To return:— You remember what was said of the democrat9; that he was the son of a miserly father, who encouraged the saving desires and repressed the ornamental10 and expensive ones; presently the youth got into fine company, and began to entertain a dislike to his father’s narrow ways; and being a better man than the corrupters of his youth, he came to a mean, and led a life, not of lawless or slavish passion, but of regular and successive indulgence. Now imagine that the youth has become a father, and has a son who is exposed to the same temptations, and has companions who lead him into every sort of iniquity11, and parents and friends who try to keep him right. The counsellors of evil find that their only chance of retaining him is to implant12 in his soul a monster drone, or love; while other desires buzz around him and mystify him with sweet sounds and scents13, this monster love takes possession of him, and puts an end to every true or modest thought or wish. Love, like drunkenness and madness, is a tyranny; and the tyrannical man, whether made by nature or habit, is just a drinking, lusting15, furious sort of animal.
And how does such an one live? ‘Nay, that you must tell me.’ Well then, I fancy that he will live amid revelries and harlotries, and love will be the lord and master of the house. Many desires require much money, and so he spends all that he has and borrows more; and when he has nothing the young ravens16 are still in the nest in which they were hatched, crying for food. Love urges them on; and they must be gratified by force or fraud, or if not, they become painful and troublesome; and as the new pleasures succeed the old ones, so will the son take possession of the goods of his parents; if they show signs of refusing, he will defraud17 and deceive them; and if they openly resist, what then? ‘I can only say, that I should not much like to be in their place.’ But, O heavens, Adeimantus, to think that for some new-fangled and unnecessary love he will give up his old father and mother, best and dearest of friends, or enslave them to the fancies of the hour! Truly a tyrannical son is a blessing18 to his father and mother! When there is no more to be got out of them, he turns burglar or pickpocket19, or robs a temple. Love overmasters the thoughts of his youth, and he becomes in sober reality the monster that he was sometimes in sleep. He waxes strong in all violence and lawlessness; and is ready for any deed of daring that will supply the wants of his rabble-rout. In a well-ordered State there are only a few such, and these in time of war go out and become the mercenaries of a tyrant20. But in time of peace they stay at home and do mischief21; they are the thieves, footpads, cut-purses, man-stealers of the community; or if they are able to speak, they turn false-witnesses and informers. ‘No small catalogue of crimes truly, even if the perpetrators are few.’ Yes, I said; but small and great are relative terms, and no crimes which are committed by them approach those of the tyrant, whom this class, growing strong and numerous, create out of themselves. If the people yield, well and good, but, if they resist, then, as before he beat his father and mother, so now he beats his fatherland and motherland, and places his mercenaries over them. Such men in their early days live with flatterers, and they themselves flatter others, in order to gain their ends; but they soon discard their followers23 when they have no longer any need of them; they are always either masters or servants — the joys of friendship are unknown to them. And they are utterly24 treacherous25 and unjust, if the nature of justice be at all understood by us. They realize our dream; and he who is the most of a tyrant by nature, and leads the life of a tyrant for the longest time, will be the worst of them, and being the worst of them, will also be the most miserable26.
Like man, like State — the tyrannical man will answer to tyranny, which is the extreme opposite of the royal State; for one is the best and the other the worst. But which is the happier? Great and terrible as the tyrant may appear enthroned amid his satellites, let us not be afraid to go in and ask; and the answer is, that the monarchical27 is the happiest, and the tyrannical the most miserable of States. And may we not ask the same question about the men themselves, requesting some one to look into them who is able to penetrate28 the inner nature of man, and will not be panic-struck by the vain pomp of tyranny? I will suppose that he is one who has lived with him, and has seen him in family life, or perhaps in the hour of trouble and danger.
Assuming that we ourselves are the impartial29 judge for whom we seek, let us begin by comparing the individual and State, and ask first of all, whether the State is likely to be free or enslaved — Will there not be a little freedom and a great deal of slavery? And the freedom is of the bad, and the slavery of the good; and this applies to the man as well as to the State; for his soul is full of meanness and slavery, and the better part is enslaved to the worse. He cannot do what he would, and his mind is full of confusion; he is the very reverse of a freeman. The State will be poor and full of misery and sorrow; and the man’s soul will also be poor and full of sorrows, and he will be the most miserable of men. No, not the most miserable, for there is yet a more miserable. ‘Who is that?’ The tyrannical man who has the misfortune also to become a public tyrant. ‘There I suspect that you are right.’ Say rather, ‘I am sure;’ conjecture30 is out of place in an enquiry of this nature. He is like a wealthy owner of slaves, only he has more of them than any private individual. You will say, ‘The owners of slaves are not generally in any fear of them.’ But why? Because the whole city is in a league which protects the individual. Suppose however that one of these owners and his household is carried off by a god into a wilderness31, where there are no freemen to help him — will he not be in an agony of terror? — will he not be compelled to flatter his slaves and to promise them many things sore against his will? And suppose the same god who carried him off were to surround him with neighbours who declare that no man ought to have slaves, and that the owners of them should be punished with death. ‘Still worse and worse! He will be in the midst of his enemies.’ And is not our tyrant such a captive soul, who is tormented32 by a swarm33 of passions which he cannot indulge; living indoors always like a woman, and jealous of those who can go out and see the world?
Having so many evils, will not the most miserable of men be still more miserable in a public station? Master of others when he is not master of himself; like a sick man who is compelled to be an athlete; the meanest of slaves and the most abject34 of flatterers; wanting all things, and never able to satisfy his desires; always in fear and distraction35, like the State of which he is the representative. His jealous, hateful, faithless temper grows worse with command; he is more and more faithless, envious36, unrighteous — the most wretched of men, a misery to himself and to others. And so let us have a final trial and proclamation; need we hire a herald37, or shall I proclaim the result? ‘Made the proclamation yourself.’ The son of Ariston (the best) is of opinion that the best and justest of men is also the happiest, and that this is he who is the most royal master of himself; and that the unjust man is he who is the greatest tyrant of himself and of his State. And I add further —‘seen or unseen by gods or men.’
This is our first proof. The second is derived38 from the three kinds of pleasure, which answer to the three elements of the soul — reason, passion, desire; under which last is comprehended avarice39 as well as sensual appetite, while passion includes ambition, party-feeling, love of reputation. Reason, again, is solely40 directed to the attainment42 of truth, and careless of money and reputation. In accordance with the difference of men’s natures, one of these three principles is in the ascendant, and they have their several pleasures corresponding to them. Interrogate43 now the three natures, and each one will be found praising his own pleasures and depreciating44 those of others. The money-maker will contrast the vanity of knowledge with the solid advantages of wealth. The ambitious man will despise knowledge which brings no honour; whereas the philosopher will regard only the fruition of truth, and will call other pleasures necessary rather than good. Now, how shall we decide between them? Is there any better criterion than experience and knowledge? And which of the three has the truest knowledge and the widest experience? The experience of youth makes the philosopher acquainted with the two kinds of desire, but the avaricious45 and the ambitious man never taste the pleasures of truth and wisdom. Honour he has equally with them; they are ‘judged of him,’ but he is ‘not judged of them,’ for they never attain41 to the knowledge of true being. And his instrument is reason, whereas their standard is only wealth and honour; and if by reason we are to judge, his good will be the truest. And so we arrive at the result that the pleasure of the rational part of the soul, and a life passed in such pleasure is the pleasantest. He who has a right to judge judges thus. Next comes the life of ambition, and, in the third place, that of money-making.
Twice has the just man overthrown46 the unjust — once more, as in an Olympian contest, first offering up a prayer to the saviour47 Zeus, let him try a fall. A wise man whispers to me that the pleasures of the wise are true and pure; all others are a shadow only. Let us examine this: Is not pleasure opposed to pain, and is there not a mean state which is neither? When a man is sick, nothing is more pleasant to him than health. But this he never found out while he was well. In pain he desires only to cease from pain; on the other hand, when he is in an ecstasy48 of pleasure, rest is painful to him. Thus rest or cessation is both pleasure and pain. But can that which is neither become both? Again, pleasure and pain are motions, and the absence of them is rest; but if so, how can the absence of either of them be the other? Thus we are led to infer that the contradiction is an appearance only, and witchery of the senses. And these are not the only pleasures, for there are others which have no preceding pains. Pure pleasure then is not the absence of pain, nor pure pain the absence of pleasure; although most of the pleasures which reach the mind through the body are reliefs of pain, and have not only their reactions when they depart, but their anticipations49 before they come. They can be best described in a simile51. There is in nature an upper, lower, and middle region, and he who passes from the lower to the middle imagines that he is going up and is already in the upper world; and if he were taken back again would think, and truly think, that he was descending52. All this arises out of his ignorance of the true upper, middle, and lower regions. And a like confusion happens with pleasure and pain, and with many other things. The man who compares grey with black, calls grey white; and the man who compares absence of pain with pain, calls the absence of pain pleasure. Again, hunger and thirst are inanitions of the body, ignorance and folly of the soul; and food is the satisfaction of the one, knowledge of the other. Now which is the purer satisfaction — that of eating and drinking, or that of knowledge? Consider the matter thus: The satisfaction of that which has more existence is truer than of that which has less. The invariable and immortal53 has a more real existence than the variable and mortal, and has a corresponding measure of knowledge and truth. The soul, again, has more existence and truth and knowledge than the body, and is therefore more really satisfied and has a more natural pleasure. Those who feast only on earthly food, are always going at random54 up to the middle and down again; but they never pass into the true upper world, or have a taste of true pleasure. They are like fatted beasts, full of gluttony and sensuality, and ready to kill one another by reason of their insatiable lust14; for they are not filled with true being, and their vessel55 is leaky (Gorgias). Their pleasures are mere56 shadows of pleasure, mixed with pain, coloured and intensified57 by contrast, and therefore intensely desired; and men go fighting about them, as Stesichorus says that the Greeks fought about the shadow of Helen at Troy, because they know not the truth.
The same may be said of the passionate58 element:— the desires of the ambitious soul, as well as of the covetous59, have an inferior satisfaction. Only when under the guidance of reason do either of the other principles do their own business or attain the pleasure which is natural to them. When not attaining60, they compel the other parts of the soul to pursue a shadow of pleasure which is not theirs. And the more distant they are from philosophy and reason, the more distant they will be from law and order, and the more illusive61 will be their pleasures. The desires of love and tyranny are the farthest from law, and those of the king are nearest to it. There is one genuine pleasure, and two spurious ones: the tyrant goes beyond even the latter; he has run away altogether from law and reason. Nor can the measure of his inferiority be told, except in a figure. The tyrant is the third removed from the oligarch, and has therefore, not a shadow of his pleasure, but the shadow of a shadow only. The oligarch, again, is thrice removed from the king, and thus we get the formula 3 x 3, which is the number of a surface, representing the shadow which is the tyrant’s pleasure, and if you like to cube this ‘number of the beast,’ you will find that the measure of the difference amounts to 729; the king is 729 times more happy than the tyrant. And this extraordinary number is NEARLY equal to the number of days and nights in a year (365 x 2 = 730); and is therefore concerned with human life. This is the interval62 between a good and bad man in happiness only: what must be the difference between them in comeliness63 of life and virtue64!
Perhaps you may remember some one saying at the beginning of our discussion that the unjust man was profited if he had the reputation of justice. Now that we know the nature of justice and injustice65, let us make an image of the soul, which will personify his words. First of all, fashion a multitudinous beast, having a ring of heads of all manner of animals, tame and wild, and able to produce and change them at pleasure. Suppose now another form of a lion, and another of a man; the second smaller than the first, the third than the second; join them together and cover them with a human skin, in which they are completely concealed66. When this has been done, let us tell the supporter of injustice that he is feeding up the beasts and starving the man. The maintainer of justice, on the other hand, is trying to strengthen the man; he is nourishing the gentle principle within him, and making an alliance with the lion heart, in order that he may be able to keep down the many-headed hydra67, and bring all into unity22 with each other and with themselves. Thus in every point of view, whether in relation to pleasure, honour, or advantage, the just man is right, and the unjust wrong.
But now, let us reason with the unjust, who is not intentionally68 in error. Is not the noble that which subjects the beast to the man, or rather to the God in man; the ignoble69, that which subjects the man to the beast? And if so, who would receive gold on condition that he was to degrade the noblest part of himself under the worst? — who would sell his son or daughter into the hands of brutal70 and evil men, for any amount of money? And will he sell his own fairer and diviner part without any compunction to the most godless and foul71? Would he not be worse than Eriphyle, who sold her husband’s life for a necklace? And intemperance72 is the letting loose of the multiform monster, and pride and sullenness73 are the growth and increase of the lion and serpent element, while luxury and effeminacy are caused by a too great relaxation74 of spirit. Flattery and meanness again arise when the spirited element is subjected to avarice, and the lion is habituated to become a monkey. The real disgrace of handicraft arts is, that those who are engaged in them have to flatter, instead of mastering their desires; therefore we say that they should be placed under the control of the better principle in another because they have none in themselves; not, as Thrasymachus imagined, to the injury of the subjects, but for their good. And our intention in educating the young, is to give them self-control; the law desires to nurse up in them a higher principle, and when they have acquired this, they may go their ways.
‘What, then, shall a man profit, if he gain the whole world’ and become more and more wicked? Or what shall he profit by escaping discovery, if the concealment75 of evil prevents the cure? If he had been punished, the brute76 within him would have been silenced, and the gentler element liberated77; and he would have united temperance, justice, and wisdom in his soul — a union better far than any combination of bodily gifts. The man of understanding will honour knowledge above all; in the next place he will keep under his body, not only for the sake of health and strength, but in order to attain the most perfect harmony of body and soul. In the acquisition of riches, too, he will aim at order and harmony; he will not desire to heap up wealth without measure, but he will fear that the increase of wealth will disturb the constitution of his own soul. For the same reason he will only accept such honours as will make him a better man; any others he will decline. ‘In that case,’ said he, ‘he will never be a politician.’ Yes, but he will, in his own city; though probably not in his native country, unless by some divine accident. ‘You mean that he will be a citizen of the ideal city, which has no place upon earth.’ But in heaven, I replied, there is a pattern of such a city, and he who wishes may order his life after that image. Whether such a state is or ever will be matters not; he will act according to that pattern and no other . . .
The most noticeable points in the 9th Book of the Republic are:—(1) the account of pleasure; (2) the number of the interval which divides the king from the tyrant; (3) the pattern which is in heaven.
1. Plato’s account of pleasure is remarkable78 for moderation, and in this respect contrasts with the later Platonists and the views which are attributed to them by Aristotle. He is not, like the Cynics, opposed to all pleasure, but rather desires that the several parts of the soul shall have their natural satisfaction; he even agrees with the Epicureans in describing pleasure as something more than the absence of pain. This is proved by the circumstance that there are pleasures which have no antecedent pains (as he also remarks in the Philebus), such as the pleasures of smell, and also the pleasures of hope and anticipation50. In the previous book he had made the distinction between necessary and unnecessary pleasure, which is repeated by Aristotle, and he now observes that there are a further class of ‘wild beast’ pleasures, corresponding to Aristotle’s (Greek). He dwells upon the relative and unreal character of sensual pleasures and the illusion which arises out of the contrast of pleasure and pain, pointing out the superiority of the pleasures of reason, which are at rest, over the fleeting79 pleasures of sense and emotion. The pre-eminence of royal pleasure is shown by the fact that reason is able to form a judgment80 of the lower pleasures, while the two lower parts of the soul are incapable81 of judging the pleasures of reason. Thus, in his treatment of pleasure, as in many other subjects, the philosophy of Plato is ‘sawn up into quantities’ by Aristotle; the analysis which was originally made by him became in the next generation the foundation of further technical distinctions. Both in Plato and Aristotle we note the illusion under which the ancients fell of regarding the transience of pleasure as a proof of its unreality, and of confounding the permanence of the intellectual pleasures with the unchangeableness of the knowledge from which they are derived. Neither do we like to admit that the pleasures of knowledge, though more elevating, are not more lasting82 than other pleasures, and are almost equally dependent on the accidents of our bodily state (Introduction to Philebus).
2. The number of the interval which separates the king from the tyrant, and royal from tyrannical pleasures, is 729, the cube of 9. Which Plato characteristically designates as a number concerned with human life, because NEARLY equivalent to the number of days and nights in the year. He is desirous of proclaiming that the interval between them is immeasurable, and invents a formula to give expression to his idea. Those who spoke83 of justice as a cube, of virtue as an art of measuring (Prot.), saw no inappropriateness in conceiving the soul under the figure of a line, or the pleasure of the tyrant as separated from the pleasure of the king by the numerical interval of 729. And in modern times we sometimes use metaphorically84 what Plato employed as a philosophical85 formula. ‘It is not easy to estimate the loss of the tyrant, except perhaps in this way,’ says Plato. So we might say, that although the life of a good man is not to be compared to that of a bad man, yet you may measure the difference between them by valuing one minute of the one at an hour of the other (‘One day in thy courts is better than a thousand’), or you might say that ‘there is an infinite difference.’ But this is not so much as saying, in homely86 phrase, ‘They are a thousand miles asunder87.’ And accordingly Plato finds the natural vehicle of his thoughts in a progression of numbers; this arithmetical formula he draws out with the utmost seriousness, and both here and in the number of generation seems to find an additional proof of the truth of his speculation88 in forming the number into a geometrical figure; just as persons in our own day are apt to fancy that a statement is verified when it has been only thrown into an abstract form. In speaking of the number 729 as proper to human life, he probably intended to intimate that one year of the tyrannical = 12 hours of the royal life.
The simple observation that the comparison of two similar solids is effected by the comparison of the cubes of their sides, is the mathematical groundwork of this fanciful expression. There is some difficulty in explaining the steps by which the number 729 is obtained; the oligarch is removed in the third degree from the royal and aristocratical, and the tyrant in the third degree from the oligarchical89; but we have to arrange the terms as the sides of a square and to count the oligarch twice over, thus reckoning them not as = 5 but as = 9. The square of 9 is passed lightly over as only a step towards the cube.
3. Towards the close of the Republic, Plato seems to be more and more convinced of the ideal character of his own speculations90. At the end of the 9th Book the pattern which is in heaven takes the place of the city of philosophers on earth. The vision which has received form and substance at his hands, is now discovered to be at a distance. And yet this distant kingdom is also the rule of man’s life. (‘Say not lo! here, or lo! there, for the kingdom of God is within you.’) Thus a note is struck which prepares for the revelation of a future life in the following Book. But the future life is present still; the ideal of politics is to be realized in the individual.
点击收听单词发音
1 enquire | |
v.打听,询问;调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 misery | |
n.痛苦,苦恼,苦难;悲惨的境遇,贫苦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 folly | |
n.愚笨,愚蠢,蠢事,蠢行,傻话 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 unnatural | |
adj.不自然的;反常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 temperately | |
adv.节制地,适度地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 perturbing | |
v.使(某人)烦恼,不安( perturb的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 luminous | |
adj.发光的,发亮的;光明的;明白易懂的;有启发的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 democrat | |
n.民主主义者,民主人士;民主党党员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 ornamental | |
adj.装饰的;作装饰用的;n.装饰品;观赏植物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 iniquity | |
n.邪恶;不公正 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 implant | |
vt.注入,植入,灌输 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 scents | |
n.香水( scent的名词复数 );气味;(动物的)臭迹;(尤指狗的)嗅觉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 lust | |
n.性(淫)欲;渴(欲)望;vi.对…有强烈的欲望 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 lusting | |
贪求(lust的现在分词形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 ravens | |
n.低质煤;渡鸦( raven的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 defraud | |
vt.欺骗,欺诈 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 blessing | |
n.祈神赐福;祷告;祝福,祝愿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 pickpocket | |
n.扒手;v.扒窃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 tyrant | |
n.暴君,专制的君主,残暴的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 mischief | |
n.损害,伤害,危害;恶作剧,捣蛋,胡闹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 unity | |
n.团结,联合,统一;和睦,协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 followers | |
追随者( follower的名词复数 ); 用户; 契据的附面; 从动件 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 utterly | |
adv.完全地,绝对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 treacherous | |
adj.不可靠的,有暗藏的危险的;adj.背叛的,背信弃义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 miserable | |
adj.悲惨的,痛苦的;可怜的,糟糕的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 monarchical | |
adj. 国王的,帝王的,君主的,拥护君主制的 =monarchic | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 penetrate | |
v.透(渗)入;刺入,刺穿;洞察,了解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 impartial | |
adj.(in,to)公正的,无偏见的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 conjecture | |
n./v.推测,猜测 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 wilderness | |
n.杳无人烟的一片陆地、水等,荒漠 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 tormented | |
饱受折磨的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 swarm | |
n.(昆虫)等一大群;vi.成群飞舞;蜂拥而入 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 abject | |
adj.极可怜的,卑屈的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 distraction | |
n.精神涣散,精神不集中,消遣,娱乐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 envious | |
adj.嫉妒的,羡慕的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 herald | |
vt.预示...的来临,预告,宣布,欢迎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 avarice | |
n.贪婪;贪心 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 attainment | |
n.达到,到达;[常pl.]成就,造诣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 interrogate | |
vt.讯问,审问,盘问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 depreciating | |
v.贬值,跌价,减价( depreciate的现在分词 );贬低,蔑视,轻视 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 avaricious | |
adj.贪婪的,贪心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 overthrown | |
adj. 打翻的,推倒的,倾覆的 动词overthrow的过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 saviour | |
n.拯救者,救星 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 ecstasy | |
n.狂喜,心醉神怡,入迷 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 anticipations | |
预期( anticipation的名词复数 ); 预测; (信托财产收益的)预支; 预期的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 anticipation | |
n.预期,预料,期望 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 simile | |
n.直喻,明喻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 descending | |
n. 下行 adj. 下降的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 immortal | |
adj.不朽的;永生的,不死的;神的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 random | |
adj.随机的;任意的;n.偶然的(或随便的)行动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 vessel | |
n.船舶;容器,器皿;管,导管,血管 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 intensified | |
v.(使)增强, (使)加剧( intensify的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 passionate | |
adj.热情的,热烈的,激昂的,易动情的,易怒的,性情暴躁的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 covetous | |
adj.贪婪的,贪心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 attaining | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的现在分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 illusive | |
adj.迷惑人的,错觉的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 interval | |
n.间隔,间距;幕间休息,中场休息 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 comeliness | |
n. 清秀, 美丽, 合宜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 injustice | |
n.非正义,不公正,不公平,侵犯(别人的)权利 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 concealed | |
a.隐藏的,隐蔽的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 hydra | |
n.水螅;难于根除的祸患 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 intentionally | |
ad.故意地,有意地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 ignoble | |
adj.不光彩的,卑鄙的;可耻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 brutal | |
adj.残忍的,野蛮的,不讲理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 foul | |
adj.污秽的;邪恶的;v.弄脏;妨害;犯规;n.犯规 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 intemperance | |
n.放纵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 sullenness | |
n. 愠怒, 沉闷, 情绪消沉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 relaxation | |
n.松弛,放松;休息;消遣;娱乐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 concealment | |
n.隐藏, 掩盖,隐瞒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 brute | |
n.野兽,兽性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 liberated | |
a.无拘束的,放纵的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 remarkable | |
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 fleeting | |
adj.短暂的,飞逝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 judgment | |
n.审判;判断力,识别力,看法,意见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 incapable | |
adj.无能力的,不能做某事的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 lasting | |
adj.永久的,永恒的;vbl.持续,维持 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 spoke | |
n.(车轮的)辐条;轮辐;破坏某人的计划;阻挠某人的行动 v.讲,谈(speak的过去式);说;演说;从某种观点来说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 metaphorically | |
adv. 用比喻地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 homely | |
adj.家常的,简朴的;不漂亮的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 asunder | |
adj.分离的,化为碎片 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 speculation | |
n.思索,沉思;猜测;投机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 oligarchical | |
adj.寡头政治的,主张寡头政治的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 speculations | |
n.投机买卖( speculation的名词复数 );思考;投机活动;推断 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |