And first, as regards the current theories of the primitive11 condition of society, there was a wide divergence12 of opinion in Hellenic society, just as there is now. For while the majority of the orthodox public, of whom Hesiod may be taken as the representative, looked back, as a great many of our own day still do, to a fabulous13 age of innocent happiness, a bell’ età dell’ auro, where sin and death were unknown and men and women were like Gods, the foremost men of intellect such as Aristotle and Plato, ?schylus and many of the other poets [29] saw in primitive man ‘a few small sparks of humanity preserved on the tops of mountains after some deluge,’ ‘without an idea of cities, governments or legislation,’ ‘living the lives of wild beasts in sunless caves,’ ‘their only law being the survival of the fittest.’
And this, too, was the opinion of Thucydides, whose Arch?ologia as it is contains a most valuable disquisition on the early condition of Hellas, which it will be necessary to examine at some length.
Now, as regards the means employed generally by Thucydides for the elucidation14 of ancient history, I have already pointed15 out how that, while acknowledging that ‘it is the tendency of every poet to exaggerate, as it is of every chronicler to seek to be attractive at the expense of truth,’ he yet assumes in the thoroughly16 euhemeristic way, that under the veil of myth and legend there does yet exist a rational basis of fact discoverable by the method of rejecting all supernatural interference as well as any extraordinary motives18 influencing the actors. It is in complete accordance with this spirit that he appeals, for instance, to the Homeric epithet19 of ?φνει??, as applied20 to Corinth, as a proof of the early commercial prosperity of that city; to the fact of the generic21 name Hellenes not occurring in the Iliad as a corroboration22 of his theory of the essentially23 disunited character of the primitive Greek tribes; and he argues from the line ‘O’er many islands and all Argos ruled,’ as applied to Agamemnon, that his forces must have been partially24 naval25, ‘for Agamemnon’s was a continental26 power, and he could not have been master of any but the adjacent islands, and these would not be many but through the possession of a fleet.’
Anticipating in some measure the comparative method of research, he argues from the fact of the more barbarous Greek tribes, such as the ?tolians and Acarnanians, still carrying arms in his own day, that this custom was the case originally over the whole country. ‘The fact,’ he says, ‘that the people in these parts of Hellas are still living in the old way points to a time when the same mode of life was equally common to all.’ Similarly, in another passage, he shows how a corroboration of his theory of the respectable character of piracy27 in ancient days is afforded by ‘the honour with which some of the inhabitants of the continent still regard a successful marauder,’ as well as by the fact that the question, ‘Are you a pirate?’ is a common feature of primitive society as shown in the poets; and finally, after observing how the old Greek custom of wearing belts in gymnastic contests still survived among the more uncivilised Asiatic tribes, he observes that there are many other points in which a likeness28 may be shown between the life of the primitive Hellenes and that of the barbarians29 to-day.’
As regards the evidence afforded by ancient remains30, while adducing as a proof of the insecure character of early Greek society the fact of their cities [31] being always built at some distance from the sea, yet he is careful to warn us, and the caution ought to be borne in mind by all arch?ologists, that we have no right to conclude from the scanty31 remains of any city that its legendary32 greatness in primitive times was a mere2 exaggeration. ‘We are not justified33,’ he says, ‘in rejecting the tradition of the magnitude of the Trojan armament, because Mycen? and the other towns of that age seem to us small and insignificant34. For, if Laced?mon was to become desolate35, any antiquarian judging merely from its ruins would be inclined to regard the tale of the Spartan36 hegemony as an idle myth; for the city is a mere collection of villages after the old fashion of Hellas, and has none of those splendid public buildings and temples which characterise Athens, and whose remains, in the case of the latter city, would be so marvellous as to lead the superficial observer into an exaggerated estimate of the Athenian power.’ Nothing can be more scientific than the arch?ological canons laid down, whose truth is strikingly illustrated37 to any one who has compared the waste fields of the Eurotas plain with the lordly monuments of the Athenian acropolis. [32]
On the other hand, Thucydides is quite conscious of the value of the positive evidence afforded by arch?ological remains. He appeals, for instance, to the character of the armour39 found in the Delian tombs and the peculiar40 mode of sepulture, as corroboration of his theory of the predominance of the Carian element among the primitive islanders, and to the concentration of all the temples either in the Acropolis, or in its immediate41 vicinity, to the name of ?στυ by which it was still known, and to the extraordinary sanctity of the spring of water there, as proof that the primitive city was originally confined to the citadel42, and the district immediately beneath it (ii. 16). And lastly, in the very opening of his history, anticipating one of the most scientific of modern methods, he points out how in early states of civilisation43 immense fertility of the soil tends to favour the personal aggrandisement of individuals, and so to stop the normal progress of the country through ‘the rise of factions44, that endless source of ruin’; and also by the allurements45 it offers to a foreign invader46, to necessitate47 a continual change of population, one immigration following on another. He exemplifies his theory by pointing to the endless political revolutions that characterised Arcadia, Thessaly and Boeotia, the three richest spots in Greece, as well as by the negative instance of the undisturbed state in primitive time of Attica, which was always remarkable48 for the dryness and poverty of its soil.
Now, while undoubtedly49 in these passages we may recognise the first anticipation50 of many of the most modern principles of research, we must remember how essentially limited is the range of the arch?ologia, and how no theory at all is offered on the wider questions of the general conditions of the rise and progress of humanity, a problem which is first scientifically discussed in the Republic of Plato.
And at the outset it must be premised that, while the study of primitive man is an essentially inductive science, resting rather on the accumulation of evidence than on speculation51, among the Greeks it was prosecuted52 rather on deductive principles. Thucydides did, indeed, avail himself of the opportunities afforded by the unequal development of civilisation in his own day in Greece, and in the places I have pointed out seems to have anticipated the comparative method. But we do not find later writers availing themselves of the wonderfully accurate and picturesque54 accounts given by Herodotus of the customs of savage55 tribes. To take one instance, which bears a good deal on modern questions, we find in the works of this great traveller the gradual and progressive steps in the development of the family life clearly manifested in the mere gregarious56 herding57 together of the Agathyrsi, their primitive kinsmanship through women in common, and the rise of a feeling of paternity from a state of polyandry. This tribe stood at that time on that borderland between umbilical relationship and the family which has been such a difficult point for modern anthropologists to find.
The ancient authors, however, are unanimous in insisting that the family is the ultimate unit of society, though, as I have said, an inductive study of primitive races, or even the accounts given of them by Herodotus, would have shown them that the νεοττι? ?δια of a personal household, to use Plato’s expression, is really a most complex notion appearing always in a late stage of civilisation, along with recognition of private property and the rights of individualism.
Philology59 also, which in the hands of modern investigators60 has proved such a splendid instrument of research, was in ancient days studied on principles too unscientific to be of much use. Herodotus points out that the word Eridanos is essentially Greek in character, that consequently the river supposed to run round the world is probably a mere Greek invention. His remarks, however, on language generally, as in the case of Piromis and the ending of the Persian names, show on what unsound basis his knowledge of language rested.
In the Bacch? of Euripides there is an extremely interesting passage in which the immoral8 stories of the Greek mythology61 are accounted for on the principle of that misunderstanding of words and metaphors62 to which modern science has given the name of a disease of language. In answer to the impious rationalism of Pentheus—a sort of modern Philistine—Teiresias, who may be termed the Max Müller of the Theban cycle, points out that the story of Dionysus being inclosed in Zeus’ thigh63 really arose from the linguistic64 confusion between μηρ?? and ?μηρο?.
On the whole, however—for I have quoted these two instances only to show the unscientific character of early philology—we may say that this important instrument in recreating the history of the past was not really used by the ancients as a means of historical criticism. Nor did the ancients employ that other method, used to such advantage in our own day, by which in the symbolism and formulas of an advanced civilisation we can detect the unconscious survival of ancient customs: for, whereas in the sham65 capture of the bride at a marriage feast, which was common in Wales till a recent time, we can discern the lingering reminiscence of the barbarous habit of exogamy, the ancient writers saw only the deliberate commemoration of an historical event.
Aristotle does not tell us by what method he discovered that the Greeks used to buy their wives in primitive times, but, judging by his general principles, it was probably through some legend or myth on the subject which lasted to his own day, and not, as we would do, by arguing back from the marriage presents given to the bride and her relatives. [37]
The origin of the common proverb ‘worth so many beeves,’ in which we discern the unconscious survival of a purely66 pastoral state of society before the use of metals was known, is ascribed by Plutarch to the fact of Theseus having coined money bearing a bull’s head. Similarly, the Amathusian festival, in which a young man imitated the labours of a woman in travail67, is regarded by him as a rite53 instituted in Ariadne’s honour, and the Carian adoration68 of asparagus as a simple commemoration of the adventure of the nymph Perigune. In the first of these we discern the beginning of agnation and kinsmanship through the father, which still lingers in the ‘couvee’ of New Zealand tribes: while the second is a relic69 of the totem and fetish worship of plants.
Now, in entire opposition70 to this modern inductive principle of research stands the philosophic3 Plato, whose account of primitive man is entirely71 speculative72 and deductive.
The origin of society he ascribes to necessity, the mother of all inventions, and imagines that individual man began deliberately73 to herd58 together on account of the advantages of the principle of division of labour and the rendering74 of mutual75 need.
It must, however, be borne in mind that Plato’s object in this whole passage in the Republic was, perhaps, not so much to analyse the conditions of early society as to illustrate38 the importance of the division of labour, the shibboleth76 of his political economy, by showing what a powerful factor it must have been in the most primitive as well as in the most complex states of society; just as in the Laws he almost rewrites entirely the history of the Peloponnesus in order to prove the necessity of a balance of power. He surely, I mean, must have recognised himself how essentially incomplete his theory was in taking no account of the origin of family life, the position and influence of women, and other social questions, as well as in disregarding those deeper motives of religion, which are such important factors in early civilisation, and whose influence Aristotle seems to have clearly apprehended77, when he says that the aim of primitive society was not merely life but the higher life, and that in the origin of society utility is not the sole motive17, but that there is something spiritual in it if, at least, ‘spiritual’ will bring out the meaning of that complex expression τ? καλ?ν. Otherwise, the whole account in the Republic of primitive man will always remain as a warning against the intrusion of a priori speculations78 in the domain79 appropriate to induction80.
Now, Aristotle’s theory of the origin of society, like his philosophy of ethics81, rests ultimately on the principle of final causes, not in the theological meaning of an aim or tendency imposed from without, but in the scientific sense of function corresponding to organ. ‘Nature maketh no thing in vain’ is the text of Aristotle in this as in other inquiries82. Man being the only animal possessed83 of the power of rational speech is, he asserts, by nature intended to be social, more so than the bee or any other gregarious animal.
He is φ?σει πολιτικ??, and the national tendency towards higher forms of perfection brings the ‘armed savage who used to sell his wife’ to the free independence of a free state, and to the ?σ?τη? το? ?ρχειν κα? το? ?ρχεσθαι, which was the test of true citizenship84. The stages passed through by humanity start with the family first as the ultimate unit.
The conglomeration85 of families forms a village ruled by that patriarchal sway which is the oldest form of government in the world, as is shown by the fact that all men count it to be the constitution of heaven, and the villages are merged86 into the state, and here the progression stops.
For Aristotle, like all Greek thinkers, found his ideal within the walls of the π?λι?, yet perhaps in his remark that a united Greece would rule the world we may discern some anticipation of that ‘federal union of free states into one consolidated87 empire’ which, more than the π?λι?, is to our eyes the ultimately perfect polity.
How far Aristotle was justified in regarding the family as the ultimate unit, with the materials afforded to him by Greek literature, I have already noticed. Besides, Aristotle, I may remark, had he reflected on the meaning of that Athenian law which, while prohibiting marriage with a uterine sister, permitted it with a sister-german, or on the common tradition in Athens that before the time of Cecrops children bore their mothers’ names, or on some of the Spartan regulations, could hardly have failed to see the universality of kinsmanship through women in early days, and the late appearance of monandry. Yet, while he missed this point, in common, it must be acknowledged, with many modern writers, such as Sir Henry Maine, it is essentially as an explorer of inductive instances that we recognise his improvement on Plato. The treatise6 περ? πολιτε?ων, did it remain to us in its entirety, would have been one of the most valuable landmarks88 in the progress of historical criticism, and the first scientific treatise on the science of comparative politics.
A few fragments still remain to us, in one of which we find Aristotle appealing to the authority of an ancient inscription89 on the ‘Disk of Iphitus,’ one of the most celebrated90 Greek antiquities91, to corroborate92 his theory of the Lycurgean revival93 of the Olympian festival; while his enormous research is evinced in the elaborate explanation he gives of the historical origin of proverbs such as ο?δε?? μ?γα? κακ?? ?χθ??, of religious songs like the ??μεν ?? ?θ?να? of the Botticean virgins94, or the praises of love and war.
And, finally, it is to be observed how much wider than Plato’s his theory of the origin of society is. They both rest on a psychological basis, but Aristotle’s recognition of the capacity for progress and the tendency towards a higher life shows how much deeper his knowledge of human nature was.
In imitation of these two philosophers, Polybius gives an account of the origin of society in the opening to his philosophy of history. Somewhat in the spirit of Plato, he imagines that after one of the cyclic deluges95 which sweep off mankind at stated periods and annihilate96 all pre-existing civilisation, the few surviving members of humanity coalesce97 for mutual protection, and, as in the case with ordinary animals, the one most remarkable for physical strength is elected king. In a short time, owing to the workings of sympathy and the desire of approbation98, the moral qualities begin to make their appearance, and intellectual instead of bodily excellence99 becomes the qualification for sovereignty.
Other points, as the rise of law and the like, are dwelt on in a somewhat modern spirit, and although Polybius seems not to have employed the inductive method of research in this question, or rather, I should say, of the hierarchical order of the rational progress of ideas in life, he is not far removed from what the laborious100 investigations101 of modern travellers have given us.
And, indeed, as regards the working of the speculative faculty102 in the creation of history, it is in all respects marvellous how that the most truthful103 accounts of the passage from barbarism to civilisation in ancient literature come from the works of poets. The elaborate researches of Mr. Tylor and Sir John Lubbock have done little more than verify the theories put forward in the Prometheus Bound and the De Natura Rerum; yet neither ?schylus nor Lucretias followed in the modern path, but rather attained104 to truth by a certain almost mystic power of creative imagination, such as we now seek to banish105 from science as a dangerous power, though to it science seems to owe many of its most splendid generalities. [43]
Leaving then the question of the origin of society as treated by the ancients, I shall now turn to the other and the more important question of how far they may he said to have attained to what we call the philosophy of history.
Now at the outset we must note that, while the conceptions of law and order have been universally received as the governing principles of the phenomena106 of nature in the sphere of physical science, yet their intrusion into the domain of history and the life of man has always been met with a strong opposition, on the ground of the incalculable nature of two great forces acting107 on human action, a certain causeless spontaneity which men call free will, and the extra-natural interference which they attribute as a constant attribute to God.
Now, that there is a science of the apparently108 variable phenomena of history is a conception which we have perhaps only recently begun to appreciate; yet, like all other great thoughts, it seems to have come to the Greek mind spontaneously, through a certain splendour of imagination, in the morning tide of their civilisation, before inductive research had armed them with the instruments of verification. For I think it is possible to discern in some of the mystic speculations of the early Greek thinkers that desire to discover what is that ‘invariable existence of which there are variable states,’ and to incorporate it in some one formula of law which may serve to explain the different manifestations109 of all organic bodies, man included, which is the germ of the philosophy of history; the germ indeed of an idea of which it is not too much to say that on it any kind of historical criticism, worthy110 of the name, must ultimately rest.
For the very first requisite111 for any scientific conception of history is the doctrine112 of uniform sequence: in other words, that certain events having happened, certain other events corresponding to them will happen also; that the past is the key of the future.
Now at the birth of this great conception science, it is true, presided, yet religion it was which at the outset clothed it in its own garb113, and familiarised men with it by appealing to their hearts first and then to their intellects; knowing that at the beginning of things it is through the moral nature, and not through the intellectual, that great truths are spread.
So in Herodotus, who may be taken as a representative of the orthodox tone of thought, the idea of the uniform sequence of cause and effect appears under the theological aspect of Nemesis114 and Providence115, which is really the scientific conception of law, only it is viewed from an ethical standpoint.
Now in Thucydides the philosophy of history rests on the probability, which the uniformity of human nature affords us, that the future will in the course of human things resemble the past, if not reproduce it. He appears to contemplate116 a recurrence117 of the phenomena of history as equally certain with a return of the epidemic118 of the Great Plague.
Notwithstanding what German critics have written on the subject, we must beware of regarding this conception as a mere reproduction of that cyclic theory of events which sees in the world nothing but the regular rotation119 of Strophe and Antistrophe, in the eternal choir120 of life and death.
For, in his remarks on the excesses of the Corcyrean Revolution, Thucydides distinctly rests his idea of the recurrence of history on the psychological grounds of the general sameness of mankind.
‘The sufferings,’ he says, ‘which revolution entailed121 upon the cities were many and terrible, such as have occurred and always will occurs as long as human nature remains the same, though in a severer or milder form, and varying in their symptoms according to the variety of the particular cases.
‘In peace and prosperity states and individuals have better sentiments, because they are not confronted with imperious necessities; but war takes away the easy supply of men’s wants, and so proves a hard taskmaster, which brings most men’s characters to a level with their fortunes.’
点击收听单词发音
1 investigation | |
n.调查,调查研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 philosophic | |
adj.哲学的,贤明的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 treatises | |
n.专题著作,专题论文,专著( treatise的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 treatise | |
n.专著;(专题)论文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 purge | |
n.整肃,清除,泻药,净化;vt.净化,清除,摆脱;vi.清除,通便,腹泻,变得清洁 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 immoral | |
adj.不道德的,淫荡的,荒淫的,有伤风化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 immorality | |
n. 不道德, 无道义 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 ethical | |
adj.伦理的,道德的,合乎道德的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 divergence | |
n.分歧,岔开 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 fabulous | |
adj.极好的;极为巨大的;寓言中的,传说中的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 elucidation | |
n.说明,阐明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 pointed | |
adj.尖的,直截了当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 thoroughly | |
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 epithet | |
n.(用于褒贬人物等的)表述形容词,修饰语 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 generic | |
adj.一般的,普通的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 corroboration | |
n.进一步的证实,进一步的证据 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 partially | |
adv.部分地,从某些方面讲 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 naval | |
adj.海军的,军舰的,船的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 continental | |
adj.大陆的,大陆性的,欧洲大陆的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 piracy | |
n.海盗行为,剽窃,著作权侵害 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 likeness | |
n.相像,相似(之处) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 barbarians | |
n.野蛮人( barbarian的名词复数 );外国人;粗野的人;无教养的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 scanty | |
adj.缺乏的,仅有的,节省的,狭小的,不够的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 legendary | |
adj.传奇(中)的,闻名遐迩的;n.传奇(文学) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 justified | |
a.正当的,有理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 insignificant | |
adj.无关紧要的,可忽略的,无意义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 desolate | |
adj.荒凉的,荒芜的;孤独的,凄凉的;v.使荒芜,使孤寂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 spartan | |
adj.简朴的,刻苦的;n.斯巴达;斯巴达式的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 illustrated | |
adj. 有插图的,列举的 动词illustrate的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 illustrate | |
v.举例说明,阐明;图解,加插图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 armour | |
(=armor)n.盔甲;装甲部队 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 citadel | |
n.城堡;堡垒;避难所 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 civilisation | |
n.文明,文化,开化,教化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 factions | |
组织中的小派别,派系( faction的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 allurements | |
n.诱惑( allurement的名词复数 );吸引;诱惑物;有诱惑力的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 invader | |
n.侵略者,侵犯者,入侵者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 necessitate | |
v.使成为必要,需要 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 remarkable | |
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 undoubtedly | |
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 anticipation | |
n.预期,预料,期望 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 speculation | |
n.思索,沉思;猜测;投机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 prosecuted | |
a.被起诉的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 rite | |
n.典礼,惯例,习俗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 picturesque | |
adj.美丽如画的,(语言)生动的,绘声绘色的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 savage | |
adj.野蛮的;凶恶的,残暴的;n.未开化的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 gregarious | |
adj.群居的,喜好群居的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 herding | |
中畜群 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 herd | |
n.兽群,牧群;vt.使集中,把…赶在一起 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 philology | |
n.语言学;语文学 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 investigators | |
n.调查者,审查者( investigator的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 mythology | |
n.神话,神话学,神话集 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 metaphors | |
隐喻( metaphor的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 thigh | |
n.大腿;股骨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 linguistic | |
adj.语言的,语言学的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 sham | |
n./adj.假冒(的),虚伪(的) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 purely | |
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 travail | |
n.阵痛;努力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 adoration | |
n.爱慕,崇拜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 relic | |
n.神圣的遗物,遗迹,纪念物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 speculative | |
adj.思索性的,暝想性的,推理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 deliberately | |
adv.审慎地;蓄意地;故意地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 rendering | |
n.表现,描写 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 mutual | |
adj.相互的,彼此的;共同的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 shibboleth | |
n.陈规陋习;口令;暗语 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 apprehended | |
逮捕,拘押( apprehend的过去式和过去分词 ); 理解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 speculations | |
n.投机买卖( speculation的名词复数 );思考;投机活动;推断 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 domain | |
n.(活动等)领域,范围;领地,势力范围 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 induction | |
n.感应,感应现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 ethics | |
n.伦理学;伦理观,道德标准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 inquiries | |
n.调查( inquiry的名词复数 );疑问;探究;打听 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 citizenship | |
n.市民权,公民权,国民的义务(身份) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 conglomeration | |
n.团块,聚集,混合物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 merged | |
(使)混合( merge的过去式和过去分词 ); 相融; 融入; 渐渐消失在某物中 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 consolidated | |
a.联合的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 landmarks | |
n.陆标( landmark的名词复数 );目标;(标志重要阶段的)里程碑 ~ (in sth);有历史意义的建筑物(或遗址) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 inscription | |
n.(尤指石块上的)刻印文字,铭文,碑文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 celebrated | |
adj.有名的,声誉卓著的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 antiquities | |
n.古老( antiquity的名词复数 );古迹;古人们;古代的风俗习惯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 corroborate | |
v.支持,证实,确定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 revival | |
n.复兴,复苏,(精力、活力等的)重振 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 virgins | |
处女,童男( virgin的名词复数 ); 童贞玛利亚(耶稣之母) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 deluges | |
v.使淹没( deluge的第三人称单数 );淹没;被洪水般涌来的事物所淹没;穷于应付 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 annihilate | |
v.使无效;毁灭;取消 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 coalesce | |
v.联合,结合,合并 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 approbation | |
n.称赞;认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 excellence | |
n.优秀,杰出,(pl.)优点,美德 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 laborious | |
adj.吃力的,努力的,不流畅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 investigations | |
(正式的)调查( investigation的名词复数 ); 侦查; 科学研究; 学术研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 faculty | |
n.才能;学院,系;(学院或系的)全体教学人员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 truthful | |
adj.真实的,说实话的,诚实的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 banish | |
vt.放逐,驱逐;消除,排除 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 acting | |
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 apparently | |
adv.显然地;表面上,似乎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 manifestations | |
n.表示,显示(manifestation的复数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 worthy | |
adj.(of)值得的,配得上的;有价值的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 requisite | |
adj.需要的,必不可少的;n.必需品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 garb | |
n.服装,装束 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 nemesis | |
n.给以报应者,复仇者,难以对付的敌手 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 providence | |
n.深谋远虑,天道,天意;远见;节约;上帝 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 contemplate | |
vt.盘算,计议;周密考虑;注视,凝视 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 recurrence | |
n.复发,反复,重现 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 epidemic | |
n.流行病;盛行;adj.流行性的,流传极广的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 rotation | |
n.旋转;循环,轮流 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 choir | |
n.唱诗班,唱诗班的席位,合唱团,舞蹈团;v.合唱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 entailed | |
使…成为必要( entail的过去式和过去分词 ); 需要; 限定继承; 使必需 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |