Yet some of the topics may have been actually used by Socrates; and the recollection of his very words may have rung in the ears of his disciple14. The Apology of Plato may be compared generally with those speeches of Thucydides in which he has embodied15 his conception of the lofty character and policy of the great Pericles, and which at the same time furnish a commentary on the situation of affairs from the point of view of the historian. So in the Apology there is an ideal rather than a literal truth; much is said which was not said, and is only Plato's view of the situation. Plato was not, like Xenophon, a chronicler of facts; he does not appear in any of his writings to have aimed at literal accuracy. He is not therefore to be supplemented from the Memorabilia and Symposium16 of Xenophon, who belongs to an entirely17 different class of writers. The Apology of Plato is not the report of what Socrates said, but an elaborate composition, quite as much so in fact as one of the Dialogues. And we may perhaps even indulge in the fancy that the actual defence of Socrates was as much greater than the Platonic18 defence as the master was greater than the disciple. But in any case, some of the words used by him must have been remembered, and some of the facts recorded must have actually occurred. It is significant that Plato is said to have been present at the defence (Apol.), as he is also said to have been absent at the last scene in the Phaedo. Is it fanciful to suppose that he meant to give the stamp of authenticity19 to the one and not to the other?—especially when we consider that these two passages are the only ones in which Plato makes mention of himself. The circumstance that Plato was to be one of his sureties for the payment of the fine which he proposed has the appearance of truth. More suspicious is the statement that Socrates received the first impulse to his favourite calling of cross-examining the world from the Oracle20 of Delphi; for he must already have been famous before Chaerephon went to consult the Oracle (Riddell), and the story is of a kind which is very likely to have been invented. On the whole we arrive at the conclusion that the Apology is true to the character of Socrates, but we cannot show that any single sentence in it was actually spoken by him. It breathes the spirit of Socrates, but has been cast anew in the mould of Plato.
There is not much in the other Dialogues which can be compared with the Apology. The same recollection of his master may have been present to the mind of Plato when depicting21 the sufferings of the Just in the Republic. The Crito may also be regarded as a sort of appendage22 to the Apology, in which Socrates, who has defied the judges, is nevertheless represented as scrupulously23 obedient to the laws. The idealization of the sufferer is carried still further in the Gorgias, in which the thesis is maintained, that 'to suffer is better than to do evil;' and the art of rhetoric24 is described as only useful for the purpose of self-accusation25. The parallelisms which occur in the so-called Apology of Xenophon are not worth noticing, because the writing in which they are contained is manifestly spurious. The statements of the Memorabilia respecting the trial and death of Socrates agree generally with Plato; but they have lost the flavour of Socratic irony in the narrative26 of Xenophon.
The Apology or Platonic defence of Socrates is divided into three parts: 1st. The defence properly so called; 2nd. The shorter address in mitigation of the penalty; 3rd. The last words of prophetic rebuke27 and exhortation28.
The first part commences with an apology for his colloquial30 style; he is, as he has always been, the enemy of rhetoric, and knows of no rhetoric but truth; he will not falsify his character by making a speech. Then he proceeds to divide his accusers into two classes; first, there is the nameless accuser—public opinion. All the world from their earliest years had heard that he was a corrupter32 of youth, and had seen him caricatured in the Clouds of Aristophanes. Secondly33, there are the professed34 accusers, who are but the mouth-piece of the others. The accusations35 of both might be summed up in a formula. The first say, 'Socrates is an evil-doer and a curious person, searching into things under the earth and above the heaven; and making the worse appear the better cause, and teaching all this to others.' The second, 'Socrates is an evil-doer and corrupter of the youth, who does not receive the gods whom the state receives, but introduces other new divinities.' These last words appear to have been the actual indictment36 (compare Xen. Mem.); and the previous formula, which is a summary of public opinion, assumes the same legal style.
The answer begins by clearing up a confusion. In the representations of the Comic poets, and in the opinion of the multitude, he had been identified with the teachers of physical science and with the Sophists. But this was an error. For both of them he professes37 a respect in the open court, which contrasts with his manner of speaking about them in other places. (Compare for Anaxagoras, Phaedo, Laws; for the Sophists, Meno, Republic, Tim., Theaet., Soph., etc.) But at the same time he shows that he is not one of them. Of natural philosophy he knows nothing; not that he despises such pursuits, but the fact is that he is ignorant of them, and never says a word about them. Nor is he paid for giving instruction—that is another mistaken notion:—he has nothing to teach. But he commends Evenus for teaching virtue38 at such a 'moderate' rate as five minae. Something of the 'accustomed irony,' which may perhaps be expected to sleep in the ear of the multitude, is lurking39 here.
He then goes on to explain the reason why he is in such an evil name. That had arisen out of a peculiar40 mission which he had taken upon himself. The enthusiastic Chaerephon (probably in anticipation41 of the answer which he received) had gone to Delphi and asked the oracle if there was any man wiser than Socrates; and the answer was, that there was no man wiser. What could be the meaning of this—that he who knew nothing, and knew that he knew nothing, should be declared by the oracle to be the wisest of men? Reflecting upon the answer, he determined42 to refute it by finding 'a wiser;' and first he went to the politicians, and then to the poets, and then to the craftsmen43, but always with the same result—he found that they knew nothing, or hardly anything more than himself; and that the little advantage which in some cases they possessed44 was more than counter-balanced by their conceit45 of knowledge. He knew nothing, and knew that he knew nothing: they knew little or nothing, and imagined that they knew all things. Thus he had passed his life as a sort of missionary46 in detecting the pretended wisdom of mankind; and this occupation had quite absorbed him and taken him away both from public and private affairs. Young men of the richer sort had made a pastime of the same pursuit, 'which was not unamusing.' And hence bitter enmities had arisen; the professors of knowledge had revenged themselves by calling him a villainous corrupter of youth, and by repeating the commonplaces about atheism47 and materialism48 and sophistry49, which are the stock-accusations against all philosophers when there is nothing else to be said of them.
The second accusation he meets by interrogating50 Meletus, who is present and can be interrogated51. 'If he is the corrupter, who is the improver of the citizens?' (Compare Meno.) 'All men everywhere.' But how absurd, how contrary to analogy is this! How inconceivable too, that he should make the citizens worse when he has to live with them. This surely cannot be intentional52; and if unintentional, he ought to have been instructed by Meletus, and not accused in the court.
But there is another part of the indictment which says that he teaches men not to receive the gods whom the city receives, and has other new gods. 'Is that the way in which he is supposed to corrupt31 the youth?' 'Yes, it is.' 'Has he only new gods, or none at all?' 'None at all.' 'What, not even the sun and moon?' 'No; why, he says that the sun is a stone, and the moon earth.' That, replies Socrates, is the old confusion about Anaxagoras; the Athenian people are not so ignorant as to attribute to the influence of Socrates notions which have found their way into the drama, and may be learned at the theatre. Socrates undertakes to show that Meletus (rather unjustifiably) has been compounding a riddle53 in this part of the indictment: 'There are no gods, but Socrates believes in the existence of the sons of gods, which is absurd.'
Leaving Meletus, who has had enough words spent upon him, he returns to the original accusation. The question may be asked, Why will he persist in following a profession which leads him to death? Why?—because he must remain at his post where the god has placed him, as he remained at Potidaea, and Amphipolis, and Delium, where the generals placed him. Besides, he is not so overwise as to imagine that he knows whether death is a good or an evil; and he is certain that desertion of his duty is an evil. Anytus is quite right in saying that they should never have indicted54 him if they meant to let him go. For he will certainly obey God rather than man; and will continue to preach to all men of all ages the necessity of virtue and improvement; and if they refuse to listen to him he will still persevere55 and reprove them. This is his way of corrupting56 the youth, which he will not cease to follow in obedience57 to the god, even if a thousand deaths await him.
He is desirous that they should let him live—not for his own sake, but for theirs; because he is their heaven-sent friend (and they will never have such another), or, as he may be ludicrously described, he is the gadfly who stirs the generous steed into motion. Why then has he never taken part in public affairs? Because the familiar divine voice has hindered him; if he had been a public man, and had fought for the right, as he would certainly have fought against the many, he would not have lived, and could therefore have done no good. Twice in public matters he has risked his life for the sake of justice—once at the trial of the generals; and again in resistance to the tyrannical commands of the Thirty.
But, though not a public man, he has passed his days in instructing the citizens without fee or reward—this was his mission. Whether his disciples58 have turned out well or ill, he cannot justly be charged with the result, for he never promised to teach them anything. They might come if they liked, and they might stay away if they liked: and they did come, because they found an amusement in hearing the pretenders to wisdom detected. If they have been corrupted59, their elder relatives (if not themselves) might surely come into court and witness against him, and there is an opportunity still for them to appear. But their fathers and brothers all appear in court (including 'this' Plato), to witness on his behalf; and if their relatives are corrupted, at least they are uncorrupted; 'and they are my witnesses. For they know that I am speaking the truth, and that Meletus is lying.'
This is about all that he has to say. He will not entreat60 the judges to spare his life; neither will he present a spectacle of weeping children, although he, too, is not made of 'rock or oak.' Some of the judges themselves may have complied with this practice on similar occasions, and he trusts that they will not be angry with him for not following their example. But he feels that such conduct brings discredit61 on the name of Athens: he feels too, that the judge has sworn not to give away justice; and he cannot be guilty of the impiety62 of asking the judge to break his oath, when he is himself being tried for impiety.
As he expected, and probably intended, he is convicted. And now the tone of the speech, instead of being more conciliatory, becomes more lofty and commanding. Anytus proposes death as the penalty: and what counter-proposition shall he make? He, the benefactor63 of the Athenian people, whose whole life has been spent in doing them good, should at least have the Olympic victor's reward of maintenance in the Prytaneum. Or why should he propose any counter-penalty when he does not know whether death, which Anytus proposes, is a good or an evil? And he is certain that imprisonment64 is an evil, exile is an evil. Loss of money might be an evil, but then he has none to give; perhaps he can make up a mina. Let that be the penalty, or, if his friends wish, thirty minae; for which they will be excellent securities.
He is an old man already, and the Athenians will gain nothing but disgrace by depriving him of a few years of life. Perhaps he could have escaped, if he had chosen to throw down his arms and entreat for his life. But he does not at all repent66 of the manner of his defence; he would rather die in his own fashion than live in theirs. For the penalty of unrighteousness is swifter than death; that penalty has already overtaken his accusers as death will soon overtake him.
And now, as one who is about to die, he will prophesy67 to them. They have put him to death in order to escape the necessity of giving an account of their lives. But his death 'will be the seed' of many disciples who will convince them of their evil ways, and will come forth68 to reprove them in harsher terms, because they are younger and more inconsiderate.
He would like to say a few words, while there is time, to those who would have acquitted him. He wishes them to know that the divine sign never interrupted him in the course of his defence; the reason of which, as he conjectures69, is that the death to which he is going is a good and not an evil. For either death is a long sleep, the best of sleeps, or a journey to another world in which the souls of the dead are gathered together, and in which there may be a hope of seeing the heroes of old—in which, too, there are just judges; and as all are immortal70, there can be no fear of any one suffering death for his opinions.
Nothing evil can happen to the good man either in life or death, and his own death has been permitted by the gods, because it was better for him to depart; and therefore he forgives his judges because they have done him no harm, although they never meant to do him any good.
He has a last request to make to them—that they will trouble his sons as he has troubled them, if they appear to prefer riches to virtue, or to think themselves something when they are nothing.
'Few persons will be found to wish that Socrates should have defended himself otherwise,'—if, as we must add, his defence was that with which Plato has provided him. But leaving this question, which does not admit of a precise solution, we may go on to ask what was the impression which Plato in the Apology intended to give of the character and conduct of his master in the last great scene? Did he intend to represent him (1) as employing sophistries71; (2) as designedly irritating the judges? Or are these sophistries to be regarded as belonging to the age in which he lived and to his personal character, and this apparent haughtiness72 as flowing from the natural elevation73 of his position?
For example, when he says that it is absurd to suppose that one man is the corrupter and all the rest of the world the improvers of the youth; or, when he argues that he never could have corrupted the men with whom he had to live; or, when he proves his belief in the gods because he believes in the sons of gods, is he serious or jesting? It may be observed that these sophisms all occur in his cross-examination of Meletus, who is easily foiled and mastered in the hands of the great dialectician. Perhaps he regarded these answers as good enough for his accuser, of whom he makes very light. Also there is a touch of irony in them, which takes them out of the category of sophistry. (Compare Euthyph.)
That the manner in which he defends himself about the lives of his disciples is not satisfactory, can hardly be denied. Fresh in the memory of the Athenians, and detestable as they deserved to be to the newly restored democracy, were the names of Alcibiades, Critias, Charmides. It is obviously not a sufficient answer that Socrates had never professed to teach them anything, and is therefore not justly chargeable with their crimes. Yet the defence, when taken out of this ironical form, is doubtless sound: that his teaching had nothing to do with their evil lives. Here, then, the sophistry is rather in form than in substance, though we might desire that to such a serious charge Socrates had given a more serious answer.
Truly characteristic of Socrates is another point in his answer, which may also be regarded as sophistical. He says that 'if he has corrupted the youth, he must have corrupted them involuntarily.' But if, as Socrates argues, all evil is involuntary, then all criminals ought to be admonished74 and not punished. In these words the Socratic doctrine75 of the involuntariness of evil is clearly intended to be conveyed. Here again, as in the former instance, the defence of Socrates is untrue practically, but may be true in some ideal or transcendental sense. The commonplace reply, that if he had been guilty of corrupting the youth their relations would surely have witnessed against him, with which he concludes this part of his defence, is more satisfactory.
Again, when Socrates argues that he must believe in the gods because he believes in the sons of gods, we must remember that this is a refutation not of the original indictment, which is consistent enough—'Socrates does not receive the gods whom the city receives, and has other new divinities'—but of the interpretation76 put upon the words by Meletus, who has affirmed that he is a downright atheist77. To this Socrates fairly answers, in accordance with the ideas of the time, that a downright atheist cannot believe in the sons of gods or in divine things. The notion that demons78 or lesser79 divinities are the sons of gods is not to be regarded as ironical or sceptical. He is arguing 'ad hominem' according to the notions of mythology80 current in his age. Yet he abstains81 from saying that he believed in the gods whom the State approved. He does not defend himself, as Xenophon has defended him, by appealing to his practice of religion. Probably he neither wholly believed, nor disbelieved, in the existence of the popular gods; he had no means of knowing about them. According to Plato (compare Phaedo; Symp.), as well as Xenophon (Memor.), he was punctual in the performance of the least religious duties; and he must have believed in his own oracular sign, of which he seemed to have an internal witness. But the existence of Apollo or Zeus, or the other gods whom the State approves, would have appeared to him both uncertain and unimportant in comparison of the duty of self-examination, and of those principles of truth and right which he deemed to be the foundation of religion. (Compare Phaedr.; Euthyph.; Republic.)
The second question, whether Plato meant to represent Socrates as braving or irritating his judges, must also be answered in the negative. His irony, his superiority, his audacity82, 'regarding not the person of man,' necessarily flow out of the loftiness of his situation. He is not acting83 a part upon a great occasion, but he is what he has been all his life long, 'a king of men.' He would rather not appear insolent84, if he could avoid it (ouch os authadizomenos touto lego). Neither is he desirous of hastening his own end, for life and death are simply indifferent to him. But such a defence as would be acceptable to his judges and might procure85 an acquittal, it is not in his nature to make. He will not say or do anything that might pervert86 the course of justice; he cannot have his tongue bound even 'in the throat of death.' With his accusers he will only fence and play, as he had fenced with other 'improvers of youth,' answering the Sophist according to his sophistry all his life long. He is serious when he is speaking of his own mission, which seems to distinguish him from all other reformers of mankind, and originates in an accident. The dedication87 of himself to the improvement of his fellow-citizens is not so remarkable88 as the ironical spirit in which he goes about doing good only in vindication89 of the credit of the oracle, and in the vain hope of finding a wiser man than himself. Yet this singular and almost accidental character of his mission agrees with the divine sign which, according to our notions, is equally accidental and irrational90, and is nevertheless accepted by him as the guiding principle of his life. Socrates is nowhere represented to us as a freethinker or sceptic. There is no reason to doubt his sincerity91 when he speculates on the possibility of seeing and knowing the heroes of the Trojan war in another world. On the other hand, his hope of immortality92 is uncertain;—he also conceives of death as a long sleep (in this respect differing from the Phaedo), and at last falls back on resignation to the divine will, and the certainty that no evil can happen to the good man either in life or death. His absolute truthfulness93 seems to hinder him from asserting positively94 more than this; and he makes no attempt to veil his ignorance in mythology and figures of speech. The gentleness of the first part of the speech contrasts with the aggravated95, almost threatening, tone of the conclusion. He characteristically remarks that he will not speak as a rhetorician, that is to say, he will not make a regular defence such as Lysias or one of the orators96 might have composed for him, or, according to some accounts, did compose for him. But he first procures97 himself a hearing by conciliatory words. He does not attack the Sophists; for they were open to the same charges as himself; they were equally ridiculed98 by the Comic poets, and almost equally hateful to Anytus and Meletus. Yet incidentally the antagonism99 between Socrates and the Sophists is allowed to appear. He is poor and they are rich; his profession that he teaches nothing is opposed to their readiness to teach all things; his talking in the marketplace to their private instructions; his tarry-at-home life to their wandering from city to city. The tone which he assumes towards them is one of real friendliness100, but also of concealed101 irony. Towards Anaxagoras, who had disappointed him in his hopes of learning about mind and nature, he shows a less kindly102 feeling, which is also the feeling of Plato in other passages (Laws). But Anaxagoras had been dead thirty years, and was beyond the reach of persecution103.
It has been remarked that the prophecy of a new generation of teachers who would rebuke and exhort29 the Athenian people in harsher and more violent terms was, as far as we know, never fulfilled. No inference can be drawn104 from this circumstance as to the probability of the words attributed to him having been actually uttered. They express the aspiration105 of the first martyr106 of philosophy, that he would leave behind him many followers107, accompanied by the not unnatural108 feeling that they would be fiercer and more inconsiderate in their words when emancipated109 from his control.
The above remarks must be understood as applying with any degree of certainty to the Platonic Socrates only. For, although these or similar words may have been spoken by Socrates himself, we cannot exclude the possibility, that like so much else, e.g. the wisdom of Critias, the poem of Solon, the virtues110 of Charmides, they may have been due only to the imagination of Plato. The arguments of those who maintain that the Apology was composed during the process, resting on no evidence, do not require a serious refutation. Nor are the reasonings of Schleiermacher, who argues that the Platonic defence is an exact or nearly exact reproduction of the words of Socrates, partly because Plato would not have been guilty of the impiety of altering them, and also because many points of the defence might have been improved and strengthened, at all more conclusive111. (See English Translation.) What effect the death of Socrates produced on the mind of Plato, we cannot certainly determine; nor can we say how he would or must have written under the circumstances. We observe that the enmity of Aristophanes to Socrates does not prevent Plato from introducing them together in the Symposium engaged in friendly intercourse112. Nor is there any trace in the Dialogues of an attempt to make Anytus or Meletus personally odious113 in the eyes of the Athenian public.
点击收听单词发音
1 acquitted | |
宣判…无罪( acquit的过去式和过去分词 ); 使(自己)作出某种表现 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 testimony | |
n.证词;见证,证明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 defiance | |
n.挑战,挑衅,蔑视,违抗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 desultory | |
adj.散漫的,无方法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 spoke | |
n.(车轮的)辐条;轮辐;破坏某人的计划;阻挠某人的行动 v.讲,谈(speak的过去式);说;演说;从某种观点来说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 allusion | |
n.暗示,间接提示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 habitual | |
adj.习惯性的;通常的,惯常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 irony | |
n.反语,冷嘲;具有讽刺意味的事,嘲弄 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 tragic | |
adj.悲剧的,悲剧性的,悲惨的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 pathos | |
n.哀婉,悲怆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 conversational | |
adj.对话的,会话的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 ironical | |
adj.讽刺的,冷嘲的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 simplicity | |
n.简单,简易;朴素;直率,单纯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 disciple | |
n.信徒,门徒,追随者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 embodied | |
v.表现( embody的过去式和过去分词 );象征;包括;包含 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 symposium | |
n.讨论会,专题报告会;专题论文集 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 platonic | |
adj.精神的;柏拉图(哲学)的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 authenticity | |
n.真实性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 oracle | |
n.神谕,神谕处,预言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 depicting | |
描绘,描画( depict的现在分词 ); 描述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 appendage | |
n.附加物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 scrupulously | |
adv.一丝不苟地;小心翼翼地,多顾虑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 rhetoric | |
n.修辞学,浮夸之言语 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 accusation | |
n.控告,指责,谴责 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 narrative | |
n.叙述,故事;adj.叙事的,故事体的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 rebuke | |
v.指责,非难,斥责 [反]praise | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 exhortation | |
n.劝告,规劝 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 exhort | |
v.规劝,告诫 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 colloquial | |
adj.口语的,会话的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 corrupt | |
v.贿赂,收买;adj.腐败的,贪污的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 corrupter | |
堕落的,道德败坏的; 贪污的,腐败的; 腐烂的; (文献等)错误百出的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 secondly | |
adv.第二,其次 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 professed | |
公开声称的,伪称的,已立誓信教的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 accusations | |
n.指责( accusation的名词复数 );指控;控告;(被告发、控告的)罪名 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 indictment | |
n.起诉;诉状 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 professes | |
声称( profess的第三人称单数 ); 宣称; 公开表明; 信奉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 lurking | |
潜在 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 anticipation | |
n.预期,预料,期望 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 craftsmen | |
n. 技工 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 conceit | |
n.自负,自高自大 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 missionary | |
adj.教会的,传教(士)的;n.传教士 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 atheism | |
n.无神论,不信神 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 materialism | |
n.[哲]唯物主义,唯物论;物质至上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 sophistry | |
n.诡辩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 interrogating | |
n.询问技术v.询问( interrogate的现在分词 );审问;(在计算机或其他机器上)查询 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 interrogated | |
v.询问( interrogate的过去式和过去分词 );审问;(在计算机或其他机器上)查询 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 intentional | |
adj.故意的,有意(识)的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 riddle | |
n.谜,谜语,粗筛;vt.解谜,给…出谜,筛,检查,鉴定,非难,充满于;vi.出谜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 indicted | |
控告,起诉( indict的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 persevere | |
v.坚持,坚忍,不屈不挠 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 corrupting | |
(使)败坏( corrupt的现在分词 ); (使)腐化; 引起(计算机文件等的)错误; 破坏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 obedience | |
n.服从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 disciples | |
n.信徒( disciple的名词复数 );门徒;耶稣的信徒;(尤指)耶稣十二门徒之一 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 corrupted | |
(使)败坏( corrupt的过去式和过去分词 ); (使)腐化; 引起(计算机文件等的)错误; 破坏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 entreat | |
v.恳求,恳请 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 discredit | |
vt.使不可置信;n.丧失信义;不信,怀疑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 impiety | |
n.不敬;不孝 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 benefactor | |
n. 恩人,行善的人,捐助人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 imprisonment | |
n.关押,监禁,坐牢 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 condemned | |
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 repent | |
v.悔悟,悔改,忏悔,后悔 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 prophesy | |
v.预言;预示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 conjectures | |
推测,猜想( conjecture的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 immortal | |
adj.不朽的;永生的,不死的;神的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 sophistries | |
n.诡辩术( sophistry的名词复数 );(一次)诡辩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 haughtiness | |
n.傲慢;傲气 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 elevation | |
n.高度;海拔;高地;上升;提高 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 admonished | |
v.劝告( admonish的过去式和过去分词 );训诫;(温和地)责备;轻责 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 interpretation | |
n.解释,说明,描述;艺术处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 atheist | |
n.无神论者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 demons | |
n.恶人( demon的名词复数 );恶魔;精力过人的人;邪念 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 lesser | |
adj.次要的,较小的;adv.较小地,较少地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 mythology | |
n.神话,神话学,神话集 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 abstains | |
戒(尤指酒),戒除( abstain的第三人称单数 ); 弃权(不投票) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 audacity | |
n.大胆,卤莽,无礼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 acting | |
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 insolent | |
adj.傲慢的,无理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 procure | |
vt.获得,取得,促成;vi.拉皮条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 pervert | |
n.堕落者,反常者;vt.误用,滥用;使人堕落,使入邪路 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 dedication | |
n.奉献,献身,致力,题献,献辞 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 remarkable | |
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 vindication | |
n.洗冤,证实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 irrational | |
adj.无理性的,失去理性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 sincerity | |
n.真诚,诚意;真实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 immortality | |
n.不死,不朽 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 truthfulness | |
n. 符合实际 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 positively | |
adv.明确地,断然,坚决地;实在,确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 aggravated | |
使恶化( aggravate的过去式和过去分词 ); 使更严重; 激怒; 使恼火 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 orators | |
n.演说者,演讲家( orator的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 procures | |
v.(努力)取得, (设法)获得( procure的第三人称单数 );拉皮条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 ridiculed | |
v.嘲笑,嘲弄,奚落( ridicule的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 antagonism | |
n.对抗,敌对,对立 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 friendliness | |
n.友谊,亲切,亲密 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 concealed | |
a.隐藏的,隐蔽的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 kindly | |
adj.和蔼的,温和的,爽快的;adv.温和地,亲切地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 persecution | |
n. 迫害,烦扰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 aspiration | |
n.志向,志趣抱负;渴望;(语)送气音;吸出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 martyr | |
n.烈士,殉难者;vt.杀害,折磨,牺牲 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 followers | |
追随者( follower的名词复数 ); 用户; 契据的附面; 从动件 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 unnatural | |
adj.不自然的;反常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 emancipated | |
adj.被解放的,不受约束的v.解放某人(尤指摆脱政治、法律或社会的束缚)( emancipate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 virtues | |
美德( virtue的名词复数 ); 德行; 优点; 长处 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 conclusive | |
adj.最后的,结论的;确凿的,消除怀疑的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 intercourse | |
n.性交;交流,交往,交际 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 odious | |
adj.可憎的,讨厌的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |