Immanuel Kant is generally regarded as the greatest of the modern philosophers. Though he lived through the Seven Years War and the French Revolution, he never interrupted his teaching of philosophy at K?nigsberg in East Prussia. His most distinctive1 contribution was the invention of what he called the 'critical' philosophy, which, assuming as a datum2 that there is knowledge of various kinds, inquired how such knowledge comes to be possible, and deduced, from the answer to this inquiry3, many metaphysical results as to the nature of the world. Whether these results were valid4 may well be doubted. But Kant undoubtedly5 deserves credit for two things: first, for having perceived that we have a priori knowledge which is not purely6 'analytic7', i.e. such that the opposite would be self-contradictory, and secondly8, for having made evident the philosophical9 importance of the theory of knowledge.
Before the time of Kant, it was generally held that whatever knowledge was a priori must be 'analytic'. What this word means will be best illustrated10 by examples. If I say, 'A bald man is a man', 'A plane figure is a figure', 'A bad poet is a poet', I make a purely analytic judgement: the subject spoken about is given as having at least two properties, of which one is singled out to be asserted of it. Such propositions as the above are trivial, and would never be enunciated11 in real life except by an orator12 preparing the way for a piece of sophistry13. They are called 'analytic' because the predicate is obtained by merely analysing the subject. Before the time of Kant it was thought that all judgements of which we could be certain a priori were of this kind: that in all of them there was a predicate which was only part of the subject of which it was asserted. If this were so, we should be involved in a definite contradiction if we attempted to deny anything that could be known a priori. 'A bald man is not bald' would assert and deny baldness of the same man, and would therefore contradict itself. Thus according to the philosophers before Kant, the law of contradiction, which asserts that nothing can at the same time have and not have a certain property, sufficed to establish the truth of all a priori knowledge.
Hume (1711-76), who preceded Kant, accepting the usual view as to what makes knowledge a priori, discovered that, in many cases which had previously14 been supposed analytic, and notably15 in the case of cause and effect, the connexion was really synthetic16. Before Hume, rationalists at least had supposed that the effect could be logically deduced from the cause, if only we had sufficient knowledge. Hume argued—correctly, as would now be generally admitted—that this could not be done. Hence he inferred the far more doubtful proposition that nothing could be known a priori about the connexion of cause and effect. Kant, who had been educated in the rationalist tradition, was much perturbed18 by Hume's scepticism, and endeavoured to find an answer to it. He perceived that not only the connexion of cause and effect, but all the propositions of arithmetic and geometry, are 'synthetic', i.e. not analytic: in all these propositions, no analysis of the subject will reveal the predicate. His stock instance was the proposition 7 + 5 = 12. He pointed19 out, quite truly, that 7 and 5 have to be put together to give 12: the idea of 12 is not contained in them, nor even in the idea of adding them together. Thus he was led to the conclusion that all pure mathematics, though a priori, is synthetic; and this conclusion raised a new problem of which he endeavoured to find the solution.
The question which Kant put at the beginning of his philosophy, namely 'How is pure mathematics possible?' is an interesting and difficult one, to which every philosophy which is not purely sceptical must find some answer. The answer of the pure empiricists, that our mathematical knowledge is derived20 by induction21 from particular instances, we have already seen to be inadequate22, for two reasons: first, that the validity of the inductive principle itself cannot be proved by induction; secondly, that the general propositions of mathematics, such as 'two and two always make four', can obviously be known with certainty by consideration of a single instance, and gain nothing by enumeration23 of other cases in which they have been found to be true. Thus our knowledge of the general propositions of mathematics (and the same applies to logic17) must be accounted for otherwise than our (merely probable) knowledge of empirical generalizations24 such as 'all men are mortal'.
The problem arises through the fact that such knowledge is general, whereas all experience is particular. It seems strange that we should apparently25 be able to know some truths in advance about particular things of which we have as yet no experience; but it cannot easily be doubted that logic and arithmetic will apply to such things. We do not know who will be the inhabitants of London a hundred years hence; but we know that any two of them and any other two of them will make four of them. This apparent power of anticipating facts about things of which we have no experience is certainly surprising. Kant's solution of the problem, though not valid in my opinion, is interesting. It is, however, very difficult, and is differently understood by different philosophers. We can, therefore, only give the merest outline of it, and even that will be thought misleading by many exponents26 of Kant's system.
What Kant maintained was that in all our experience there are two elements to be distinguished27, the one due to the object (i.e. to what we have called the 'physical object'), the other due to our own nature. We saw, in discussing matter and sense-data, that the physical object is different from the associated sense-data, and that the sense-data are to be regarded as resulting from an interaction between the physical object and ourselves. So far, we are in agreement with Kant. But what is distinctive of Kant is the way in which he apportions28 the shares of ourselves and the physical object respectively. He considers that the crude material given in sensation—the colour, hardness, etc.—is due to the object, and that what we supply is the arrangement in space and time, and all the relations between sense-data which result from comparison or from considering one as the cause of the other or in any other way. His chief reason in favour of this view is that we seem to have a priori knowledge as to space and time and causality and comparison, but not as to the actual crude material of sensation. We can be sure, he says, that anything we shall ever experience must show the characteristics affirmed of it in our a priori knowledge, because these characteristics are due to our own nature, and therefore nothing can ever come into our experience without acquiring these characteristics.
The physical object, which he calls the 'thing in itself',(1) he regards as essentially29 unknowable; what can be known is the object as we have it in experience, which he calls the 'phenomenon'. The phenomenon, being a joint30 product of us and the thing in itself, is sure to have those characteristics which are due to us, and is therefore sure to conform to our a priori knowledge. Hence this knowledge, though true of all actual and possible experience, must not be supposed to apply outside experience. Thus in spite of the existence of a priori knowledge, we cannot know anything about the thing in itself or about what is not an actual or possible object of experience. In this way he tries to reconcile and harmonize the contentions31 of the rationalists with the arguments of the empiricists.
(1) Kant's 'thing in itself' is identical in definition with the physical object, namely, it is the cause of sensations. In the properties deduced from the definition it is not identical, since Kant held (in spite of some inconsistency as regards cause) that we can know that none of the categories are applicable to the 'thing in itself'.
Apart from minor32 grounds on which Kant's philosophy may be criticized, there is one main objection which seems fatal to any attempt to deal with the problem of a priori knowledge by his method. The thing to be accounted for is our certainty that the facts must always conform to logic and arithmetic. To say that logic and arithmetic are contributed by us does not account for this. Our nature is as much a fact of the existing world as anything, and there can be no certainty that it will remain constant. It might happen, if Kant is right, that to-morrow our nature would so change as to make two and two become five. This possibility seems never to have occurred to him, yet it is one which utterly33 destroys the certainty and universality which he is anxious to vindicate34 for arithmetical propositions. It is true that this possibility, formally, is inconsistent with the Kantian view that time itself is a form imposed by the subject upon phenomena35, so that our real Self is not in time and has no to-morrow. But he will still have to suppose that the time-order of phenomena is determined36 by characteristics of what is behind phenomena, and this suffices for the substance of our argument.
Reflection, moreover, seems to make it clear that, if there is any truth in our arithmetical beliefs, they must apply to things equally whether we think of them or not. Two physical objects and two other physical objects must make four physical objects, even if physical objects cannot be experienced. To assert this is certainly within the scope of what we mean when we state that two and two are four. Its truth is just as indubitable as the truth of the assertion that two phenomena and two other phenomena make four phenomena. Thus Kant's solution unduly37 limits the scope of a priori propositions, in addition to failing in the attempt at explaining their certainty.
Apart from the special doctrines38 advocated by Kant, it is very common among philosophers to regard what is a priori as in some sense mental, as concerned rather with the way we must think than with any fact of the outer world. We noted39 in the preceding chapter the three principles commonly called 'laws of thought'. The view which led to their being so named is a natural one, but there are strong reasons for thinking that it is erroneous. Let us take as an illustration the law of contradiction. This is commonly stated in the form 'Nothing can both be and not be', which is intended to express the fact that nothing can at once have and not have a given quality. Thus, for example, if a tree is a beech40 it cannot also be not a beech; if my table is rectangular it cannot also be not rectangular, and so on.
Now what makes it natural to call this principle a law of thought is that it is by thought rather than by outward observation that we persuade ourselves of its necessary truth. When we have seen that a tree is a beech, we do not need to look again in order to ascertain41 whether it is also not a beech; thought alone makes us know that this is impossible. But the conclusion that the law of contradiction is a law of thought is nevertheless erroneous. What we believe, when we believe the law of contradiction, is not that the mind is so made that it must believe the law of contradiction. This belief is a subsequent result of psychological reflection, which presupposes the belief in the law of contradiction. The belief in the law of contradiction is a belief about things, not only about thoughts. It is not, e.g., the belief that if we think a certain tree is a beech, we cannot at the same time think that it is not a beech; it is the belief that if the tree is a beech, it cannot at the same time be not a beech. Thus the law of contradiction is about things, and not merely about thoughts; and although belief in the law of contradiction is a thought, the law of contradiction itself is not a thought, but a fact concerning the things in the world. If this, which we believe when we believe the law of contradiction, were not true of the things in the world, the fact that we were compelled to think it true would not save the law of contradiction from being false; and this shows that the law is not a law of thought.
A similar argument applies to any other a priori judgement. When we judge that two and two are four, we are not making a judgement about our thoughts, but about all actual or possible couples. The fact that our minds are so constituted as to believe that two and two are four, though it is true, is emphatically not what we assert when we assert that two and two are four. And no fact about the constitution of our minds could make it true that two and two are four. Thus our a priori knowledge, if it is not erroneous, is not merely knowledge about the constitution of our minds, but is applicable to whatever the world may contain, both what is mental and what is non-mental.
The fact seems to be that all our a priori knowledge is concerned with entities42 which do not, properly speaking, exist, either in the mental or in the physical world. These entities are such as can be named by parts of speech which are not substantives43; they are such entities as qualities and relations. Suppose, for instance, that I am in my room. I exist, and my room exists; but does 'in' exist? Yet obviously the word 'in' has a meaning; it denotes a relation which holds between me and my room. This relation is something, although we cannot say that it exists in the same sense in which I and my room exist. The relation 'in' is something which we can think about and understand, for, if we could not understand it, we could not understand the sentence 'I am in my room'. Many philosophers, following Kant, have maintained that relations are the work of the mind, that things in themselves have no relations, but that the mind brings them together in one act of thought and thus produces the relations which it judges them to have.
This view, however, seems open to objections similar to those which we urged before against Kant. It seems plain that it is not thought which produces the truth of the proposition 'I am in my room'. It may be true that an earwig is in my room, even if neither I nor the earwig nor any one else is aware of this truth; for this truth concerns only the earwig and the room, and does not depend upon anything else. Thus relations, as we shall see more fully44 in the next chapter, must be placed in a world which is neither mental nor physical. This world is of great importance to philosophy, and in particular to the problems of a priori knowledge. In the next chapter we shall proceed to develop its nature and its bearing upon the questions with which we have been dealing45.
点击收听单词发音
1 distinctive | |
adj.特别的,有特色的,与众不同的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 datum | |
n.资料;数据;已知数 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 valid | |
adj.有确实根据的;有效的;正当的,合法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 undoubtedly | |
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 purely | |
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 analytic | |
adj.分析的,用分析方法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 secondly | |
adv.第二,其次 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 illustrated | |
adj. 有插图的,列举的 动词illustrate的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 enunciated | |
v.(清晰地)发音( enunciate的过去式和过去分词 );确切地说明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 orator | |
n.演说者,演讲者,雄辩家 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 sophistry | |
n.诡辩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 notably | |
adv.值得注意地,显著地,尤其地,特别地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 synthetic | |
adj.合成的,人工的;综合的;n.人工制品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 logic | |
n.逻辑(学);逻辑性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 perturbed | |
adj.烦燥不安的v.使(某人)烦恼,不安( perturb的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 pointed | |
adj.尖的,直截了当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 induction | |
n.感应,感应现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 inadequate | |
adj.(for,to)不充足的,不适当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 enumeration | |
n.计数,列举;细目;详表;点查 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 generalizations | |
一般化( generalization的名词复数 ); 普通化; 归纳; 概论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 apparently | |
adv.显然地;表面上,似乎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 exponents | |
n.倡导者( exponent的名词复数 );说明者;指数;能手 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 apportions | |
n.分摊,分配( apportion的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 joint | |
adj.联合的,共同的;n.关节,接合处;v.连接,贴合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 contentions | |
n.竞争( contention的名词复数 );争夺;争论;论点 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 minor | |
adj.较小(少)的,较次要的;n.辅修学科;vi.辅修 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 utterly | |
adv.完全地,绝对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 vindicate | |
v.为…辩护或辩解,辩明;证明…正确 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 unduly | |
adv.过度地,不适当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 doctrines | |
n.教条( doctrine的名词复数 );教义;学说;(政府政策的)正式声明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 noted | |
adj.著名的,知名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 beech | |
n.山毛榉;adj.山毛榉的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 ascertain | |
vt.发现,确定,查明,弄清 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 entities | |
实体对像; 实体,独立存在体,实际存在物( entity的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 substantives | |
n.作名词用的词或词组(substantive的复数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 dealing | |
n.经商方法,待人态度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |