The maxim1 enjoined2 upon teachers, "to proceed from the concrete to the abstract," is perhaps familiar rather than comprehended. Few who read and hear it gain a clear conception of the starting-point, the concrete; of the nature of the goal, the abstract; and of the exact nature of the path to be traversed in going from one to the other. At times the injunction is positively3 misunderstood, being taken to mean that education should advance from things to thought—as if any dealing4 with things in which thinking is not involved could possibly be educative. So understood, the maxim encourages mechanical routine or sensuous5 excitation at one end of the educational scale—the lower—and academic and unapplied learning at the upper end.
Actually, all dealing with things, even the child's, is immersed in inferences; things are clothed by the suggestions they arouse, and are significant as challenges to interpretation7 or as evidences to substantiate8 a belief. Nothing could be more unnatural9 than instruction in things without thought; in sense-perceptions without judgments10 based upon them. And if the abstract to which we are to proceed denotes thought apart from things, the goal recommended is formal and[Pg 136] empty, for effective thought always refers, more or less directly, to things.
Direct and indirect understanding again
Yet the maxim has a meaning which, understood and supplemented, states the line of development of logical capacity. What is this signification? Concrete denotes a meaning definitely marked off from other meanings so that it is readily apprehended11 by itself. When we hear the words, table, chair, stove, coat, we do not have to reflect in order to grasp what is meant. The terms convey meaning so directly that no effort at translating is needed. The meanings of some terms and things, however, are grasped only by first calling to mind more familiar things and then tracing out connections between them and what we do not understand. Roughly speaking, the former kind of meanings is concrete; the latter abstract.
What is familiar is mentally concrete
To one who is thoroughly12 at home in physics and chemistry, the notions of atom and molecule13 are fairly concrete. They are constantly used without involving any labor14 of thought in apprehending15 what they mean. But the layman16 and the beginner in science have first to remind themselves of things with which they already are well acquainted, and go through a process of slow translation; the terms atom and molecule losing, moreover, their hard-won meaning only too easily if familiar things, and the line of transition from them to the strange, drop out of mind. The same difference is illustrated17 by any technical terms: coefficient and exponent18 in algebra19, triangle and square in their geometric as distinct from their popular meanings; capital and value as used in political economy, and so on.
Practical things are familiar
The difference as noted20 is purely21 relative to the intellectual progress of an individual; what is abstract[Pg 137] at one period of growth is concrete at another; or even the contrary, as one finds that things supposed to be thoroughly familiar involve strange factors and unsolved problems. There is, nevertheless, a general line of cleavage which, deciding upon the whole what things fall within the limits of familiar acquaintance and what without, marks off the concrete and the abstract in a more permanent way. These limits are fixed22 mainly by the demands of practical life. Things such as sticks and stones, meat and potatoes, houses and trees, are such constant features of the environment of which we have to take account in order to live, that their important meanings are soon learnt, and indissolubly associated with objects. We are acquainted with a thing (or it is familiar to us) when we have so much to do with it that its strange and unexpected corners are rubbed off. The necessities of social intercourse23 convey to adults a like concreteness upon such terms as taxes, elections, wages, the law, and so on. Things the meaning of which I personally do not take in directly, appliances of cook, carpenter, or weaver24, for example, are nevertheless unhesitatingly classed as concrete, since they are so directly connected with our common social life.
By contrast, the abstract is the theoretical, or that not intimately associated with practical concerns. The abstract thinker (the man of pure science as he is sometimes called) deliberately26 abstracts from application in life; that is, he leaves practical uses out of account. This, however, is a merely negative statement. What remains28 when connections with use and application are excluded? Evidently only what has to do with knowing considered as an end in itself. Many notions of science[Pg 138] are abstract, not only because they cannot be understood without a long apprenticeship29 in the science (which is equally true of technical matters in the arts), but also because the whole content of their meaning has been framed for the sole purpose of facilitating further knowledge, inquiry30, and speculation31. When thinking is used as a means to some end, good, or value beyond itself, it is concrete; when it is employed simply as a means to more thinking, it is abstract. To a theorist an idea is adequate and self-contained just because it engages and rewards thought; to a medical practitioner32, an engineer, an artist, a merchant, a politician, it is complete only when employed in the furthering of some interest in life—health, wealth, beauty, goodness, success, or what you will.
Contempt for theory
For the great majority of men under ordinary circumstances, the practical exigencies33 of life are almost, if not quite, coercive. Their main business is the proper conduct of their affairs. Whatever is of significance only as affording scope for thinking is pallid34 and remote—almost artificial. Hence the contempt felt by the practical and successful executive for the "mere27 theorist"; hence his conviction that certain things may be all very well in theory, but that they will not do in practice; in general, the depreciatory35 way in which he uses the terms abstract, theoretical, and intellectual—as distinct from intelligent.
But theory is highly practical
This attitude is justified36, of course, under certain conditions. But depreciation37 of theory does not contain the whole truth, as common or practical sense recognizes. There is such a thing, even from the common-sense standpoint, as being "too practical," as being so intent upon the immediately practical as not to see[Pg 139] beyond the end of one's nose or as to cut off the limb upon which one is sitting. The question is one of limits, of degrees and adjustments, rather than one of absolute separation. Truly practical men give their minds free play about a subject without asking too closely at every point for the advantage to be gained; exclusive preoccupation with matters of use and application so narrows the horizon as in the long run to defeat itself. It does not pay to tether one's thoughts to the post of use with too short a rope. Power in action requires some largeness and imaginativeness of vision. Men must at least have enough interest in thinking for the sake of thinking to escape the limits of routine and custom. Interest in knowledge for the sake of knowledge, in thinking for the sake of the free play of thought, is necessary then to the emancipation39 of practical life—to make it rich and progressive.
Begin with the concrete means begin with practical manipulations
1. Since the concrete denotes thinking applied6 to activities for the sake of dealing effectively with the difficulties that present themselves practically, "beginning with the concrete" signifies that we should at the outset make much of doing; especially, make much in occupations that are not of a routine and mechanical kind and hence require intelligent selection and adaptation of means and materials. We do not "follow the order of nature" when we multiply mere sensations or accumulate physical objects. Instruction in number is not concrete merely because splints or beans or dots are employed, while whenever the use and bearing of number relations are clearly perceived, the number idea is concrete even if figures alone are used. Just what sort of[Pg 140] symbol it is best to use at a given time—whether blocks, or lines, or figures—is entirely41 a matter of adjustment to the given case. If physical things used in teaching number or geography or anything else do not leave the mind illuminated42 with recognition of a meaning beyond themselves, the instruction that uses them is as abstract as that which doles43 out ready-made definitions and rules; for it distracts attention from ideas to mere physical excitations.
The conception that we have only to put before the senses particular physical objects in order to impress certain ideas upon the mind amounts almost to a superstition45. The introduction of object lessons and sense-training scored a distinct advance over the prior method of linguistic46 symbols, and this advance tended to blind educators to the fact that only a halfway47 step had been taken. Things and sensations develop the child, indeed, but only because he uses them in mastering his body and in the scheme of his activities. Appropriate continuous occupations or activities involve the use of natural materials, tools, modes of energy, and do it in a way that compels thinking as to what they mean, how they are related to one another and to the realization48 of ends; while the mere isolated presentation of things remains barren and dead. A few generations ago the great obstacle in the way of reform of primary education was belief in the almost magical efficacy of the symbols of language (including number) to produce mental training; at present, belief in the efficacy of objects just as objects, blocks the way. As frequently happens, the better is an enemy of the best.
Transfer of interest to intellectual matters
2. The interest in results, in the successful carrying on of an activity, should be gradually transferred to study[Pg 141] of objects—their properties, consequences, structures, causes, and effects. The adult when at work in his life calling is rarely free to devote time or energy—beyond the necessities of his immediate38 action—to the study of what he deals with. (Ante, p. 43.) The educative activities of childhood should be so arranged that direct interest in the activity and its outcome create a demand for attention to matters that have a more and more indirect and remote connection with the original activity. The direct interest in carpentering or shop work should yield organically and gradually an interest in geometric and mechanical problems. The interest in cooking should grow into an interest in chemical experimentation49 and in the physiology50 and hygiene51 of bodily growth. The making of pictures should pass to an interest in the technique of representation and the ?sthetics of appreciation52, and so on. This development is what the term go signifies in the maxim "go from the concrete to the abstract"; it represents the dynamic and truly educative factor of the process.
Development of delight in the activity of thinking
3. The outcome, the abstract to which education is to proceed, is an interest in intellectual matters for their own sake, a delight in thinking for the sake of thinking. It is an old story that acts and processes which at the outset are incidental to something else develop and maintain an absorbing value of their own. So it is with thinking and with knowledge; at first incidental to results and adjustments beyond themselves, they attract more and more attention to themselves till they become ends, not means. Children engage, unconstrainedly and continually, in reflective inspection53 and testing for the sake of what they are interested in doing successfully. Habits of thinking thus generated may increase in volume[Pg 142] and extent till they become of importance on their own account.
Examples of the transition
The three instances cited in Chapter Six represented an ascending54 cycle from the practical to the theoretical. Taking thought to keep a personal engagement is obviously of the concrete kind. Endeavoring to work out the meaning of a certain part of a boat is an instance of an intermediate kind. The reason for the existence and position of the pole is a practical reason, so that to the architect the problem was purely concrete—the maintenance of a certain system of action. But for the passenger on the boat, the problem was theoretical, more or less speculative55. It made no difference to his reaching his destination whether he worked out the meaning of the pole. The third case, that of the appearance and movement of the bubbles, illustrates56 a strictly theoretical or abstract case. No overcoming of physical obstacles, no adjustment of external means to ends, is at stake. Curiosity, intellectual curiosity, is challenged by a seemingly anomalous57 occurrence; and thinking tries simply to account for an apparent exception in terms of recognized principles.
Theoretical knowledge never the whole end
(i) Abstract thinking, it should be noted, represents an end, not the end. The power of sustained thinking on matters remote from direct use is an outgrowth of practical and immediate modes of thought, but not a substitute for them. The educational end is not the destruction of power to think so as to surmount58 obstacles and adjust means and ends; it is not its replacement59 by abstract reflection. Nor is theoretical thinking a higher type of thinking than practical. A person who has at command both types of thinking is of a higher order than he who possesses only one. Methods that in de[Pg 143]veloping abstract intellectual abilities weaken habits of practical or concrete thinking, fall as much short of the educational ideal as do the methods that in cultivating ability to plan, to invent, to arrange, to forecast, fail to secure some delight in thinking irrespective of practical consequences.
Nor that most congenial to the majority of pupils
(ii) Educators should also note the very great individual differences that exist; they should not try to force one pattern and model upon all. In many (probably the majority) the executive tendency, the habit of mind that thinks for purposes of conduct and achievement, not for the sake of knowing, remains dominant60 to the end. Engineers, lawyers, doctors, merchants, are much more numerous in adult life than scholars, scientists, and philosophers. While education should strive to make men who, however prominent their professional interests and aims, partake of the spirit of the scholar, philosopher, and scientist, no good reason appears why education should esteem61 the one mental habit inherently superior to the other, and deliberately try to transform the type from practical to theoretical. Have not our schools (as already suggested, p. 49) been one-sidedly devoted62 to the more abstract type of thinking, thus doing injustice63 to the majority of pupils? Has not the idea of a "liberal" and "humane64" education tended too often in practice to the production of technical, because overspecialized, thinkers?
Aim of education is a working balance
The aim of education should be to secure a balanced interaction of the two types of mental attitude, having sufficient regard to the disposition65 of the individual not to hamper66 and cripple whatever powers are naturally strong in him. The narrowness of individuals of strong concrete bent67 needs to be liberalized. Every oppor[Pg 144]tunity that occurs within their practical activities for developing curiosity and susceptibility to intellectual problems should be seized. Violence is not done to natural disposition, but the latter is broadened. As regards the smaller number of those who have a taste for abstract, purely intellectual topics, pains should be taken to multiply opportunities and demands for the application of ideas; for translating symbolic68 truths into terms of social life and its ends. Every human being has both capabilities69, and every individual will be more effective and happier if both powers are developed in easy and close interaction with each other.
点击收听单词发音
1 maxim | |
n.格言,箴言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 enjoined | |
v.命令( enjoin的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 positively | |
adv.明确地,断然,坚决地;实在,确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 dealing | |
n.经商方法,待人态度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 sensuous | |
adj.激发美感的;感官的,感觉上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 interpretation | |
n.解释,说明,描述;艺术处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 substantiate | |
v.证实;证明...有根据 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 unnatural | |
adj.不自然的;反常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 judgments | |
判断( judgment的名词复数 ); 鉴定; 评价; 审判 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 apprehended | |
逮捕,拘押( apprehend的过去式和过去分词 ); 理解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 thoroughly | |
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 molecule | |
n.分子,克分子 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 labor | |
n.劳动,努力,工作,劳工;分娩;vi.劳动,努力,苦干;vt.详细分析;麻烦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 apprehending | |
逮捕,拘押( apprehend的现在分词 ); 理解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 layman | |
n.俗人,门外汉,凡人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 illustrated | |
adj. 有插图的,列举的 动词illustrate的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 exponent | |
n.倡导者,拥护者;代表人物;指数,幂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 algebra | |
n.代数学 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 noted | |
adj.著名的,知名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 purely | |
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 intercourse | |
n.性交;交流,交往,交际 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 weaver | |
n.织布工;编织者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 deliberately | |
adv.审慎地;蓄意地;故意地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 apprenticeship | |
n.学徒身份;学徒期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 speculation | |
n.思索,沉思;猜测;投机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 practitioner | |
n.实践者,从事者;(医生或律师等)开业者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 exigencies | |
n.急切需要 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 pallid | |
adj.苍白的,呆板的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 depreciatory | |
adj.贬值的,蔑视的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 justified | |
a.正当的,有理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 depreciation | |
n.价值低落,贬值,蔑视,贬低 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 emancipation | |
n.(从束缚、支配下)解放 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 recur | |
vi.复发,重现,再发生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 illuminated | |
adj.被照明的;受启迪的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 doles | |
救济物( dole的名词复数 ); 失业救济金 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 isolated | |
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 superstition | |
n.迷信,迷信行为 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 linguistic | |
adj.语言的,语言学的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 halfway | |
adj.中途的,不彻底的,部分的;adv.半路地,在中途,在半途 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 realization | |
n.实现;认识到,深刻了解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 experimentation | |
n.实验,试验,实验法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 physiology | |
n.生理学,生理机能 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 hygiene | |
n.健康法,卫生学 (a.hygienic) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 appreciation | |
n.评价;欣赏;感谢;领会,理解;价格上涨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 inspection | |
n.检查,审查,检阅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 ascending | |
adj.上升的,向上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 speculative | |
adj.思索性的,暝想性的,推理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 illustrates | |
给…加插图( illustrate的第三人称单数 ); 说明; 表明; (用示例、图画等)说明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 anomalous | |
adj.反常的;不规则的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 surmount | |
vt.克服;置于…顶上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 replacement | |
n.取代,替换,交换;替代品,代用品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 dominant | |
adj.支配的,统治的;占优势的;显性的;n.主因,要素,主要的人(或物);显性基因 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 esteem | |
n.尊敬,尊重;vt.尊重,敬重;把…看作 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 devoted | |
adj.忠诚的,忠实的,热心的,献身于...的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 injustice | |
n.非正义,不公正,不公平,侵犯(别人的)权利 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 humane | |
adj.人道的,富有同情心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 disposition | |
n.性情,性格;意向,倾向;排列,部署 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 hamper | |
vt.妨碍,束缚,限制;n.(有盖的)大篮子 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 bent | |
n.爱好,癖好;adj.弯的;决心的,一心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 symbolic | |
adj.象征性的,符号的,象征主义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 capabilities | |
n.能力( capability的名词复数 );可能;容量;[复数]潜在能力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |