It would be difficult to say if anarchy2 has passed from ideas to facts, or from facts to ideas, but it is certain that it pervades3 all, and abounds4 everywhere.
The poor rise up against the rich, men without fortune or profession against property; the populace against the bourgeoisie; labour against capital; agriculture against manufactures; the country against the town; the provinces against the metropolis6; the denizen7 against the stranger.
And theorists step in, and form a system of this antagonism8. “It is the inevitable9 result, they say, of the nature of things, that is to say, of Liberty. Man is endued10 with self-love, and hence comes all the evil; for since he is endued with self-love, he seeks to better his own condition, and he can only do so by entailing11 misery12 on his brethren. Let us hinder him, then, from following his inclinations13; let us stifle14 his liberty, change the human heart, substitute other motives16 for those which God has placed there: let us invent and constitute an artificial society!”
When they have got this length, an unlimited17 career opens itself to their reason or imagination. If they are possessed18 of a disputatious turn and a peevish19 temper, they enter with eagerness into an analysis of Evil. They dissect20 it, they put it in the crucible21, they interrogate22 it, they remount to its causes, they pursue it to its consequences; and, as by reason of our native imperfection there is nothing in which Evil is not present, they asperse23 and disparage24 everything. They exhibit to us Property, Family, Capital, Labour, Competition, Liberty, Personal Interest, only in one of their aspects, and always on the dark side, the side which injures or [p064] destroys. Their lectures on the natural history of man are, if I may use the expression, clinical lectures—the subject is always on his deathbed. They impiously defy God to reconcile what is said of His infinite goodness with the existence of evil. They stain and sully everything; they disgust us with everything; they dispute everything; and yet they obtain only a melancholy25 and dangerous success with those classes whom suffering disposes but too much to despair.
If, on the other hand, such theorists have a heart open to benevolence26, a mind which is pleased with illusions, they rush to the region of chimeras27. They dream of an Oceania, an Atlantis, a Salente, a Spensonie, an Icarie, a Utopia, a Phalanstère,20 and they people these imaginary regions with a docile28, loving, devoted29 race who always avoid setting themselves up against the fancies of the dreamer. He installs himself complacently30 in the seat of Providence31. He arranges, he disposes, he moulds men after his own fancy. Nothing stops him. He never encounters deceit. He resembles the Roman preacher, who, after having transformed his square cap into Rousseau, refuted warmly the Contrat Social, and triumphantly32 reduced his adversary33 to silence. It is thus that our Reformers dazzle those who suffer by means of seductive pictures of ideal felicity, well fitted to disgust them with the hard necessities of real life.
The theorist, however, rarely confines himself to such innocent chimeras. The moment he aims at leading mankind, he finds the people impatient of attempted transformations34. Men resist, they get angry. In order to gain them over, he harangues35 them not only on the happiness they reject, but more especially on the evils from which he professes36 to deliver them. He finds it impossible to make too striking a picture. He is continually charging his palette and deepening his colours. He hunts out the evils of existing society with as much zeal37 as another employs in discovering the good. He sees nothing but sufferings, rags, leanness, starvation, pain, oppression. He is enraged38 that society has not a deeper sense of its misery. He neglects no means of making it throw off its insensibility, and, having begun with benevolence, he ends with misanthropy.21
God forbid that I should call in question the sincerity39 of any one. But, in truth, I cannot explain to myself how these writers, [p065] who see a radical40 antagonism in the natural order of things, can ever taste a moment’s calm or repose41. Discouragement and despair would seem to be their unhappy portion. For, to sum up all, if nature is mistaken in making personal interest the mainspring of human society (and the mistake is manifest if it be admitted that the interests of society are fatally antagonistic42), how do they not perceive that the evil is without remedy? Being men ourselves, and being able to have recourse only to men, where can be our point d’appui for changing the tendencies of human nature? Shall we invoke43 the Police, the Magistracy, the State, the Legislature? That would only be to invoke men, that is to say, beings subject to the common infirmity. Shall we address ourselves to Universal Suffrage44? That would be to give the freest course to the universal tendency.
Only one expedient45 remains46 to these gentlemen. It is to hold themselves out as discoverers, as prophets, made of different clay from their fellow-men, and deriving47 their inspiration from a different source. This is the reason, no doubt, why we find them so frequently enveloping48 their systems and their councils in a mystic phraseology. But if they are ambassadors of God, let them exhibit their credentials49. In effect, what they demand is sovereign power, despotism the most absolute that ever existed. They not only wish to govern our acts, but to revolutionize our thoughts. Do they hope that mankind will believe them on their word, when they are not able to agree among themselves?
But before even examining their projects of artificial societies, is there not one point upon which it is necessary to assure ourselves, namely, whether they are not mistaken in the very foundation of their argument? Is it quite certain that MEN’S INTERESTS ARE NATURALLY ANTAGONISTIC; that an irremediable cause of inequality is fatally developed in the natural order of human society under the influence of personal interest, and that Providence is manifestly in error in ordaining50 that the progress of man should be towards ease and competency?
This is what I propose to inquire into.
Taking man as it has pleased God to constitute him, capable of foresight51 and experience, perfectible, endued with self-love, it is true,—but self-love qualified52 by the sympathetic principle, and at all events restrained and balanced by encountering an analogous53 sentiment universally prevailing54 in the medium in which it acts,—I proceed to inquire what social order must necessarily result from the combination and free play of such elements.
If we find that this result is nothing else than a progressive [p066] march towards prosperity, improvement, and equality,—a sustained approximation of all classes towards the same physical, intellectual, and moral level, accompanied by a constant elevation55 of that level, the ways of God to man will be vindicated56. We shall learn with delight that there is no gap, no blank, in creation, and that the social order, like everything else, attests57 the existence of those harmonic laws before which Newton bowed his head, and which elicited58 from the Psalmist the exclamation59, “The heavens declare the glory of God.”
Rousseau has said, “If I were a prince or a legislator, I should not lose my time in pointing out what was necessary to be done—I should do it or hold my tongue.”
I am not a prince, but the confidence of my fellow-citizens has made me a legislator. Perhaps they will tell me that this is the time for me to act and not to write.
Let them pardon me. Whether it be truth itself which urges me on, or that I am the dupe of an illusion. I have never ceased to feel the want of concentrating those ideas which have hitherto failed to find acceptance when presented in detached portions. I think I discover in the play of the natural laws of society sublime60 and consoling harmonies. What I see, or think I see, ought I not to try to exhibit to others, in order to rally round a sentiment of concord61 and fraternity many unsettled minds, many imbittered hearts? If, when the much-loved vessel62 of the state is beat by the tempest, I sometimes appear to absent myself from my post, in order to collect my scattered63 thoughts, it is because I feel my feeble hands unfitted for the work. Is it, besides, to betray my mission, to reflect upon the causes of the tempest itself, and endeavour to act upon these causes? And then, what I find I cannot do to-day, who knows but it may be given me to accomplish to-morrow?
I shall begin by establishing some Economical ideas. Availing myself of the works of my predecessors64, I shall endeavour to sum up the science in one principle—true, simple, and prolific—of which we have had a glimpse from the beginning, to which we are constantly drawing nearer and nearer, and of which, perhaps, the time is now come to fix the formula. By the light thus afforded, I shall afterwards essay the solution of some yet disputed problems—Competition, Machinery65, Foreign trade, Luxury, Capital, Rent, etc. I shall note some of the relations, or, I should rather say, the harmonies of Political Economy, with the other moral and social sciences, glancing at the important subjects indicated by the terms—Personal Interest, Property, Community, Liberty, [p067] Equality, Responsibility, Solidarity67, Fraternity, Unity66. Last of all, I shall invite attention to the artificial obstacles which the pacific, regular, and progressive development of human society encounters. From these two ideas—Natural harmonic Laws—Artificial disturbing Causes—will be deduced the solution of the Social Problem.
It is easy to see that there are two rocks ahead upon which this undertaking68 may founder69. In the middle of the vortex in which we are carried along, if this work is abstruse70, it will not be read; if it obtains readers, the questions of which it treats will be but glanced at. How are we to reconcile the exactions of the reader with the requirements of science? To satisfy all conditions both in form and substance, each word would require to be weighed, and have its proper place assigned to it. It is thus that the crystal is formed drop by drop in silence and obscurity. Retirement71, quiet, time, freedom from care—all are wanting to me—and I am forced to trust to the sagacity of the public, and throw myself on its indulgence.
The subject of Political Economy is Man.
But it does not embrace the whole range of human affairs. The science of morals has appropriated all that comes within the attractive regions of Sympathy—the religious sentiment, paternal72 and maternal73 tenderness, filial piety74, love, friendship, patriotism75, charity, politeness. To Political Economy is left only the cold domain76 of Personal interest. This is unjustly forgotten when Economical science is reproached with wanting the charm and unction of morals. How can it be otherwise? Dispute its right to existence as a science, but don’t force it to counterfeit77 what it is not, and cannot be. If human transactions which have wealth for their object are vast enough, complicated enough, to afford materials for a special science, leave to it its own attractions, such as they are, and don’t force it to speak of men’s Interests in the language of Sentiment. For my own part, I believe that little good has been effected of late in exacting78 from writers on Political Economy a tone of enthusiastic sentimentality which in their mouth can only be declamation80. Of what do they treat? Of transactions which take place between people who know nothing of each other, who owe each other nothing but common Justice, who seek to defend or advance certain interests. It has to do with claims and pretensions81 which limit and restrain each other, and with which disinterestedness82 and devotion have nothing to do. Take a lyre, and chant such themes! As well might Lamartine sing his odes with the aid of the logarithm tables. [p068]
Not that Political Economy is without its poetry. There is poetry wherever order and harmony exist. But it is in the results, not in the demonstrations83. It is brought out, not created. Kepler did not give himself out as a poet, and yet the laws which he discovered are the true poetry of mind.
Thus, Political Economy regards man only in one aspect, and our first care must be to study man in that point of view. This is the reason why we cannot avoid going back to the primary phenomena84 of human Sensibility and Activity. Start not, gentle reader! We shall not detain you long in those cloudy regions of metaphysics, and we shall borrow from that science only such notions as are clear, simple, and, if possible, incontestable.
The soul, or (to get rid of the spiritual question) man, is endued with Sensibility. Let this sensibility be either in the soul or in the body, man, as a passive being, always experiences sensations either painful or agreeable. As an active being, he makes an effort to drive away the one set of sensations and to multiply the other. The result, which affects him again as a passive being, may be called Satisfaction.
The general idea of Sensibility springs from other ideas which are more precise: pain, want, desire, taste, appetite, on one side; and, on the other, pleasure, enjoyment85, competence86.
Between these two extremes a middle term is interposed, and from the general idea of Activity spring the more precise ideas of pain, effort, fatigue87, labour, production.
In analyzing88 Sensibility and Activity we encounter a word common to both; the word Pain. To experience certain sensations is a pain, and we cannot put an end to it but by an effort, which is also a pain. We feel pains; we take pains. This advertises us that here below we have only a choice of evils.
In the aggregate89 of these phenomena all is personal, as well the Sensation which precedes the effort, as the Satisfaction which follows it.
We cannot doubt, then, that Personal interest is the great mainspring of human nature. It must be perfectly90 understood, however, that this term is here employed as the expression of a universal fact, incontestable, and resulting from the organization of man,—and not of a critical judgment91 on his conduct and actions, as if, instead of it, we should employ the word egotism. Moral science would be rendered impossible, if we were to pervert92 beforehand the terms of which it is compelled to make use.
Human effort does not always come necessarily to place itself between the sensation and the satisfaction. Sometimes the [p069] satisfaction comes of its own accord. More frequently the effort is exercised upon materials, by the intervention93 of forces which nature has placed gratuitously95 at our disposal.
If we give the name of Utility to all which effects the satisfaction of wants, there are, then, utilities of two kinds:—one, vouchsafed96 to us gratuitously by Providence; the other (if I may use the expression), requiring to be purchased by an Effort.
Thus the complete evolution embraces, or may embrace, these four ideas:
Man is endued with progressive faculties98. He compares, he foresees, he learns, he reforms himself, by experience. If want is a pain, effort is a pain also, and there is therefore no reason why he should not seek to diminish the latter, when he can do so without diminishing the satisfaction, which is his ultimate object. This is the reason of his success when he comes to replace onerous by gratuitous Utility, which is the perpetual object of his search.
It follows from the interested nature of the human heart, that we constantly seek to increase the proportion which our Satisfactions bear to our Efforts; and it results from the intelligent nature of our mind that we manage at each step to augment99 the proportion which gratuitous bears to onerous Utility.
Every time a success of this nature is achieved, a part of our efforts is, so to speak, rendered disposable, and we have the option of either indulging ourselves with longer repose, or of working for the satisfaction of new desires, if these are strong enough to stimulate100 our activity.
Such is the principle of all economic progress; and it is easy to see that it is the principle also of all deception101; for progress and error have both their root in that marvellous gift of God to man—Free will.
We are endued with the faculty102 of comparing, of judging, of choosing, and of acting79 in consequence; which implies that we may form a right or a wrong judgment, and make a good or a bad choice. It is never useless to remind men of this when they talk of Liberty.
We never deceive ourselves, it is true, regarding the particular nature of our sensations, and we discern with an infallible instinct whether they are painful or agreeable. But how many various forms may our errors take! We may be labouring under a mistake as to the cause, and pursue with ardour, as likely to afford us enjoyment, what can only indict103 pain upon us; or we may be [p070] mistaken as to the chain of consequences, and be ignorant that an immediate104 satisfaction will be followed by greater ulterior pain; or, again, we may mistake the relative importance of our wants and our desires.
Not only may we thus give a false direction to our efforts through ignorance, but also through a perverse105 will. “Man,” says M. Bonald, “is an intelligence served by organs.” What! is there nothing else in us? Have we no passions?
When we speak of harmony, then, we must not be understood to mean that the natural arrangement of the social world is such that error and vice106 have been excluded from it. To maintain that thesis in the face of plain facts would be to carry the love of system to madness. To have harmony without dissonance man must either be devoid107 of free will or he must be infallible. All we say is this, that the great social tendencies are harmonious108, inasmuch as—all error leading to deception and all vice to chastisement—the dissonances have a continual tendency to disappear.
A first and vague notion of property may be deduced from these premises109. Since it is the individual who experiences the sensation, the desire, the want,—since it is he who makes the Effort,—the satisfaction must necessarily redound110 to him, for otherwise the effort would be without cause or reason.
The same may be said of Inheritance. No theory, no declamation, is required in order to make fathers love their children. People who sit down to manufacture imaginary societies may think it strange, but it is so;—a father makes as many Efforts for the satisfaction of his children as for his own. Perhaps he makes more. If, then, an unnatural111 law should interdict112 the transmission of property, not only would that law violate property by the very act, but it would hinder its formation by abandoning to inaction one-half at least of our Efforts.
We shall have occasion to return to the subjects of Personal interest, Property, and Inheritance. Let us, in the first instance, mark out the limits of the science with which we have more immediately to do.
I am not one of those who think that a science, as such, has natural and unalterable boundaries. In the domain of ideas, as in that of facts, all things are bound up and linked together; truths run into one another; and there is no science which, in order to be complete, might not be made to include all. It has been said with reason that to an infinite intelligence there is but a single verity113. It is, then, our weakness which obliges us to study separately a [p071] certain order of phenomena, and the classifications which result from it cannot escape a certain decree of arbitrariness.
The true merit is to explain accurately114 the facts, their causes, and their consequences. It is also a merit, although a much less and a purely115 relative one, to determine, not rigorously—for that is impossible—but rationally, the order of the facts which we propose to study.
I say this in order that it may not be supposed that I intend to criticise116 my predecessors if I give to Political Economy limits somewhat different from those which they have assigned to that science.
Economists117 have of late been reproached with addicting119 themselves too much to the study of Wealth. It has been wished that they had found a place in their science for all that, directly or indirectly120, contributes to the happiness or sufferings of humanity. They have even been supposed to deny everything which they did not profess5 to teach—for example, the phenomena of sympathy, which is as natural to the heart of man as the principle of self-interest. It is as if they accused the mineralogist of denying the existence of the animal kingdom. What! Wealth, the laws of its production, of its distribution, of its consumption,—is not this a subject vast enough, and important enough, to be made the object of a special science? If the conclusions of the Economist118 were at variance121 with those of morals and politics. I could conceive ground for the accusation122. One might say to him, “In limiting your science you are mistaken, for it is not possible for two verities123 to run counter to each other.” Perhaps one result of the work which I now submit to the public may be, that the Science of Wealth will be found to be in perfect harmony with all the other sciences.
Of the three terms comprehended in the human destinies—Sensation, Effort, Satisfaction—the first and the last are always and necessarily confounded in the same individuality. It is impossible to imagine them separated. We can conceive a sensation unsatisfied, a want unappeased, but it is quite impossible to suppose the want to be in one man and the satisfaction to be in another.
If the same observation applied124 to the middle term, Effort, man would be a being completely solitary125. The Economic phenomena would then manifest themselves in an isolated126 individual. There might be a juxtaposition127 of persons, but there could be no society; there might be a Personal, but not a Political, Economy.
But it is not so. It is very possible, and very often happens, that the wants of one owe their satisfaction to the efforts of [p072] another. This is a fact. If any one of us were to pass in review all the satisfactions he enjoys, he would acknowledge that he owes them chiefly to efforts which he has not himself made; and in the same way, the labour which we undergo, each in his own profession, goes almost always to satisfy the desires of others.
This tells us, that it is neither in the wants nor in the satisfactions (phenomena essentially128 personal and intransmissible), but in the nature of the mean term, human Efforts, that we must search for the social principle—the origin of Political Economy.
It is in fact to this faculty, given to men, and to men alone, among all creatures, to work the one for the other; it is this transmission of efforts, this exchange of services, with all the infinite and involved combinations to which it gives rise, through time and through space, it is THIS precisely129 which constitutes Economic Science, points out its origin, and determines its limits.
I say, then:
Every effort, capable of satisfying, on condition of a return, the wants of a person other than the man who makes the effort, and consequently the wants and satisfactions relative to this species of effort, constitute the domain of Political Economy.
Thus, to give an example: the act of breathing, although it includes the three terms which constitute the Economic phenomenon, does not pertain130 to that science, and we see the reason. What we have here to do with is a series of facts, of which not only the two extremes—want and satisfaction—are incapable131 of transmission (they are always so); but the mean term, Effort, is also incapable of transmission. To enable us to respire we invoke the assistance of no one; in that there is neither a service to be received nor a service to render. The fact is in its nature individual, not social, and consequently cannot enter into a science which is essentially one of relation, as its very name indicates.
But if, in peculiar132 circumstances, people were to render each other assistance to enable them to breathe, as when a workman descends133 in a diving-bell, when a physician treats a patient for pulmonary complaints, or when the police take measures for purifying the air, in such cases there is a want satisfied by a person other than the person who experiences the want; there is a service rendered; and respiration134 itself, as far at least as concerns assistance and remuneration, is brought within the sphere of Political Economy.
It is not necessary that the transaction should be completed, it is sufficient that it is possible, in order to impart to the labour employed an economic character. The labourer who raises corn [p073] for his own use accomplishes an economic fact in this respect that the corn is capable of being exchanged.
To make an effort in order to satisfy another’s wants is to render him a service. If a service is stipulated135 in return, there is an exchange of services; and as this is the most ordinary case, Political Economy may be defined the theory of Exchange.
Whatever may be for one of the contracting parties the urgency of the want, or for the other the intensity136 of the effort, if the exchange is free, the two services exchanged are worth each other. Value, then, consists in the comparative appreciation137 of reciprocal services, and Political Economy again may be defined the theory of Value.
I have just defined Political Economy, and marked out its domain, without mentioning an essential element, gratuitous Utility.
All authors have remarked that we derive138 a multitude of satisfactions from this source. They denominate these utilities, such as air, water, the light of the sun, etc., natural wealth, in contradistinction to social wealth, and having done so, they take no more notice of them; and in fact it would seem that, as they give rise to no effort, to no exchange, to no service, as (being destitute139 of value) they figure in no inventory140 of goods, they should not be admitted into the domain of Political Economy.
This exclusion141 would be rational if gratuitous utility were a fixed142 invariable quantity, always separated from onerous utility; but they are constantly mixed up, and in inverse143 proportions. Man’s constant endeavour is to substitute the one for the other, that is to say, to arrive, by means of natural and gratuitous agents, at the same results as by efforts. He accomplishes by the wind, by gravitation, by heat, by the elasticity144 of the air, what he accomplished145 at first only by muscular exertion146.
Now what happens? Although the effect is equally useful, the effort is less. Less effort implies less service, and less service implies less value. Each step of progress, then, annihilates147 value; but how? Not by suppressing the useful effect, but by substituting gratuitous for onerous utility, natural for social wealth. In one sense the portion of value thus annihilated148 is excluded from the domain of Political Economy, just as it is excluded from our inventories149. It is no longer exchanged, bought, or sold, and mankind enjoy it without effort and almost without consciousness. It is no longer accounted relative wealth, but is ranked among the gifts of God.
But, on the other hand, if science takes it no longer into account, the error is assuredly committed of losing sight of what [p074] under all circumstances is the main, the essential thing—the result, the useful effect. In that case we overlook the strongest tendencies towards community and equality, and discover much less of harmony in the social order. If this book is destined150 to advance Political Economy a single step, it will be by keeping constantly before the eyes of the reader that portion of value which is successively annihilated, and recovered, under the form of gratuitous utility, by mankind at large.
I shall here make an observation which will prove how frequently the sciences unite and nearly run into each other.
I have just defined service. It is the effort in one man, while the want and the satisfaction are in another. Sometimes the service is rendered gratuitously, without remuneration, without any service being exacted in return. It proceeds, then, from the principle of sympathy rather than from the principle of self-interest. It constitutes gift, not exchange. Consequently it would seem to appertain not to Political Economy (which is the theory of exchange), but to morals. In fact, acts of that nature, by reason of their motive15, are rather moral than economical. We shall see, however, that, by reason of their effects, they concern the science which now engages us. On the other hand, services rendered for an onerous consideration, on condition of a return, and, by reason of that motive (essentially economic), do not on that account remain excluded from the domain of morals, in so far as their effects are concerned.
Thus these two branches of knowledge have an infinite number of points of contact; and as two truths cannot be antagonistic, when the economist ascribes to a phenomenon injurious consequences, and the moralist ascribes to it beneficial effects, we may affirm that one or other of them is mistaken. It is thus that the sciences verify and fortify151 one another.
点击收听单词发音
1 afflicting | |
痛苦的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 anarchy | |
n.无政府状态;社会秩序混乱,无秩序 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 pervades | |
v.遍及,弥漫( pervade的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 abounds | |
v.大量存在,充满,富于( abound的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 profess | |
v.声称,冒称,以...为业,正式接受入教,表明信仰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 metropolis | |
n.首府;大城市 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 denizen | |
n.居民,外籍居民 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 antagonism | |
n.对抗,敌对,对立 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 inevitable | |
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 endued | |
v.授予,赋予(特性、才能等)( endue的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 entailing | |
使…成为必要( entail的现在分词 ); 需要; 限定继承; 使必需 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 misery | |
n.痛苦,苦恼,苦难;悲惨的境遇,贫苦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 inclinations | |
倾向( inclination的名词复数 ); 倾斜; 爱好; 斜坡 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 stifle | |
vt.使窒息;闷死;扼杀;抑止,阻止 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 unlimited | |
adj.无限的,不受控制的,无条件的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 peevish | |
adj.易怒的,坏脾气的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 dissect | |
v.分割;解剖 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 crucible | |
n.坩锅,严酷的考验 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 interrogate | |
vt.讯问,审问,盘问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 asperse | |
v.流言;n.流言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 disparage | |
v.贬抑,轻蔑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 melancholy | |
n.忧郁,愁思;adj.令人感伤(沮丧)的,忧郁的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 benevolence | |
n.慈悲,捐助 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 chimeras | |
n.(由几种动物的各部分构成的)假想的怪兽( chimera的名词复数 );不可能实现的想法;幻想;妄想 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 docile | |
adj.驯服的,易控制的,容易教的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 devoted | |
adj.忠诚的,忠实的,热心的,献身于...的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 complacently | |
adv. 满足地, 自满地, 沾沾自喜地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 providence | |
n.深谋远虑,天道,天意;远见;节约;上帝 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 triumphantly | |
ad.得意洋洋地;得胜地;成功地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 adversary | |
adj.敌手,对手 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 transformations | |
n.变化( transformation的名词复数 );转换;转换;变换 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 harangues | |
n.高谈阔论的长篇演讲( harangue的名词复数 )v.高谈阔论( harangue的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 professes | |
声称( profess的第三人称单数 ); 宣称; 公开表明; 信奉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 zeal | |
n.热心,热情,热忱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 enraged | |
使暴怒( enrage的过去式和过去分词 ); 歜; 激愤 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 sincerity | |
n.真诚,诚意;真实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 radical | |
n.激进份子,原子团,根号;adj.根本的,激进的,彻底的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 repose | |
v.(使)休息;n.安息 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 antagonistic | |
adj.敌对的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 invoke | |
v.求助于(神、法律);恳求,乞求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 suffrage | |
n.投票,选举权,参政权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 expedient | |
adj.有用的,有利的;n.紧急的办法,权宜之计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 deriving | |
v.得到( derive的现在分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 enveloping | |
v.包围,笼罩,包住( envelop的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 credentials | |
n.证明,资格,证明书,证件 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 ordaining | |
v.任命(某人)为牧师( ordain的现在分词 );授予(某人)圣职;(上帝、法律等)命令;判定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 foresight | |
n.先见之明,深谋远虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 qualified | |
adj.合格的,有资格的,胜任的,有限制的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 analogous | |
adj.相似的;类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 prevailing | |
adj.盛行的;占优势的;主要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 elevation | |
n.高度;海拔;高地;上升;提高 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 vindicated | |
v.澄清(某人/某事物)受到的责难或嫌疑( vindicate的过去式和过去分词 );表明或证明(所争辩的事物)属实、正当、有效等;维护 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 attests | |
v.证明( attest的第三人称单数 );证实;声称…属实;使宣誓 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 elicited | |
引出,探出( elicit的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 exclamation | |
n.感叹号,惊呼,惊叹词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 sublime | |
adj.崇高的,伟大的;极度的,不顾后果的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 concord | |
n.和谐;协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 vessel | |
n.船舶;容器,器皿;管,导管,血管 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 scattered | |
adj.分散的,稀疏的;散步的;疏疏落落的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 predecessors | |
n.前任( predecessor的名词复数 );前辈;(被取代的)原有事物;前身 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 machinery | |
n.(总称)机械,机器;机构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 unity | |
n.团结,联合,统一;和睦,协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 solidarity | |
n.团结;休戚相关 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 undertaking | |
n.保证,许诺,事业 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 Founder | |
n.创始者,缔造者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 abstruse | |
adj.深奥的,难解的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 retirement | |
n.退休,退职 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 paternal | |
adj.父亲的,像父亲的,父系的,父方的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 maternal | |
adj.母亲的,母亲般的,母系的,母方的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 piety | |
n.虔诚,虔敬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 patriotism | |
n.爱国精神,爱国心,爱国主义 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 domain | |
n.(活动等)领域,范围;领地,势力范围 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 counterfeit | |
vt.伪造,仿造;adj.伪造的,假冒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 exacting | |
adj.苛求的,要求严格的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 acting | |
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 declamation | |
n. 雄辩,高调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 pretensions | |
自称( pretension的名词复数 ); 自命不凡; 要求; 权力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 disinterestedness | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 demonstrations | |
证明( demonstration的名词复数 ); 表明; 表达; 游行示威 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 enjoyment | |
n.乐趣;享有;享用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 competence | |
n.能力,胜任,称职 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 fatigue | |
n.疲劳,劳累 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 analyzing | |
v.分析;分析( analyze的现在分词 );分解;解释;对…进行心理分析n.分析 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 aggregate | |
adj.总计的,集合的;n.总数;v.合计;集合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 judgment | |
n.审判;判断力,识别力,看法,意见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 pervert | |
n.堕落者,反常者;vt.误用,滥用;使人堕落,使入邪路 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 intervention | |
n.介入,干涉,干预 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 gratuitous | |
adj.无偿的,免费的;无缘无故的,不必要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 gratuitously | |
平白 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 vouchsafed | |
v.给予,赐予( vouchsafe的过去式和过去分词 );允诺 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 onerous | |
adj.繁重的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 faculties | |
n.能力( faculty的名词复数 );全体教职员;技巧;院 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 augment | |
vt.(使)增大,增加,增长,扩张 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 stimulate | |
vt.刺激,使兴奋;激励,使…振奋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 deception | |
n.欺骗,欺诈;骗局,诡计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 faculty | |
n.才能;学院,系;(学院或系的)全体教学人员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 indict | |
v.起诉,控告,指控 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 perverse | |
adj.刚愎的;坚持错误的,行为反常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 devoid | |
adj.全无的,缺乏的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 harmonious | |
adj.和睦的,调和的,和谐的,协调的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 premises | |
n.建筑物,房屋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 redound | |
v.有助于;提;报应 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 unnatural | |
adj.不自然的;反常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 interdict | |
v.限制;禁止;n.正式禁止;禁令 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 verity | |
n.真实性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 accurately | |
adv.准确地,精确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 purely | |
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 criticise | |
v.批评,评论;非难 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 economists | |
n.经济学家,经济专家( economist的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 economist | |
n.经济学家,经济专家,节俭的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 addicting | |
使沉溺(addict的现在分词形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 indirectly | |
adv.间接地,不直接了当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 variance | |
n.矛盾,不同 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 accusation | |
n.控告,指责,谴责 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 verities | |
n.真实( verity的名词复数 );事实;真理;真实的陈述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 solitary | |
adj.孤独的,独立的,荒凉的;n.隐士 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 isolated | |
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 juxtaposition | |
n.毗邻,并置,并列 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 pertain | |
v.(to)附属,从属;关于;有关;适合,相称 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 incapable | |
adj.无能力的,不能做某事的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 descends | |
v.下来( descend的第三人称单数 );下去;下降;下斜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 respiration | |
n.呼吸作用;一次呼吸;植物光合作用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 stipulated | |
vt.& vi.规定;约定adj.[法]合同规定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 intensity | |
n.强烈,剧烈;强度;烈度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 appreciation | |
n.评价;欣赏;感谢;领会,理解;价格上涨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 derive | |
v.取得;导出;引申;来自;源自;出自 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 destitute | |
adj.缺乏的;穷困的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 inventory | |
n.详细目录,存货清单 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141 exclusion | |
n.拒绝,排除,排斥,远足,远途旅行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143 inverse | |
adj.相反的,倒转的,反转的;n.相反之物;v.倒转 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144 elasticity | |
n.弹性,伸缩力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145 accomplished | |
adj.有才艺的;有造诣的;达到了的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146 exertion | |
n.尽力,努力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147 annihilates | |
n.(彻底)消灭( annihilate的名词复数 );使无效;废止;彻底击溃v.(彻底)消灭( annihilate的第三人称单数 );使无效;废止;彻底击溃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148 annihilated | |
v.(彻底)消灭( annihilate的过去式和过去分词 );使无效;废止;彻底击溃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149 inventories | |
n.总结( inventory的名词复数 );细账;存货清单(或财产目录)的编制 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151 fortify | |
v.强化防御,为…设防;加强,强化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |