IN dreams we are always reasoning. That is a general characteristic of dreams which is worth noting, because its significance is not usually recognised. It is sometimes imagined that reason is in abeyance3 during sleep.[42] So far from this being the case, we may almost be said to reason much more during sleep than when we are awake. That our reasoning is bad, often even preposterous4, that it constantly ignores the most elementary facts of waking life, scarcely affects the question. All dreaming is a process of reasoning. That artful confusion of ideas and images which, at the outset, I referred to as the most constant feature of dream mechanism6 is nothing but a process of reasoning, a perpetual effort to argue out harmoniously7 the absurdly limited and incongruous data present to sleeping consciousness. Binet, grounding his conclusions on hypnotic experiments, finds that reasoning is the fundamental[57] part of all thinking, the very texture8 of thought.[43] It is founded on perception itself, which already contains all the elements of the ancient syllogism9. For in all perception, as Binet plausibly10 argues, there is a succession of three images, of which the first fuses with the second, which, in its turn, suggests the third. Now this establishment of new associations, this construction of images, which, as we may easily convince ourselves, is precisely11 what takes place in dreaming, is reasoning itself.
Reasoning may thus be regarded as a synthesis of images suggested by resemblance and contiguity12, indeed a sort of logical vision, more intense even than actual vision, since it is capable of producing hallucinations. To reasoning all forms of mental activity may finally be reduced; mind, as Wundt has said, is a thing that reasons. Or, as H. R. Marshall puts it, 'reason is a mode of instinct.'[44] When we apply these general statements to dreaming, we may see that the whole phenomenon of dreaming is really the same process of image formation, based on resemblance and contiguity. Every dream is the outcome of this strenuous14, wide-ranging instinct to reason. The supposed 'imaginative faculty,' regarded as so highly active during sleep, is the inevitable15 play of this automatic logic13.
[58]
The syllogistic16 arrangement of dream imagery is carried on in an absolutely automatic manner; it is spontaneous, involuntary, without effort. Sleeping consciousness, though all the time it is weaving the data that reach it into some pattern of reason with immense ingenuity17, is quite unaware18 that it is itself responsible for the arguments thus presented. In the evening, before going to bed, I glance casually19 through a newspaper; I see the usual kind of news, revolutionists in Russia, Irish affairs, crimes, etc.; I see also a caricature of the Liberal Party as a headless horseman on a barren plain. During sleep these unconnected impressions revive, float into dream consciousness, and spontaneously fall into as reasonable a whole as could be expected. I dream that by some chemical or mechanical device a man has succeeded in conveying the impression that he is headless, and is preparing to gallop20 across some district in Russia, with the idea of making so mysterious an impression upon the credulous21 population that he will be accepted as a great religious prophet. I distinctly see him careering across sands like those of the seashore, but I avoid going near him. Then I see figures approaching him in the far distance, and his progress ceases. I learn subsequently that he has been arrested and found to be an Irish criminal. A coherent story is thus formed out of a few random22 impressions.
All such typical dreams are syllogistic. There is, that is to say, as Binet expresses it, the establishment of an association between two states of consciousness[59] by means of an intermediate state which resembles the first, is associated with the second, and by fusing with the first associates it with the second. In this dream, for instance, we have the three terms of (1) headless horseman, (2) revolutionary crime, and (3) Russia and Ireland. The intermediate term, by the fact that it resembles the first, and is contiguous in the mind with the third, seems to fuse the first and the third terms, so that the headless horseman becomes an Irish criminal in Russia. In dreaming life, as in waking life, our minds are always moving by the construction of similar syllogisms, marked by more or less freedom and audacity23.
It is unnecessary to multiply examples of the instinctive and persistent24 efforts on the part of the sleeping mind to construct a coherent whole out of the incongruous elements that come before it; nearly every dream furnishes some proof of this profoundly rooted impulse.[45] It is instructive, however, to consider the nature and the limitations of dreaming reason.
This rationalisation and logical construction of imagery, it is necessary to realise, occurs at the very threshold of sleeping consciousness. The dreamer makes no effort to arrange isolated25 imagery; the arrangement has already occurred when the imagery comes to the focus of sleeping consciousness; so that this reasoning and arranging process is so fundamental and instinctive that it occurs in a region which may be[60] said to be subconscious26 to dreaming consciousness. If it were not so our dreams would never be real to us, for even dreaming consciousness could not accept as real a hallucination which it had itself arranged. In this sense it is true that, to some extent, our dreams are often based on an ultimate personal and emotional foundation.[46]
But this ingeniously guided and rationalised confusion of imagery by no means covers the whole of the reasoning process in dreams. This is a double process. It is first manifested subconsciously27 in the formation of dream imagery, and then it is manifested consciously in the dreamer's reaction to the imagery presented to him. Every dream is made up of action and reaction between a pseudo-universe and a freely responding individual. On the one side there is the irresistibly28 imposed imagery—really, though we know it not, conditioned and instinctively29 moulded by our own organism—which stands for what in our waking hours we may term God and Nature; on the other side is the Soul struggling with all its might, and very inefficient30 means, against the awful powers that oppose it. The problem of the waking world is presented over again[61] in this battle between the dreaming protagonist31 and his dreamed fate. Both of these elements are instinctively reasoned out, consciously or subconsciously; both are imperfect fragments from the rich reservoir of human personality.
The things that happen to us in dreams, the pseudo-external world that is presented to sleeping consciousness—the imagery, that is, that floats before the mental eye of sleep—are a perpetual source of astonishment32 and argument to the dreamer. A large part of dreaming activity is concerned with the attempt to explain and reason out the phenomena33 we thus encounter, to construct a theory of them, or to determine the attitude which we ought to take up with regard to them. Most dreams will furnish evidence of this reasoning process.
Thus a lady dreamed that an acquaintance wished to send a small sum of money to a person in Ireland. She rashly offered to take it over to Ireland. On arriving home she began to repent34 of her promise, as the weather was extremely wild and cold. She proceeded, however, to make preparations for dressing35 warmly, and went to consult an Irish friend, who said she would have to be floated over to Ireland tightly jammed in a crab36 basket. On returning home she fully37 discussed the matter with her husband, who thought it would be folly38 to undertake such a journey, and she finally relinquished39 it, with great relief. In this dream—the elements of which could all be accounted for—the association between sending money and the post-office, which would at once occur to waking consciousness, was closed; consciousness[62] was a prey40 to such suggestions as reached it, but on the basis of those suggestions it reasoned and concluded quite sagaciously.
Again (after looking at photographs of paintings and statuary, and also reading about the theatre), I dreamed that I was at the theatre, and that the performers were acting41 and dancing in a more or less, in some cases completely, nude42 state, but with admirable propriety43 and grace, and very charming effect. At first I was extremely surprised at so remarkable44 an innovation; but then I reflected that the beginnings of such a movement must have long been in progress on the stage unknown to me; and I proceeded to rehearse the reasons which made such a movement desirable. On another occasion, I dreamed that I was in the large plaza45 of a Spanish city (Pamplona possibly furnishing the elements of the picture), and that the governor emerged from his residence facing the square and began talking in English to the subordinate officials who were waiting to receive him. The real reason why he talked English was, of course, the simple one that he spoke46 the language native to the dreamer. But in my dream I was extremely puzzled why he should speak English. I looked carefully into his face to assure myself that he was not really English, and I finally concluded that he was speaking English in order not to be understood by the bystanders. Once more, I dreamed that I was looking at an architectural drawing of a steeple, of quite original design, somewhat in the shape of a cross, but very elongated47. I attempted in[63] my dream to account for this elongation, and concluded that it was intended to neutralise the foreshortening caused when the steeple would be looked at from below.
There is, we here see afresh, a fundamental split in dreaming intelligence. On the one side there is the subconscious, yet often highly intelligent, combination of imagery along rational although often bizarre lines. On the other side is concentrated the conscious intelligence of the dreamer, struggling to comprehend and explain the problems offered by the pseudo-external imagery thus presented to it. One might almost say that in dreams subconscious intelligence is playing a game with conscious intelligence. In a dream previously48 narrated49 (p. 43) subconscious intelligence offered to my dreaming consciousness the mysterious substance selvdrolla, and bid me guess what it was; I could not guess. And subconscious intelligence presented the drawing of the elongated steeple, and I was able to offer an explanation which seems fairly satisfactory. So that, in the world of dreams, it may be said, we see over again the process which, James Hinton was accustomed to say, we see in the universe of our waking life; God or Nature playing with man, compelling him to join in a game of hide-and-seek, and setting him problems which he must solve as best he can. It may well be, one may add, that the dream process furnishes the key to the metaphysical and even, indeed, the physical problems of our waking thoughts, and that the puzzles of the universe are questions that we ourselves unconsciously invent for ourselves to solve.
[64]
We can never go behind the fantastic universe of our dreams. The validity of that universe is for dreaming consciousness unassailable. We may try to understand it and explain it, but we can never deny it, any more than we can deny the universe of our waking life, however we may attempt to analyse it. Dreaming consciousness never realises that the universe that confronts it springs from the same source as itself springs. I dreamed that a man was looking at his own house from a distance, and on the balcony he saw his daughter and a man by her side. 'Who is that man flirting50 with my daughter?' he asked. He produced a field-glass, and, on looking through it, he exclaimed: 'Good Heavens, it's myself!' Dreaming consciousness accepted this situation with perfect equanimity51 and solemnity. In the dream world there is, indeed, nothing else to do. We may puzzle over the facts presented to us; we may try to explain them; but it would be futile52 to deny them, even when they involve the possibility of a man being in two places at the same time.[47]
Only to a few people there comes occasionally in dreams a dim realisation of the unreality of the experience:[65] 'After all, it does not matter,' they are able to say to themselves with more or less conviction, 'this is only a dream.' Thus one lady, dreaming that she is trying to kill three large snakes by stamping on them, wonders, while still dreaming, what it signifies to dream of snakes,[48] and another lady, when she dreams that she is in any unpleasant position—about to be shot, for instance—often says to herself: 'Never mind, I shall wake before it happens.'
I have never detected in my own dreams any recognition that they are dreams. I may say, indeed, that I do not consider that such a thing is really possible, though it has been borne witness to by many philosophers and others from Aristotle and Synesius and Gassendi onwards. The phenomenon occurs; the person who says to himself that he is dreaming believes that he is still dreaming, but one may be permitted to doubt that he is. It seems far more probable that he has for a moment, without realising it, emerged at the waking surface of consciousness.[49] The only approach to a recognition of dreaming as dreaming that I have[66] experienced, is connected with the reduplication that may sometimes occur, and the sense of a fatalistic predetermination. Thus I dreamed (with nothing that could suggest the dream) that I was one of a group of people who, as I realised, were carrying out a drama in which by force of circumstance I was destined53 to be the villain54, having, by bad treatment, been driven to revenge. I knew at the outset how events would turn out, and yet, though it seemed real life, I felt vaguely55 that it was all a play that was merely being rehearsed. I had attained56 in the world of dreams to the Shakespearian feeling that it was all a stage, and I merely a player. So we may become the Prosperos of the life of dreams.[50]
This quality of dreaming consciousness is a manifestation57, and the chief one, of what is called dissociation.[51] In dissociation we have a phenomenon which runs through the whole of the dreaming life, and is scarcely less fundamental than the process of fusion5 by which the imagery is built up. The fact that the[67] reasoning of dreams is usually bad, is due partly to the absence of memory elements that would be present to waking consciousness, and partly to the absence of sensory58 elements to check the false reasoning which, without them, appears to us conclusive59. That is to say, that there is a process of dissociation by which ordinary channels of association are temporarily blocked, perhaps by exhaustion60 of their conductive elements, and the conditions are prepared for the formation of the hallucination. It is, as Parish has argued, in sleep and in those sleep-resembling states called hypnagogic that a condition of dissociation leading to hallucination is most apt to occur.[52]
Thus it is that though the psychic61 frontier of the sleeping state is more extended than that of the normal waking state, the focus of sleeping consciousness is more contracted than that of waking consciousness. In other words, while facts are liable to drift from a very wide psychic distance under our dreaming attention, we cannot direct the searchlight of that attention at will over so wide a field as when we are awake. We deal with fewer psychic elements, though those elements are drawn62 from a wider field.
The psychology63 of 'attention' is, indeed, a very[68] disputed matter.[53] There is no agreement as to whether it is central or peripheral64, motor or sensory. As we have seen in the previous chapter, it seems reasonable to conclude, according to a convenient distinction established by Ribot, that spontaneous attention is persistent during sleep, but voluntary attention is at a minimum. In some such way, it seems, whatever theory of attention we adopt, we have to recognise that in dreams the attention is limited.
Such a position is fortified65 by the conclusion of those who look at the problem, not so much in terms of attention as in terms of apperception. Apperception, according to Wundt, differs from perception in that while the latter is the appearance of a content in consciousness, the former is its reception into the state of attention. Or, as Stout66 defines it, apperception is 'the process by which a mental system appropriates a new element, or otherwise receives a fresh determination.'[54] Apperception is, therefore, the final stage of attention, and ultimately, as Wundt remarks, it is one with will. Apperception and will, as most psychologists consider, like attention, are enfeebled and diminished, if not abolished, in sleep.
In dreams, it thus comes about, we accept the facts[69] presented to us—that is the fundamental assumption of dream life—and we argue about those 'facts' with the help of all the mental resources which are at our disposal, only those resources are frequently inadequate67. Sometimes they are startlingly inadequate, to such an extent, indeed, that we are unaware of possibilities which would be the very first to suggest themselves to waking consciousness. Thus the lady who wished to send a small sum of money to Ireland is not aware of the existence of postal68 orders, and when she decides to convey the money herself, she is not aware of the existence of boat-trains, or even of boats; she might have been living in palaeolithic times. She discusses the question in a clear and logical manner with the resources at her disposal, and reaches a rational conclusion, but considerations which would be the first to occur to waking consciousness are at the moment absent from sleeping consciousness; whole mental tracts69 have been dissociated, switched off from communication with consciousness; they are 'asleep,' even to sleeping consciousness.[55]
The result is that we are not only dominated by the suggestion of our visions, but we are unable adequately to appreciate and criticise70 the situations which are presented to us. We instinctively continue to reason, and to reason clearly and logically with the material at[70] our disposal, but our reasoning is hopelessly absurd. We perceive in dreams, but we do not apperceive; we cannot, that is to say, test and sift71 the new experience, and co-ordinate it adequately with the whole body of our acquired mental possessions. The phenomena of dreaming furnish a delightful72 illustration of the fact that reasoning, in its rough form, is only the crudest and most elementary form of intellectual operation, and that the finer forms of thinking involve much more than logic. 'All the thinking in the world,' as Goethe puts it, 'will not lead us to thought.'
点击收听单词发音
1 instinctive | |
adj.(出于)本能的;直觉的;(出于)天性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 disturbance | |
n.动乱,骚动;打扰,干扰;(身心)失调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 abeyance | |
n.搁置,缓办,中止,产权未定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 preposterous | |
adj.荒谬的,可笑的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 fusion | |
n.溶化;熔解;熔化状态,熔和;熔接 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 mechanism | |
n.机械装置;机构,结构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 harmoniously | |
和谐地,调和地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 texture | |
n.(织物)质地;(材料)构造;结构;肌理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 syllogism | |
n.演绎法,三段论法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 plausibly | |
似真地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 contiguity | |
n.邻近,接壤 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 logic | |
n.逻辑(学);逻辑性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 strenuous | |
adj.奋发的,使劲的;紧张的;热烈的,狂热的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 inevitable | |
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 syllogistic | |
adj.三段论法的,演绎的,演绎性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 ingenuity | |
n.别出心裁;善于发明创造 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 unaware | |
a.不知道的,未意识到的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 casually | |
adv.漠不关心地,无动于衷地,不负责任地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 gallop | |
v./n.(马或骑马等)飞奔;飞速发展 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 credulous | |
adj.轻信的,易信的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 random | |
adj.随机的;任意的;n.偶然的(或随便的)行动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 audacity | |
n.大胆,卤莽,无礼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 persistent | |
adj.坚持不懈的,执意的;持续的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 isolated | |
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 subconscious | |
n./adj.潜意识(的),下意识(的) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 subconsciously | |
ad.下意识地,潜意识地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 irresistibly | |
adv.无法抵抗地,不能自持地;极为诱惑人地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 instinctively | |
adv.本能地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 inefficient | |
adj.效率低的,无效的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 protagonist | |
n.(思想观念的)倡导者;主角,主人公 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 astonishment | |
n.惊奇,惊异 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 repent | |
v.悔悟,悔改,忏悔,后悔 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 dressing | |
n.(食物)调料;包扎伤口的用品,敷料 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 crab | |
n.螃蟹,偏航,脾气乖戾的人,酸苹果;vi.捕蟹,偏航,发牢骚;vt.使偏航,发脾气 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 folly | |
n.愚笨,愚蠢,蠢事,蠢行,傻话 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 relinquished | |
交出,让给( relinquish的过去式和过去分词 ); 放弃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 prey | |
n.被掠食者,牺牲者,掠食;v.捕食,掠夺,折磨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 acting | |
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 nude | |
adj.裸体的;n.裸体者,裸体艺术品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 propriety | |
n.正当行为;正当;适当 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 remarkable | |
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 plaza | |
n.广场,市场 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 spoke | |
n.(车轮的)辐条;轮辐;破坏某人的计划;阻挠某人的行动 v.讲,谈(speak的过去式);说;演说;从某种观点来说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 elongated | |
v.延长,加长( elongate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 narrated | |
v.故事( narrate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 flirting | |
v.调情,打情骂俏( flirt的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 equanimity | |
n.沉着,镇定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 futile | |
adj.无效的,无用的,无希望的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 villain | |
n.反派演员,反面人物;恶棍;问题的起因 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 vaguely | |
adv.含糊地,暖昧地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 manifestation | |
n.表现形式;表明;现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 sensory | |
adj.知觉的,感觉的,知觉器官的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 conclusive | |
adj.最后的,结论的;确凿的,消除怀疑的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 exhaustion | |
n.耗尽枯竭,疲惫,筋疲力尽,竭尽,详尽无遗的论述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 psychic | |
n.对超自然力敏感的人;adj.有超自然力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 psychology | |
n.心理,心理学,心理状态 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 peripheral | |
adj.周边的,外围的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 fortified | |
adj. 加强的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 inadequate | |
adj.(for,to)不充足的,不适当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 postal | |
adj.邮政的,邮局的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 tracts | |
大片土地( tract的名词复数 ); 地带; (体内的)道; (尤指宣扬宗教、伦理或政治的)短文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 criticise | |
v.批评,评论;非难 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 sift | |
v.筛撒,纷落,详察 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 delightful | |
adj.令人高兴的,使人快乐的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |