As this is the one solitary3 fact which is held to negative the mass of evidence, anatomical and physiological4, in favor of the Sensibility of the spinal cord, it is necessary that we should candidly6 examine it. No reader will suppose that during the twenty years in which I have advocated the doctrine7 expounded8 in this volume, I have not been fully9 alive to the one fact which prevented the general acceptance of the doctrine. From the first it has seemed to me that the fact has been misinterpreted.
85. Certain injuries to the spinal cord destroy the connection of the parts below the injury with the parts above it; consequently no impression made on the limbs below the injured spot is transmitted to the brain, nor can any cerebral10 incitation11 reach those limbs. The patient has lost all consciousness of these limbs, and all551 control over them. Hunter’s patient on being asked if he felt any pain when the prick12 caused his leg to kick, answered, “No: but you see my leg does.” This answer has been regarded as a drollery13; I think it expressed a physiological truth. For on the assumption that the whole of the cerebro-spinal axis14 had one uniform property, corresponding with its uniform structure, and various functions, corresponding with the variety of organs it innervates, a division of this axis would necessarily create two independent seats of Sensibility, and interrupt the consensus15 of their functions. In such a case it would be absurd to expect that the cerebral segment could be affected16 by, or co-operate with, what affected the spinal segment.
Now, when a man has a diseased spinal cord, the seat of injury causes, for the time at least, a division of the whole group of centres into two independent groups. For all purposes of sensation and volition17 it is the same as if he were cut in half; his nervous mechanism18 is cut in half. How then can any cerebral control be obeyed by his legs; how can any impression on his legs be felt by his cerebrum? As well might we expect the man whose arm has been amputated, to feel the incisions19 of the scalpel, when that limb is conveyed to the dissecting-table, as to feel by his brain impressions made upon parts wholly divorced from organic connection with the brain.
86. But, it may be objected, this is the very point urged. The man himself does not feel the impressions on his legs when his spine20 has been injured; he is as insensible to them as to the dissection21 of his amputated arm. Very true. He does not feel it. But if the amputated arm were to strike the anatomist who began its dissection, if its fingers were to grasp the scalpel, and push it away, or with the thumb to rub off the acid irritating one of the fingers, I do not see how we could552 refuse to admit that the arm felt although the man did not. And this is the case with the extremities22 of a man whose spine is injured. They manifest every indication of sensibility. In the frog and pigeon the legs manifest the unmistakable control which we ascribe to volition. It is true that the man himself, when interrogated23, declares that he feels nothing; the cerebral segment has attached to it organs of speech and expressive24 features, by which its sensations can be communicated to others; whereas the spinal segment has no such means of communicating its sensations; but those which it has, it employs. You can ask the cerebral segment a question, which can be heard, understood, and answered; this is not the case with the spinal segment: yet if you test its sensibility, the result is unequivocal. You cannot ask an animal whether it feels, but you can test its sensibility, and that test suffices.
87. The question we have to decide, therefore, is not whether a patient, with an injured spine, can feel impressions on, or convey voluntary impulses to, limbs below the seat of injury—for as respects the nervous mechanism these limbs are separated from him, no less than if actual amputation25 had taken place—the question is, whether these separated limbs have any sensibility? And the answer seems to me unequivocally affirmative. I assert, therefore, that if there is ample evidence to show that the spinal centres have sensibility, when separated from the cerebral centres, such evidence can in no respect be weakened by the fact that a man with an injured spine is unconscious of impressions made below the seat of injury; since such a fact necessarily follows from the establishment of two centres: the parts above are then not sensitive to impressions on the parts below; nor are the parts below sensitive to impressions on the parts above; but each segment is sensitive to its own affections.
553 88. Every one knows that there are animals, low down in the scale, which may be cut in two, each half continuing to live, and each capable of reproducing its lost segments. Would any one, seeing these separated halves move and manifest ordinary signs of sensibility, venture to say that the one half was a living, the other an insentient, mechanism? And since the one half had eyes, mouth, tentacles26, etc., while the other half had none of these, would the observer be surprised that the functions of the one differed from those of the other in these respects? Why, then, should he not conclude the same of the two halves of the human mechanism, when disease had divided them?
89. The man, you urge, does not feel the prick on his leg. This is true, because “the man” here designates the seeing, hearing, tasting, smelling, talking, thinking group of organs—to the exclusion27 of the limb or limbs which are no longer in sensitive connection with this group. When a leg is amputated “the man” remains—a truncated28 man, indeed, yet still one having all the distinguishing human characters. Yet obviously in strict language we can no longer say that the man is the same as he was. “Man” or “animal” means the complex whole; and each anatomically separable part forms one constituent29 of that whole. The medulla oblongata and spinal cord innervate certain parts; the mesencephalon innervates others; the cerebrum rises above the whole. If after removing one limb, then another, we continued truncating30 the organism till we left only the head, should we call that the man? Clearly not. Should we even suppose that the intact brain—the supposed seat of sensation and volition—still felt, and willed? Clearly not. There is absolutely no evidence, however faint, of the isolated31 head manifesting any sensational32 and volitional33 phenomena34; whereas there is ample evidence of the truncated554 spinal cord manifesting some of these phenomena. And this is intelligible35 when we understand that the nerve-centres stimulate36 into action the organs they innervate, but do not by themselves play any other part.
90. “The man” then does not feel the prick on his leg, but his leg feels it. The man has no consciousness of what takes place outside the sphere of his sensitive mechanism; and the leg is now outside that sphere. Consciousness—as distinguished37 from Sentience38 in general—we have seen to be a resultant of the composition of forces co-operating at the moment; the Sensibility of the spinal cord in the regions below the injury cannot now enter into that composition. It is detached from the upper organs. But inasmuch as the organs it innervates are still living and active, the functions of this detached portion are still displayed. We have seen the dog with divided cord capable of Urination, Defecation, Generation, etc.; its hinder legs, though not moving in a consensus with the forelegs, yet moved independently; and all the normal reflexes of the parts followed on stimulations. To say that “the dog” showed no signs of Sensibility when its hinder limbs were irritated, is identifying “the dog” with the anterior39 half of the organism which was not in connection with the posterior half. It is equally true that the posterior half showed no signs of Sensibility when the anterior was irritated. The two halves were united by the circulation, nutrition, etc., but disunited as to sensation and volition.
91. Do I then suppose the separated half of an animal to feel pain and pleasure, hope and terror? The reader who has attentively40 followed the exposition will be at no loss to answer. Pain, pleasure, hope, and terror, are special modes of Sensibility, dependent on particular neural41 combinations. The organs comprised in the anterior half of the animal furnish the main conditions for these special modes, whereas the organs comprised in the555 posterior half furnish few or none of those—they contain none of the special Senses, and they are without the chief combining centre, the brain. But since we know that a large amount of normal Sensation is wholly without the special characters of pain, pleasure, hope, or terror, we need not hesitate to assign Sensation to the spinal cord because these characters are absent.
92. All I contend for is that the spinal centres have Sensibility of the same order as the cerebral centres; and that in the normal organism this Sensibility enters as a factor into the general Consciousness—no one portion of the nervous system being really independent of all the others, all co-operating in every result. Over and over again I have had to insist that the property of Sensibility is only the general condition of Sensation; and that each particular sensation receives its character from the organs innervated, plus the reaction of the whole organism. Obviously, therefore, the peculiar42 character of a sensation, or “state of consciousness,” must vary with the variations in either of these factors. To say that every segment of the spinal cord has Sensibility, is not saying that an excitation of that segment will produce a particular sensation of definite character; because for this definite character there is needed the co-operation of all those parts of the mechanism which enter into the complex product.
* * * * *
93. And here attention must be called to a double fallacy pervading43 the arguments on the other side. It is always assumed that the reactions of an organ, or part of the organism, when separated from the rest, are typical of their reactions when forming constituents44 of the normal organism. Nothing of the kind. The movement of a muscle or a limb separated from the body may resemble that movement when normally effected—but only as the movements of a mechanical bird resemble those of a living bird: the modes of production are different. So that556 were we to grant the postulate45 of the brain being the exclusive seat of sensation, we should still deny that an action which was effected after removal of the brain was typical of the action effected when the brain was present. The leg of Hunter’s patient jerked when the skin was irritated; but this action could not be altogether the same as the similar action in a leg united with the rest of the sensitive mechanism. Nor is this all. The leg may have been insensible, the spinal segment which innervated it may have been wholly without Sensibility, and still we should have to question the logic5 which extended such an inference to the very different and far more complex actions of decapitated animals. On this ground:—The leg is, by the hypothesis, insensible because cut off from all connection with the sensitive mechanism. But this is not the case with the decapitated animal: there still remain the essential parts of a sensitive mechanism—all the chief organs are still in activity, still manifesting their functions. Decapitation has produced a great disturbance46 in the mechanism, and has removed an important centre; but nevertheless every impression excites a connected group of centres, and this group responds.
* * * * *
94. In conclusion, unless we adopt the opinion that Sensation—Consciousness—Sensibility, is something not belonging to the physiological properties of the nervous system in a vital organism (the opinion held by spiritualists), there seems no alternative but to adopt the opinion advocated in this volume, namely, that the physiological properties of the nervous system are inseparable from every segment of that system; and the functions are the manifestation47 of those properties as determined48 by the special organs with the co-operation of all.
The End
The End
点击收听单词发音
1 irresistible | |
adj.非常诱人的,无法拒绝的,无法抗拒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 spinal | |
adj.针的,尖刺的,尖刺状突起的;adj.脊骨的,脊髓的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 solitary | |
adj.孤独的,独立的,荒凉的;n.隐士 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 physiological | |
adj.生理学的,生理学上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 logic | |
n.逻辑(学);逻辑性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 candidly | |
adv.坦率地,直率而诚恳地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 expounded | |
论述,详细讲解( expound的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 cerebral | |
adj.脑的,大脑的;有智力的,理智型的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 incitation | |
刺激,激励 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 prick | |
v.刺伤,刺痛,刺孔;n.刺伤,刺痛 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 drollery | |
n.开玩笑,说笑话;滑稽可笑的图画(或故事、小戏等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 axis | |
n.轴,轴线,中心线;坐标轴,基准线 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 consensus | |
n.(意见等的)一致,一致同意,共识 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 affected | |
adj.不自然的,假装的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 volition | |
n.意志;决意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 mechanism | |
n.机械装置;机构,结构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 incisions | |
n.切开,切口( incision的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 spine | |
n.脊柱,脊椎;(动植物的)刺;书脊 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 dissection | |
n.分析;解剖 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 extremities | |
n.端点( extremity的名词复数 );尽头;手和足;极窘迫的境地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 interrogated | |
v.询问( interrogate的过去式和过去分词 );审问;(在计算机或其他机器上)查询 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 expressive | |
adj.表现的,表达…的,富于表情的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 amputation | |
n.截肢 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 tentacles | |
n.触手( tentacle的名词复数 );触角;触须;触毛 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 exclusion | |
n.拒绝,排除,排斥,远足,远途旅行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 truncated | |
adj.切去顶端的,缩短了的,被删节的v.截面的( truncate的过去式和过去分词 );截头的;缩短了的;截去顶端或末端 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 constituent | |
n.选民;成分,组分;adj.组成的,构成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 truncating | |
v.截面的( truncate的现在分词 );截头的;缩短了的;截去顶端或末端 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 isolated | |
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 sensational | |
adj.使人感动的,非常好的,轰动的,耸人听闻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 volitional | |
adj.意志的,凭意志的,有意志的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 intelligible | |
adj.可理解的,明白易懂的,清楚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 stimulate | |
vt.刺激,使兴奋;激励,使…振奋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 sentience | |
n.感觉性;感觉能力;知觉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 anterior | |
adj.较早的;在前的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 attentively | |
adv.聚精会神地;周到地;谛;凝神 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 neural | |
adj.神经的,神经系统的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 pervading | |
v.遍及,弥漫( pervade的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 constituents | |
n.选民( constituent的名词复数 );成分;构成部分;要素 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 postulate | |
n.假定,基本条件;vt.要求,假定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 disturbance | |
n.动乱,骚动;打扰,干扰;(身心)失调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 manifestation | |
n.表现形式;表明;现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |