought to have begun--reject all systems, and make trial of liberty--of liberty, which is an act of faith in God and in His work.
The End
点击收听单词发音
1 perverted | |
adj.不正当的v.滥用( pervert的过去式和过去分词 );腐蚀;败坏;使堕落 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 avarice | |
n.贪婪;贪心 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 iniquity | |
n.邪恶;不公正 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 bestow | |
v.把…赠与,把…授予;花费 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 bestowed | |
赠给,授予( bestow的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 entrusted | |
v.委托,托付( entrust的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 faculties | |
n.能力( faculty的名词复数 );全体教职员;技巧;院 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 plunged | |
v.颠簸( plunge的过去式和过去分词 );暴跌;骤降;突降 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 plunge | |
v.跳入,(使)投入,(使)陷入;猛冲 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 appropriation | |
n.拨款,批准支出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 subtlety | |
n.微妙,敏锐,精巧;微妙之处,细微的区别 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 anterior | |
adj.较早的;在前的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 lawful | |
adj.法律许可的,守法的,合法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 constituent | |
n.选民;成分,组分;adj.组成的,构成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 lawfulness | |
法制,合法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 isolated | |
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 lawfully | |
adv.守法地,合法地;合理地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 perversion | |
n.曲解;堕落;反常 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 premises | |
n.建筑物,房屋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 annihilate | |
v.使无效;毁灭;取消 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 acting | |
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 reign | |
n.统治时期,统治,支配,盛行;v.占优势 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 prosper | |
v.成功,兴隆,昌盛;使成功,使昌隆,繁荣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 blessing | |
n.祈神赐福;祷告;祝福,祝愿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 intervention | |
n.介入,干涉,干预 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 factions | |
组织中的小派别,派系( faction的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 displacement | |
n.移置,取代,位移,排水量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 displacements | |
n.取代( displacement的名词复数 );替代;移位;免职 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 legislative | |
n.立法机构,立法权;adj.立法的,有立法权的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 precarious | |
adj.不安定的,靠不住的;根据不足的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 aggravate | |
vt.加重(剧),使恶化;激怒,使恼火 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 annihilating | |
v.(彻底)消灭( annihilate的现在分词 );使无效;废止;彻底击溃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 effacing | |
谦逊的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 scruple | |
n./v.顾忌,迟疑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 plunder | |
vt.劫掠财物,掠夺;n.劫掠物,赃物;劫掠 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 accomplished | |
adj.有才艺的;有造诣的;达到了的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 preservation | |
n.保护,维护,保存,保留,保持 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 aspiration | |
n.志向,志趣抱负;渴望;(语)送气音;吸出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 disposition | |
n.性情,性格;意向,倾向;排列,部署 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 incessant | |
adj.不停的,连续的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 err | |
vi.犯错误,出差错 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 inevitable | |
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 imputation | |
n.归罪,责难 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 emanating | |
v.从…处传出,传出( emanate的现在分词 );产生,表现,显示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 migrations | |
n.迁移,移居( migration的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 abound | |
vi.大量存在;(in,with)充满,富于 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 invincible | |
adj.不可征服的,难以制服的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 well-being | |
n.安康,安乐,幸福 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 derive | |
v.取得;导出;引申;来自;源自;出自 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 enjoyment | |
n.乐趣;享有;享用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 prevailing | |
adj.盛行的;占优势的;主要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 preponderating | |
v.超过,胜过( preponderate的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 legislate | |
vt.制定法律;n.法规,律例;立法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 injustice | |
n.非正义,不公正,不公平,侵犯(别人的)权利 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 organise | |
vt.组织,安排,筹办 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 plundered | |
掠夺,抢劫( plunder的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 attainment | |
n.达到,到达;[常pl.]成就,造诣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 woe | |
n.悲哀,苦痛,不幸,困难;int.用来表达悲伤或惊慌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 legislating | |
v.立法,制定法律( legislate的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 equilibrium | |
n.平衡,均衡,相称,均势,平静 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 detriment | |
n.损害;损害物,造成损害的根源 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 reprisals | |
n.报复(行为)( reprisal的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 conversion | |
n.转化,转换,转变 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 efface | |
v.擦掉,抹去 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 legitimate | |
adj.合法的,合理的,合乎逻辑的;v.使合法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 defenders | |
n.防御者( defender的名词复数 );守卫者;保护者;辩护者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 innovator | |
n.改革者;创新者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 treasury | |
n.宝库;国库,金库;文库 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 abstain | |
v.自制,戒绝,弃权,避免 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 suffrage | |
n.投票,选举权,参政权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 adepts | |
n.专家,能手( adept的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 professes | |
声称( profess的第三人称单数 ); 宣称; 公开表明; 信奉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 conceals | |
v.隐藏,隐瞒,遮住( conceal的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 sophism | |
n.诡辩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 exclusion | |
n.拒绝,排除,排斥,远足,远途旅行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 judicial | |
adj.司法的,法庭的,审判的,明断的,公正的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 presumption | |
n.推测,可能性,冒昧,放肆,[法律]推定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 appreciation | |
n.评价;欣赏;感谢;领会,理解;价格上涨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 stipulate | |
vt.规定,(作为条件)讲定,保证 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 incapable | |
adj.无能力的,不能做某事的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 controversy | |
n.争论,辩论,争吵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 agitates | |
搅动( agitate的第三人称单数 ); 激怒; 使焦虑不安; (尤指为法律、社会状况的改变而)激烈争论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 agitate | |
vi.(for,against)煽动,鼓动;vt.搅动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 organisation | |
n.组织,安排,团体,有机休 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 chastisement | |
n.惩罚 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 enfranchised | |
v.给予选举权( enfranchise的过去式和过去分词 );(从奴隶制中)解放 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 pretence | |
n.假装,作假;借口,口实;虚伪;虚饰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 comedians | |
n.喜剧演员,丑角( comedian的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 eligibility | |
n.合格,资格 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 perquisites | |
n.(工资以外的)财务补贴( perquisite的名词复数 );额外收入;(随职位而得到的)好处;利益 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 gratuities | |
n.报酬( gratuity的名词复数 );小账;小费;养老金 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 stipulated | |
vt.& vi.规定;约定adj.[法]合同规定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 chambers | |
n.房间( chamber的名词复数 );(议会的)议院;卧室;会议厅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 odious | |
adj.可憎的,讨厌的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 hatred | |
n.憎恶,憎恨,仇恨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 domain | |
n.(活动等)领域,范围;领地,势力范围 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 tariffs | |
关税制度; 关税( tariff的名词复数 ); 关税表; (旅馆或饭店等的)收费表; 量刑标准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 tariff | |
n.关税,税率;(旅馆、饭店等)价目表,收费表 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 plunderer | |
掠夺者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 violation | |
n.违反(行为),违背(行为),侵犯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 remarkable | |
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 scourge | |
n.灾难,祸害;v.蹂躏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 rupture | |
n.破裂;(关系的)决裂;v.(使)破裂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 astounding | |
adj.使人震惊的vt.使震惊,使大吃一惊astound的现在分词) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 penal | |
adj.刑罚的;刑法上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 adorned | |
[计]被修饰的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 systematic | |
adj.有系统的,有计划的,有方法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 systematically | |
adv.有系统地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 dungeons | |
n.地牢( dungeon的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 blemish | |
v.损害;玷污;瑕疵,缺点 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 iniquities | |
n.邪恶( iniquity的名词复数 );极不公正 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 sophistry | |
n.诡辩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 delusion | |
n.谬见,欺骗,幻觉,迷惑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 taxation | |
n.征税,税收,税金 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 gratuitous | |
adj.无偿的,免费的;无缘无故的,不必要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 gratuity | |
n.赏钱,小费 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 abominable | |
adj.可厌的,令人憎恶的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 brute | |
n.野兽,兽性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 exonerated | |
v.使免罪,免除( exonerate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 invokes | |
v.援引( invoke的第三人称单数 );行使(权利等);祈求救助;恳求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 aspires | |
v.渴望,追求( aspire的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 aspire | |
vi.(to,after)渴望,追求,有志于 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 gendarmes | |
n.宪兵,警官( gendarme的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 prophesy | |
v.预言;预示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 plunders | |
掠夺,抢劫( plunder的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 conciliation | |
n.调解,调停 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141 inadequate | |
adj.(for,to)不充足的,不适当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142 alas | |
int.唉(表示悲伤、忧愁、恐惧等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143 sincerity | |
n.真诚,诚意;真实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144 perverting | |
v.滥用( pervert的现在分词 );腐蚀;败坏;使堕落 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145 manifestation | |
n.表现形式;表明;现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146 inevitably | |
adv.不可避免地;必然发生地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147 infringing | |
v.违反(规章等)( infringe的现在分词 );侵犯(某人的权利);侵害(某人的自由、权益等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149 trampled | |
踩( trample的过去式和过去分词 ); 践踏; 无视; 侵犯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150 metaphorical | |
a.隐喻的,比喻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151 artifice | |
n.妙计,高明的手段;狡诈,诡计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
152 aggravated | |
使恶化( aggravate的过去式和过去分词 ); 使更严重; 激怒; 使恼火 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
153 socialists | |
社会主义者( socialist的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
154 socialist | |
n.社会主义者;adj.社会主义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
155 negation | |
n.否定;否认 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
156 defensive | |
adj.防御的;防卫的;防守的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
157 legitimacy | |
n.合法,正当 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
158 reigning | |
adj.统治的,起支配作用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
159 creed | |
n.信条;信念,纲领 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
160 positively | |
adv.明确地,断然,坚决地;实在,确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
161 lumber | |
n.木材,木料;v.以破旧东西堆满;伐木;笨重移动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
162 seclusion | |
n.隐遁,隔离 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
163 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
164 perpetuating | |
perpetuate的现在进行式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
165 gratuitousness | |
n.gratuitous(免费的,无偿的,无报酬的,不收酬劳的)的变形 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
166 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
167 gratuitously | |
平白 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
168 solidarity | |
n.团结;休戚相关 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
169 repudiate | |
v.拒绝,拒付,拒绝履行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
170 emanates | |
v.从…处传出,传出( emanate的第三人称单数 );产生,表现,显示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
171 disapprove | |
v.不赞成,不同意,不批准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
172 cultivation | |
n.耕作,培养,栽培(法),养成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
173 presumptuous | |
adj.胆大妄为的,放肆的,冒昧的,冒失的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
174 devoid | |
adj.全无的,缺乏的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
175 inert | |
adj.无活动能力的,惰性的;迟钝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
176 susceptible | |
adj.过敏的,敏感的;易动感情的,易受感动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
177 exterior | |
adj.外部的,外在的;表面的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
178 artistic | |
adj.艺术(家)的,美术(家)的;善于艺术创作的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
179 Founder | |
n.创始者,缔造者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
180 sublime | |
adj.崇高的,伟大的;极度的,不顾后果的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
181 scattered | |
adj.分散的,稀疏的;散步的;疏疏落落的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
182 cones | |
n.(人眼)圆锥细胞;圆锥体( cone的名词复数 );球果;圆锥形东西;(盛冰淇淋的)锥形蛋卷筒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
183 chimera | |
n.神话怪物;梦幻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
184 hatchets | |
n.短柄小斧( hatchet的名词复数 );恶毒攻击;诽谤;休战 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
185 shears | |
n.大剪刀 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
186 inclinations | |
倾向( inclination的名词复数 ); 倾斜; 爱好; 斜坡 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
187 atheism | |
n.无神论,不信神 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
188 misery | |
n.痛苦,苦恼,苦难;悲惨的境遇,贫苦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
189 aspiring | |
adj.有志气的;有抱负的;高耸的v.渴望;追求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
190 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
191 random | |
adj.随机的;任意的;n.偶然的(或随便的)行动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
192 degradation | |
n.降级;低落;退化;陵削;降解;衰变 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
193 animates | |
v.使有生气( animate的第三人称单数 );驱动;使栩栩如生地动作;赋予…以生命 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
194 regenerates | |
n.新生,再生( regenerate的名词复数 )v.新生,再生( regenerate的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
195 quotation | |
n.引文,引语,语录;报价,牌价,行情 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
196 descended | |
a.为...后裔的,出身于...的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
197 descend | |
vt./vi.传下来,下来,下降 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
198 abounded | |
v.大量存在,充满,富于( abound的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
199 tranquil | |
adj. 安静的, 宁静的, 稳定的, 不变的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
200 patriotism | |
n.爱国精神,爱国心,爱国主义 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
201 docile | |
adj.驯服的,易控制的,容易教的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
202 admiration | |
n.钦佩,赞美,羡慕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
203 antiquity | |
n.古老;高龄;古物,古迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
204 virtues | |
美德( virtue的名词复数 ); 德行; 优点; 长处 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
205 vices | |
缺陷( vice的名词复数 ); 恶习; 不道德行为; 台钳 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
206 makers | |
n.制造者,制造商(maker的复数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
207 foresight | |
n.先见之明,深谋远虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
208 transcribe | |
v.抄写,誉写;改编(乐曲);复制,转录 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
209 celebrated | |
adj.有名的,声誉卓著的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
210 situated | |
adj.坐落在...的,处于某种境地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
211 lavished | |
v.过分给予,滥施( lavish的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
212 flutes | |
长笛( flute的名词复数 ); 细长香槟杯(形似长笛) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
213 mentor | |
n.指导者,良师益友;v.指导 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
214 obedience | |
n.服从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
215 disinterestedness | |
参考例句: |
|
|
216 fidelity | |
n.忠诚,忠实;精确 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
217 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
218 robust | |
adj.强壮的,强健的,粗野的,需要体力的,浓的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
219 frugal | |
adj.节俭的,节约的,少量的,微量的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
220 laborious | |
adj.吃力的,努力的,不流畅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
221 enervate | |
v.使虚弱,使无力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
222 gratitude | |
adj.感激,感谢 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
223 dissimulation | |
n.掩饰,虚伪,装糊涂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
224 costly | |
adj.昂贵的,价值高的,豪华的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
225 gilded | |
a.镀金的,富有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
226 census | |
n.(官方的)人口调查,人口普查 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
227 modesty | |
n.谦逊,虚心,端庄,稳重,羞怯,朴素 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
228 grandeur | |
n.伟大,崇高,宏伟,庄严,豪华 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
229 corruption | |
n.腐败,堕落,贪污 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
230 probity | |
n.刚直;廉洁,正直 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
231 spartan | |
adj.简朴的,刻苦的;n.斯巴达;斯巴达式的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
232 spartans | |
n.斯巴达(spartan的复数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
233 subdued | |
adj. 屈服的,柔和的,减弱的 动词subdue的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
234 reverence | |
n.敬畏,尊敬,尊严;Reverence:对某些基督教神职人员的尊称;v.尊敬,敬畏,崇敬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
235 enjoined | |
v.命令( enjoin的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
236 frightful | |
adj.可怕的;讨厌的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
237 paramount | |
a.最重要的,最高权力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
238 democrats | |
n.民主主义者,民主人士( democrat的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
239 edifice | |
n.宏伟的建筑物(如宫殿,教室) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
240 imperative | |
n.命令,需要;规则;祈使语气;adj.强制的;紧急的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
241 consistency | |
n.一贯性,前后一致,稳定性;(液体的)浓度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
242 banish | |
vt.放逐,驱逐;消除,排除 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
243 vessels | |
n.血管( vessel的名词复数 );船;容器;(具有特殊品质或接受特殊品质的)人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
244 inaccessible | |
adj.达不到的,难接近的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
245 maxims | |
n.格言,座右铭( maxim的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
246 formerly | |
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
247 naval | |
adj.海军的,军舰的,船的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
248 impaired | |
adj.受损的;出毛病的;有(身体或智力)缺陷的v.损害,削弱( impair的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
249 agitations | |
(液体等的)摇动( agitation的名词复数 ); 鼓动; 激烈争论; (情绪等的)纷乱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
250 regains | |
复得( regain的第三人称单数 ); 赢回; 重回; 复至某地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
251 regain | |
vt.重新获得,收复,恢复 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
252 commodious | |
adj.宽敞的;使用方便的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
253 interfere | |
v.(in)干涉,干预;(with)妨碍,打扰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
254 exacting | |
adj.苛求的,要求严格的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
255 solitary | |
adj.孤独的,独立的,荒凉的;n.隐士 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
256 fortify | |
v.强化防御,为…设防;加强,强化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
257 disciples | |
n.信徒( disciple的名词复数 );门徒;耶稣的信徒;(尤指)耶稣十二门徒之一 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
258 dwelling | |
n.住宅,住所,寓所 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
259 maritime | |
adj.海的,海事的,航海的,近海的,沿海的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
260 colonizing | |
v.开拓殖民地,移民于殖民地( colonize的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
261 perpetuated | |
vt.使永存(perpetuate的过去式与过去分词形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
262 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
263 vaguely | |
adv.含糊地,暖昧地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
264 varied | |
adj.多样的,多变化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
265 infinity | |
n.无限,无穷,大量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
266 dictate | |
v.口授;(使)听写;指令,指示,命令 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
267 manure | |
n.粪,肥,肥粒;vt.施肥 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
268 uncertainty | |
n.易变,靠不住,不确知,不确定的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
269 deign | |
v. 屈尊, 惠允 ( 做某事) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
270 faculty | |
n.才能;学院,系;(学院或系的)全体教学人员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
271 vigour | |
(=vigor)n.智力,体力,精力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
272 magistrates | |
地方法官,治安官( magistrate的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
273 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
274 dwellings | |
n.住处,处所( dwelling的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
275 barbarians | |
n.野蛮人( barbarian的名词复数 );外国人;粗野的人;无教养的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
276 impartiality | |
n. 公平, 无私, 不偏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
277 sloth | |
n.[动]树懒;懒惰,懒散 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
278 jealousy | |
n.妒忌,嫉妒,猜忌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
279 imposture | |
n.冒名顶替,欺骗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
280 superstition | |
n.迷信,迷信行为 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
281 puerile | |
adj.幼稚的,儿童的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
282 instinctive | |
adj.(出于)本能的;直觉的;(出于)天性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
283 locomotion | |
n.运动,移动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
284 thwarted | |
阻挠( thwart的过去式和过去分词 ); 使受挫折; 挫败; 横过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
285 imbued | |
v.使(某人/某事)充满或激起(感情等)( imbue的过去式和过去分词 );使充满;灌输;激发(强烈感情或品质等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
286 docility | |
n.容易教,易驾驶,驯服 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
287 yoke | |
n.轭;支配;v.给...上轭,连接,使成配偶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
288 omnipotence | |
n.全能,万能,无限威力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
289 antiquated | |
adj.陈旧的,过时的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
290 inveterate | |
adj.积习已深的,根深蒂固的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
291 eradicated | |
画着根的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
292 vehement | |
adj.感情强烈的;热烈的;(人)有强烈感情的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
293 inflexible | |
adj.不可改变的,不受影响的,不屈服的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
294 literally | |
adv.照字面意义,逐字地;确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
295 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
296 insolence | |
n.傲慢;无礼;厚颜;傲慢的态度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
297 intrigue | |
vt.激起兴趣,迷住;vi.耍阴谋;n.阴谋,密谋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
298 frivolous | |
adj.轻薄的;轻率的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
299 absurdities | |
n.极端无理性( absurdity的名词复数 );荒谬;谬论;荒谬的行为 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
300 monarchy | |
n.君主,最高统治者;君主政体,君主国 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
301 arrogance | |
n.傲慢,自大 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
302 renovation | |
n.革新,整修 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
303 discourse | |
n.论文,演说;谈话;话语;vi.讲述,著述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
304 antithesis | |
n.对立;相对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
305 repelling | |
v.击退( repel的现在分词 );使厌恶;排斥;推开 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
306 extirpating | |
v.消灭,灭绝( extirpate的现在分词 );根除 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
307 arduous | |
adj.艰苦的,费力的,陡峭的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
308 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
309 diffuse | |
v.扩散;传播;adj.冗长的;四散的,弥漫的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
310 quotations | |
n.引用( quotation的名词复数 );[商业]行情(报告);(货物或股票的)市价;时价 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
311 imposing | |
adj.使人难忘的,壮丽的,堂皇的,雄伟的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
312 mechanism | |
n.机械装置;机构,结构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
313 requisite | |
adj.需要的,必不可少的;n.必需品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
314 astonishment | |
n.惊奇,惊异 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
315 radical | |
n.激进份子,原子团,根号;adj.根本的,激进的,彻底的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
316 unlimited | |
adj.无限的,不受控制的,无条件的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
317 tact | |
n.机敏,圆滑,得体 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
318 strings | |
n.弦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
319 maturity | |
n.成熟;完成;(支票、债券等)到期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
320 inertness | |
n.不活泼,没有生气;惰性;惯量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
321 impel | |
v.推动;激励,迫使 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
322 downwards | |
adj./adv.向下的(地),下行的(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
323 extermination | |
n.消灭,根绝 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
324 exterminate | |
v.扑灭,消灭,根绝 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
325 exterminated | |
v.消灭,根绝( exterminate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
326 exorbitant | |
adj.过分的;过度的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
327 immorality | |
n. 不道德, 无道义 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
328 conjecture | |
n./v.推测,猜测 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
329 importunity | |
n.硬要,强求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
330 pretensions | |
自称( pretension的名词复数 ); 自命不凡; 要求; 权力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
331 perverse | |
adj.刚愎的;坚持错误的,行为反常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
332 justified | |
a.正当的,有理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
333 renouncing | |
v.声明放弃( renounce的现在分词 );宣布放弃;宣布与…决裂;宣布摒弃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
334 renounce | |
v.放弃;拒绝承认,宣布与…断绝关系 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
335 restrictions | |
约束( restriction的名词复数 ); 管制; 制约因素; 带限制性的条件(或规则) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
336 incompetent | |
adj.无能力的,不能胜任的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
337 fettered | |
v.给…上脚镣,束缚( fetter的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
338 dreaded | |
adj.令人畏惧的;害怕的v.害怕,恐惧,担心( dread的过去式和过去分词) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
339 destitution | |
n.穷困,缺乏,贫穷 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
340 miserable | |
adj.悲惨的,痛苦的;可怜的,糟糕的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
341 omnipotent | |
adj.全能的,万能的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
342 prospering | |
成功,兴旺( prosper的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
343 lucrative | |
adj.赚钱的,可获利的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
344 grievance | |
n.怨愤,气恼,委屈 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
345 dominion | |
n.统治,管辖,支配权;领土,版图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
346 asylum | |
n.避难所,庇护所,避难 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
347 prerogative | |
n.特权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
348 hesitation | |
n.犹豫,踌躇 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
349 enjoyments | |
愉快( enjoyment的名词复数 ); 令人愉快的事物; 享有; 享受 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
350 interfering | |
adj. 妨碍的 动词interfere的现在分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
351 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
352 abstains | |
戒(尤指酒),戒除( abstain的第三人称单数 ); 弃权(不投票) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
353 immutable | |
adj.不可改变的,永恒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
354 diminution | |
n.减少;变小 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
355 lodging | |
n.寄宿,住所;(大学生的)校外宿舍 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
356 covetousness | |
参考例句: |
|
|
357 disturbance | |
n.动乱,骚动;打扰,干扰;(身心)失调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
358 repression | |
n.镇压,抑制,抑压 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
359 repeals | |
撤销,废除( repeal的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
360 assail | |
v.猛烈攻击,抨击,痛斥 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
361 jurisdiction | |
n.司法权,审判权,管辖权,控制权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
362 irritations | |
n.激怒( irritation的名词复数 );恼怒;生气;令人恼火的事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
363 atheistic | |
adj.无神论者的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
364 worthy | |
adj.(of)值得的,配得上的;有价值的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
365 isolation | |
n.隔离,孤立,分解,分离 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
366 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
367 interferes | |
vi. 妨碍,冲突,干涉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
368 machinery | |
n.(总称)机械,机器;机构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
369 justifiable | |
adj.有理由的,无可非议的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
370 incessantly | |
ad.不停地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
371 automaton | |
n.自动机器,机器人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
372 physiologist | |
n.生理学家 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
373 animated | |
adj.生气勃勃的,活跃的,愉快的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
374 savage | |
adj.野蛮的;凶恶的,残暴的;n.未开化的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
375 quacks | |
abbr.quacksalvers 庸医,骗子(16世纪习惯用水银或汞治疗梅毒的人)n.江湖医生( quack的名词复数 );江湖郎中;(鸭子的)呱呱声v.(鸭子)发出嘎嘎声( quack的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
376 nostrils | |
鼻孔( nostril的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
377 oblique | |
adj.斜的,倾斜的,无诚意的,不坦率的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
378 frail | |
adj.身体虚弱的;易损坏的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
379 physiology | |
n.生理学,生理机能 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
380 harmoniously | |
和谐地,调和地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
381 WHIMS | |
虚妄,禅病 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
382 inflicted | |
把…强加给,使承受,遭受( inflict的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |