From its point of view, too, the distinction that we laid down between history and philology11 suggests refraining from the search hitherto made for the beginnings of Gr?co-Roman historiography by means of composing lists of magistrates12 and of adding to these brief mention of wars, treatises13, embassies from colonies, religious festivities, earthquakes, inundations, and the like, in the ?ροι and in the annales pontificum, in archives and museums made in temples, or indeed in the chronological15 nails fixed17 to the walls, spoken of by Perizonius. Such things are extrinsic18 to historiography and form the precedent19, not of it, but of chronicle and philology, which were not born for the first time in the nineteenth or seventeenth century, or at any rate during the Alexandrine period, but belong to all times, for in all times men take note of what they remember and attempt to preserve such memorials intact, to restore and to increase them. The precedent of history cannot be something different from history, but is history itself, as philosophy is the precedent of philosophy and the living of the living. Nevertheless the thought of Herodotus and of the logographs really does unite itself with religions, myths, theogonies, cosmogonies, genealogies20, and with legendary21 and epical23 tales, which were not indeed poetry, or were not only poetry but also thoughts—that is to say, metaphysics and histories.[Pg 183] The whole of later historiography developed from them by a dialectical process, for which they supplied the presuppositions—that is to say, concepts, propositions of fact and fancy mingled25, and with that the stimulus26 better to seek out the truth and to dissipate fancies. This dissipation took place more rapidly at the time which it is usual to fix by convention as the beginning of Greek historiography.
At that time thought deserts mythological27 history and its ruder form, prodigious28 or miraculous29 history, and enters earthly or human history—that is to say, the general conception that is still ours, so much so that it has been possible for an illustrious living historian to propose the works of Thucydides as an example and model to the historians of our times. Certainly that exit and that entrance did not represent for the Greeks a complete breaking with the past; and since earthly history could not have been altogether wanting in the past, so it is not to be believed that the Greeks from the sixth and seventh centuries onward30 should have abandoned all faith in mythology31 and prodigies32. These things persisted not only with the people and among lesser33 or vulgar historiographers, but also left their traces among some of the greatest. Nevertheless, looking at the whole from above, as one should look at it, it is evident that the environment is altogether changed from what it was. Even the many fables34 that we read in Herodotus, and which were to be read in the logographs, are rarely (as has been justly observed) put forward ingenuously35, but are usually given as by one who collects what others believe, and does not for that reason accept those beliefs, even if he does not openly evince his disbelief; or he collects them because he does not know what to substitute for them, and rather as matter for reflection[Pg 184] and inquiry36: qu? nec confirmare argumentis neque refellere in animo est, as Tacitus says, when he recounts the fables of the Germans: plura transcribo quam credo, declared Quintus Curtius. Herodotus is certainly not Voltaire, nor is he indeed Thucydides (Thucydides, 'the atheist'); but certainly he is no longer Homer or Hesiod.
The following are a few examples of leading problems which ancient historians had before them, dictated37 by the conditions and events of Greek and Roman life; they were treated from a mental point of view, which no longer found in those facts episodes of the rivalry38 of Aphrodite and Hera (as formerly39 in the Trojan War), but varying complex human struggles, due to human interests, expressing themselves in human actions. How did the wars between the Greeks and the Persians originate and develop? What were the origins of the Peloponnesian War? of the expedition of Cyrus against Artaxerxes? How was the Roman power formed in Latium, and how did it afterward40 extend in Italy and in the whole world? How did the Romans succeed in depriving the Carthaginians of the hegemony of the Mediterranean41? What were the political institutions developed in Athens, Rome, and Sparta, and what form did the social struggle take in those cities? What did the Athenian demos, the Roman plebs, the eupatrides, and the patres desire? What were the virtues43, the dispositions44, the points of view, of the various peoples which entered into conflict among themselves, Athenians, Lacedemonians, Persians, Macedonians, Romans, Gauls, and Germans? What were the characters of the great men who guided the destinies of the peoples, Themistocles, Pericles, Alexander, Hannibal, and Scipio? These problems were solved in a series of classical[Pg 185] works by Thucydides, Xenophon, Polybius, Livy, Tacitus, etc., and they will certainly not be blamed for failing to exhaust their themes—that is, for failing to sound the bottom of the universe, because there is no sounding the bottom of the universe—nor because they solve those problems only in the terms in which they had proposed them, neither more nor less than as we solve the problems of our day in our own terms. Nor must we forget that since modern historiography is still much as it was left by the Greeks, the greater part of those events are still thought as they were by the ancients, and although something has been added and a different light illumines the whole, the work of the ancient historians is preserved in our own: a true "eternal possession," as Thucydides intended that his history should be.
And just as historical thought had become invigorated in its passage from the mythological to the human stage, so did research and philology grow. Herodotus was already travelling, asking questions, and listening to answers, distinguishing between the things that he had seen with his own eyes and those which depended upon hearsay45, opinion, and conjecture46; Thucydides was submitting to criticism different traditions relating to the same fact, and even inserting documents in his narrative47. Later appeared legions of learned men and critics, who compiled 'antiquities48' and 'libraries,' and busied themselves also with the reading of texts, with chronology and geography, thus affording great assistance to historical studies. Such a fervour of philological49 studies was eventually attained that it was recognized as necessary to draw a clear distinction between the 'histories of antiquaries' (of which a considerable number survive either entire or in fragments)[Pg 186] and 'histories of historians,' and Polybius several times said that it is easy to compose history from books, because it suffices to take up one's residence in a city where there exist rich libraries, but that true history requires acquaintance with political and military affairs and direct knowledge of places and of people; and Lucian repeated that it is indispensable for the historian to have political sense, ?δ?δακτον φυσ?ω? δ?ρον, a gift of nature not to be learned (the maxims50 and practices praised as quite novel by M?ser and Niebuhr are therefore by no means new). The fact is that a more profound theoretical consciousness corresponded with a more vigorous historiography, so inseparable is the theory of history from history, advancing with it. It was also known that history should not be made a simple instrument of practice, of political intrigue52, or of amusement, and that its function is above all to aim at truth: ne quid falsi dicere audeat, ne quid veri non audeat. In consequence of this, partisanship53, even for one's own country, was condemned54 (although it was recognized chat solicitude55 and sympathy were permissible); and quidquid Gr?cia mendax audet in historia was blamed. It was known that history is not chronicle (annales), which is limited to external things, recording56 (in the words of Asellio, the ancient Roman historian) quod factum, quoque anno gestum sit, whereas history tries to understand quo Consilio, quaque ratione gesta sint. And it was also known that history cannot set herself the same task as poetry. We find Thucydides referring with disdain57 to histories written with the object of gaining the prize in oratorical58 competitions, and to those which indulge in fables to please the vulgar. Polybius too inveighed59 against those who seek to emphasize moving details, and depict60 women dishevelled and in tears, and dreadful[Pg 187] scenes, as though composing tragedies and as though it were their business to create the marvellous and pleasing and not impart truth and instruction. If it be a fact that rhetorical historiography (a worsening of the imaginative and poetic63) abounded64 in antiquity65 and introduced its false gold even into some masterpieces, the general tendency of the better historians was to set themselves free of ornate rhetoricians and of cheap eloquence66. But the ancient historians will never fail of lofty poetical67 power and elevation68 for this reason (not even the 'prosaic69' Polybius, who sometimes paints most effective pictures), but will ever retain what is proper to lofty historical narrative. Cicero and Quintilian, Diogenes and Lucian, all recognize that history must adopt verba ferme poetarum, that it is proxima poetis et quodammodo carmen solutum, that scribitur ad narrandum, non ad demonstrandum, that ?χει τι ποιητικ?ν, and the like. What the best historians and theorists sought at that time was not the aridity70 and dryness of mathematical or physical treatment (such as we often hear desired in our day), but gravity, abstention from fabulous71 and pleasing tales, or if not from fabulous then from frivolous72 tales, in fact from competition with the rhetoricians and composers of histories that were romances or gross caricatures of such. Above all they desired that history should remain faithful to real life, since it is the instrument of life, and a form of knowledge useful to the statesman and to the lover of his country, and by no means docile73 to the capricious requirements of the unoccupied seeking amusement.
This theory of historiography, which may be found here and there in a good many special treatises and in general treatises on the art of speech, finds nowhere such complete and conscious expression as in the frequent[Pg 188] polemical interludes of Polybius in his Histories, where the polemic74 itself endows it with precision, concreteness, and savour. Polybius is the Aristotle of ancient historiography: an Aristotle who is both historical and theoretical, completing the Stagirite, who in the vast expanse of his work had taken but little interest in history properly so called. And since so great a part of the ancient narratives75 lives in our own, so there is not one of the propositions recorded that has not been included and has not been worthy76 of being included in our treatises. And if, for example, the maxim51 that history should be narrated77 by men of the world and not by the simply erudite or by philologists78, that it is born of practice and assists in practice, has been often neglected, the blame falls on those who neglect it. A further blunder committed by such writers has been to forget completely the τι ποιητικ?ν and to pay court to an ideal of history something like an anatomical map or a treatise14 of mechanics.
But the defect that ancient historiography exposes to our gaze is of another sort. The ancients did not observe it as a defect, or only sometimes, in a vague and fugitive79 manner, without attaching weight to it, for otherwise they would have remedied it when it occurred. The modern spirit inquires how the sentiments and conceptions which are now our ideal patrimony80, and the institutions in which they are realized, have been gradually formed. It wishes to understand the revolutionary passages from primitive81 and Oriental to Gr?co-Roman culture, how modern ethic83 was attained through ancient ethic, the modern through the ancient state, the vast industry and international commerce of the modern world through the ancient mode of economic production, the passage from the myths of the Aryans to our philosophies,[Pg 189] from Mycenean to French or Swedish or Italian art of the twentieth century. Hence there are special histories of culture, of philosophy, of poetry, of the sciences, of technique, of economy, of morality, of religions, and so on, which are preferred to histories of individuals or of states themselves, in so far as they are abstract individuals. They are illuminated84 and inspired throughout with the ideas of liberty, of civilization, of humanity, and of progress. All this is not to be found in ancient historiography, although it cannot be said to be altogether absent, for with what could the mind of man have ever been occupied, save by human ideals or 'values'? Nor should the error be made of considering 'epochs' as something compact and static, whereas they are various and in motion, or of rendering86 those divisions natural and external which, as has been demonstrated, are nothing but the movement of our thought as we think history, a fallacy linked with the other one concerning the absolute beginning of history and the rendering temporal of the forms of the spirit. Whoever is gifted with the patience of the collector will meet here and there with suggestions and buddings of those historiographical conceptions of which, generally speaking, we have denied the existence in the writings of the ancients. He who finds diversion in modernizing87 the old may travesty88 the thoughts of the ancients, as they have been travestied, so as to render them almost altogether similar to those of the moderns. In the first book of Aristotle's Metaphysics, for instance, is to be admired a sketch89 of the development of Greek philosophy, of the various naturalistic interpretations90 which have been in turn proposed for the explanation of the cosmos91, and so on, up to the new orientation92 of the mind, when, "compelled by truth itself," it turned toward a different order of[Pg 190] principles—that is to say, till the time of Anaxagoras, "who seems to be a sober man among the intoxicated," thus continuing up to the time of Socrates, who founded ethic and discovered the universal and the definition. A sketch of the history of civilization is to be found at the beginning of the History of Thucydides, and Polybius will be found discoursing93 of the progress that had been made in all the arts, while Cicero, Quintilian, and several others trace the progress of rights and of literature. There are also touches of human value in conflict with one another in the narratives of the struggles between Greeks and barbarians94, between the truly civil and active life of the former and the proud, lazy habits of the latter. Other similar conceptions of human values will be found in many comparisons of peoples, and above all in the way that Tacitus describes the Germans as a new moral power rising up against that of ancient Rome, and perhaps also in the repugnance95 which the same historian experiences at seeing before him the Jews, who follow rites96 contrarius ceteris mortalibus. Finally, Rome, mistress of the world, will sometimes assume in our eyes the aspect of a transparent97 symbol of the human ideal, analogous98 to Roman law, gradually idealized in the form of natural law. But here it is rather a question of symbols than of conceptions, of our own conclusions than of the thoughts proper to the ancients. When, for instance, we examine the history of philosophy of Aristotle as outlined by him, we find that it consists above all in a rapid critical account to serve as prop24?deutic to his system; and literary and artistic99 histories and histories of civilization seem often to be weakened by the prejudice that these are not really necessary mental forms, but luxuries and refinements100. At the utmost we can speak of exceptions, incidents, tentatives; which[Pg 191] does not in any way alter the comprehensive impression and general conclusion to the effect that the ancients never possessed101 explicit102 histories of civilization, philosophy, religions, literature, art, or rights: none, in fact, of the many possessed by ourselves. Nor did they possess 'biography' in the sense that we do, as the history of the ideal function of an individual in his own time and in the life of humanity, nor the sense of development, and when they speak of primitive times they rarely feel that they are primitive, but are rather disposed to transfigure them poetically103, in the same way that Dante did by the mouth of Cacciaguida that Fiorenza which "stood soberly and modestly at peace" within the circle of the ancient days. It was one of the "severe labours" of our Vico to recover the crude reality of history beneath these poetic idylls. In this work he was assisted, not by the ancient historiographers, but by documents and mostly by languages.
The physiognomy of the histories of the ancients as described very accurately104 reflects the character of their philosophy, which never attained to the conception of the spirit, and therefore also failed to attain8 to that of humanity, liberty, and progress, which are aspects or synonyms105 of the former. It certainly passed from physiology106 or cosmology to ethic, logic16, and rhetoric62; but it schematized and materialized these spiritual disciplines because it treated them empirically. Thus their ethic did not rise above the custom of Greece and Rome, nor their logic above abstract forms of reasoning and discussing, nor their poetic above classes of literature. For this reason all assume the form of precepts107. 'Anti-historical philosophy' has been universally recognized and described, but it is anti-historical because anti-spiritual, anti-historical because naturalistic.[Pg 192] The ancients also failed to notice the deficiency observed by us, for they were entirely108 occupied with the joy of the effort of passing from myth to science and thus to the collection and classification of the facts of reality. That is to say, they were engrossed109 upon the sole problem which they set themselves to solve, and solved so successfully that they supplied naturalism with the instruments which it still employs: formal logic, grammar, the doctrine110 of the virtues, the doctrine of literary classes, categories of civil rights, and so forth111. These were all Gr?co-Roman creations.
But that ancient historians and philosophers were not explicitly112 aware of the above defect in its proper terms, or rather in our modern terms, does not mean that they were not to some extent exercised by it. In every historical period exist problems theoretically formulated113 and for that very reason solved, while others have not yet arrived at complete theoretical maturity114, but are seen, intuited, though not yet adequately thought. If the former are the positive contribution of that time to the chain whose links form the human spirit, the latter represent an unsatisfied demand, which binds115 that time in another way to the coming time. The great attention paid to the negative aspect of every epoch85 sometimes leads to the forgetting of the other aspect, and to the consequent imagining of a humanity that passes not from satisfaction to satisfaction through dissatisfaction, but from dissatisfaction to dissatisfaction and from error to error. But obscurities and discordances are possible in so far as light and concord116 have been previously117 attained. Thus they represent in their way progress, as is to be seen from the history that we are recounting, where we find them very numerous for the very reason that the age of mythologies118 and of[Pg 193] prodigies has been left behind. If Greece and Rome had not been both more than Greece and more than Rome, if they had not been the human spirit, which is infinitely119 greater than any Greece and any Rome—its transitory individuations—they would have been satisfied with the human portraits of their historians and would not have sought beyond. But they did seek beyond—that is to say, those very historians and philosophers sought; and since they had before them so many episodes and dramas of human life, reconstructed by their thought, they asked themselves what was the cause of those events, reasonably concluding that such a cause might be one fact or another, a particular fact; and for this reason they began to distinguish between facts and causes, and, in the order of causes themselves, between cause and occasion, as does Thucydides, or between beginning, cause, and occasion ?ρχ?, α?τ?α, πρ?φασι?, like Polybius. They thus became involved in disputes as to the true cause of this or that event, and ever since antiquity attempts have been made to solve the enigma120 of the 'greatness' of Rome, assuming in modern times the guise121 of a solemn experimentum of historical thought and thus forming the diversion of those historians who linger behind. The question was often generalized in the other question as to the motive122 power behind all history; and here too appear doctrines123, afterward drawn124 out to great length, such as that the form of the political constitution was the cause of all the rest, and that other doctrine relating to climate and to the temperaments125 of peoples. The doctrine principally proposed and accepted was that of the natural law of the circle in human affairs, the perpetual alternation of good and evil, or the passage through political forms, which always returns to the[Pg 194] form from which it has taken its start, or as growth from infancy126 to manhood, declining into old age and decrepitude127 and ending in death. But a law of this sort, which satisfied and still satisfies the Oriental mind, did not satisfy the classical mind, which had a lively sense of human effort and of the stimulus received from obstacles encountered and conflicts endured. Hence therefore the further questions: Does fate or immutable128 necessity oppress man, or is he not rather the plaything of capricious fortune, or is he ruled by a wise and sagacious providence129? It was also asked whether the gods are interested in human affairs or not. These questions met with answers that are sometimes pious130, advocating submission131 to the divine will and wisdom, sometimes, again, inspired with the notion that the gods are not concerned with human affairs themselves, but solely132 with vengeance133 and punishment. All these conceptions lack firmness, and are for the most part confused, since a general uncertainty134 and confession135 of ignorance prevails in them: in incerto judicium est, said Tacitus, almost summing up the ancient argument on the subject in this epigram, or rather finding non-thought, failure to understand, to be the result of the argument.
What we do not understand we do not dominate; on the contrary, it dominates us, or at least menaces us, taking the form of evil; hence the psychological attitude of the ancients toward history must be described as pessimistic. They saw much greatness fall, but they never discovered the greatness that does not fall and that rises up greater after every fall. For this reason a flood of bitterness inundates136 their histories. Happiness, beauty of human life, always seemed to be something that had been and was no[Pg 195] longer, and were it present would have soon been lost. For the Romans and those professing137 the cult82 of Rome, it was primitive, austere138, victorious139 Rome; and all the Roman historians, big and little, Livy, Sallust, and Tacitus, Paterculus and Florus, fix their gaze upon that image, as they lament140 the corruption141 of later days. Once it was Rome that trampled142 the world underfoot; but they knew that the triumphant143 queen must some day become slave from queen that once she was. This thought manifests itself in the most various forms, from the melancholy144 meditations145 of Scipio upon the ruins of Carthage to the fearful expectation of the lordship which—as Persia to Babylonia and Macedonia to Persia—must succeed to that of the Romans (the theory of the 'four monarchies146' has its origin in the Gr?co-Roman world, whence it filtered into Palestine and into the Book of Daniel). Sometimes repressed, sometimes outspoken147, we hear the anxious question: Who will be the successor and the gravedigger? Will it be the menacing Parthian? Will it be the Germans, so rich in new and mysterious energy?—all this, despite the proud consciousness of ancient times that had uttered the words "Rome, the eternal city." Certainly, that general pessimism148 is not altogether coherent, for no pessimism can be so altogether, and here and there appear fugitive hints of a perception of human progress in this or that part of life. We find, for instance, Tacitus, bitterest of men, remarking that nec omnia apud priores meliora, sed nostra quoque ?tas multa laudis et artium imitanda tulit, and one of the speakers in the De oratoribus observes that literary forms change with the times and that it is owing to the vitio malignitatis humana that we hear the perpetual praise of ancient things and the perpetual abuse of things modern.[Pg 196] Another interlocutor in the same dialogue draws attention to the dialectic connexion between the turbulence149 of life and the greatness of art, whence Rome donec erravit, donec se partibus et dissensionibus confecit, precisely150 at that time tulit valentiorem eloquentiam. This linking together of good and evil is not altogether absent in ancient philosophy, and is also to be found here and there in ancient historiography. Sallust, for example, is of opinion that Rome remained in good health so long as she had Carthage opposed to her and giving her trouble. Readers of Cicero and of Seneca will be aware that the idea of humanity also made considerable progress during the last days of the Republic and the first days of the Empire, owing to the influence of Stoicism. Divine providence too is courted, as was not formerly the case, and we also find Diodorus Siculus undertaking151 to treat the affairs of all nations as those of a single city (καθ?περ μι?? πολ?ω?). But these promises remain still weak, vague, and inert152 (the promissor Diodorus, for example, carried out none of his grandiose153 prologue154), and in any case they foretell155 the dissolution of the classical world. During this epoch the problem as to the signification of history remains156 unsolved, because the contradictory157 conceptions above mentioned of fortune or of the gods, the belief in a universal worsening of things, in a fall or a regression, which had already been expressed in many ancient myths, were not by any means solutions.
Owing to their failure to realize spiritual value as the immanent progressive force in history, even the loftiest of the ancient historians were not able to maintain the unity158 and autonomy of historiographical work, which in other respects they had discovered and asserted. Although they had penetrated159 the deception160 exercised by those histories that are really poetry, or lies and[Pg 197] partisanship, or collections of material and unintelligent piling up of erudition, or instruments of pleasure, affording marvel61 for simple folk, yet they were on the other hand incapable161 of ever setting themselves free of the preconception of history as directed to an end of edification and chiefly of instruction. This real heteronomy then appeared to be autonomy. They are all agreed as to this: Thucydides proposed to narrate past events in order to predict from them future events, identical or similar, the perpetual return of human fortunes; Polybius sought out the causes of facts in order that he might apply them to analogous cases, and held those unexpected events to be of inferior importance whose irregularities place them outside rules; Tacitus, in conformity162 with his chief interest, which was rather moralistic than social or political, held his chief end to be the collection of facts notable for the vice163 or virtue42 which they contained, ne virtutes sileantur utque pravis dictis factìsque ex posteritate et infamia metus sit. Behind them came all the minor164 historians, all the hypocrites, who repeated by imitation or involuntary echo or false unction and in a superficial way what in the greater writers was the result of profound thought, as, for instance, the Sallusts, the Diogenes, the Diodori, the Plutarchs, and those that resemble them. Then there were all the extractors of historical quintessences, of memorable165 deeds and words of statesmen, captains, and philosophers, and even of women (the γυναικ?ν ?ρετα?). Ancient historiography has been called 'pragmatical,' and such it is, in the double sense of the word, ancient and modern: in so far as it limits itself to the earthly side of things and especially to the political (the 'pragmatic' of Polybius), and in so far as it adorns166 them with reflections and advice (the 'apodictic' of the same historian-theorist).
[Pg 198]
This heteronomous theory of history does not always remain merely theory, prologue, or frame, but sometimes operates so as to lead to the mingling167 of elements that are not historiographical with history, such as, for instance, is the case with the 'speeches' or 'orations168' of historical personages, not delivered or not in agreement with what was really said, but invented or arranged by the historian and put into the mouths of the personages. This, in my opinion, has been wrongly looked upon as a survival of the 'epic22 spirit' in ancient historiography, or as a simple proof of the rhetorical ability of the narrators, because, if the first explanation hold as to some of the popular writers and the second as to certain rhetoricians, the origin of those falsifications was with the greater historians nothing but the fulfilment of the obligation of teaching and counselling accepted by them. But when such ends had been assigned to history, its intrinsic quality of truth and the line of demarcation which it drew between real and imaginary could not but vacillate to some extent, since the imaginary sometimes served excellently well and even better than the real for those ends. And setting aside Plato, who despised all knowledge save that of the transcendental ideas, did not Aristotle himself ask whether the greater truth belonged to history or to poetry? Had he not indeed said that history is 'less philosophical' than poetry? And if so why should not history have availed itself of the aid of poetry and of imagination? In any case, resistance could be opposed to this ulterior perversion169 by seeking the truth with vigilant170 eye, and also by reducing the share of the imaginary speeches and other parerga co the smallest dimensions. But it was impossible to dispense171 with belief in the end of instruction, because it was in any case necessary that history should have[Pg 199] some end, and a true end had not been discovered, and the end of instruction performed almost the function of a metaphor172 of the truth, since it was to some extent the nearest to the truth. In Polybius critical vigilance, scientific austerity, a keen desire for ample and severe history, attain to so high a level that one would feel disposed to treat the historian of Megalopolis173 like one of those great pagans that medieval imagination admitted to Paradise, or at least to Purgatory174, as worthy of having known the true God by extraordinary means and as a reward for their intense moral conscience. But if we envisage175 the matter with greater calmness we shall have to consign176 Polybius also to the Limbo177 where those who "were before Christianity" and "did not duly adore God" are received. They were men of great value and reached the boundary, even touching178 it, but they never passed beyond.
[1] See pp. 112-116.
点击收听单词发音
1 investigation | |
n.调查,调查研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 narrate | |
v.讲,叙述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 superfluous | |
adj.过多的,过剩的,多余的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 pinnacle | |
n.尖塔,尖顶,山峰;(喻)顶峰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 edifice | |
n.宏伟的建筑物(如宫殿,教室) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 salute | |
vi.行礼,致意,问候,放礼炮;vt.向…致意,迎接,赞扬;n.招呼,敬礼,礼炮 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 scarcity | |
n.缺乏,不足,萧条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 philology | |
n.语言学;语文学 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 magistrates | |
地方法官,治安官( magistrate的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 treatises | |
n.专题著作,专题论文,专著( treatise的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 treatise | |
n.专著;(专题)论文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 chronological | |
adj.按年月顺序排列的,年代学的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 logic | |
n.逻辑(学);逻辑性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 extrinsic | |
adj.外部的;不紧要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 precedent | |
n.先例,前例;惯例;adj.在前的,在先的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 genealogies | |
n.系谱,家系,宗谱( genealogy的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 legendary | |
adj.传奇(中)的,闻名遐迩的;n.传奇(文学) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 epic | |
n.史诗,叙事诗;adj.史诗般的,壮丽的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 epical | |
adj.叙事诗的,英勇的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 prop | |
vt.支撑;n.支柱,支撑物;支持者,靠山 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 mingled | |
混合,混入( mingle的过去式和过去分词 ); 混进,与…交往[联系] | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 stimulus | |
n.刺激,刺激物,促进因素,引起兴奋的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 mythological | |
adj.神话的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 prodigious | |
adj.惊人的,奇妙的;异常的;巨大的;庞大的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 miraculous | |
adj.像奇迹一样的,不可思议的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 onward | |
adj.向前的,前进的;adv.向前,前进,在先 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 mythology | |
n.神话,神话学,神话集 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 prodigies | |
n.奇才,天才(尤指神童)( prodigy的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 lesser | |
adj.次要的,较小的;adv.较小地,较少地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 fables | |
n.寓言( fable的名词复数 );神话,传说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 ingenuously | |
adv.率直地,正直地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 dictated | |
v.大声讲或读( dictate的过去式和过去分词 );口授;支配;摆布 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 rivalry | |
n.竞争,竞赛,对抗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 formerly | |
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 afterward | |
adv.后来;以后 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 Mediterranean | |
adj.地中海的;地中海沿岸的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 virtues | |
美德( virtue的名词复数 ); 德行; 优点; 长处 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 dispositions | |
安排( disposition的名词复数 ); 倾向; (财产、金钱的)处置; 气质 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 hearsay | |
n.谣传,风闻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 conjecture | |
n./v.推测,猜测 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 narrative | |
n.叙述,故事;adj.叙事的,故事体的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 antiquities | |
n.古老( antiquity的名词复数 );古迹;古人们;古代的风俗习惯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 philological | |
adj.语言学的,文献学的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 maxims | |
n.格言,座右铭( maxim的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 maxim | |
n.格言,箴言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 intrigue | |
vt.激起兴趣,迷住;vi.耍阴谋;n.阴谋,密谋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 Partisanship | |
n. 党派性, 党派偏见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 condemned | |
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 solicitude | |
n.焦虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 recording | |
n.录音,记录 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 disdain | |
n.鄙视,轻视;v.轻视,鄙视,不屑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 oratorical | |
adj.演说的,雄辩的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 inveighed | |
v.猛烈抨击,痛骂,谩骂( inveigh的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 depict | |
vt.描画,描绘;描写,描述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 marvel | |
vi.(at)惊叹vt.感到惊异;n.令人惊异的事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 rhetoric | |
n.修辞学,浮夸之言语 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 poetic | |
adj.富有诗意的,有诗人气质的,善于抒情的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 abounded | |
v.大量存在,充满,富于( abound的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 antiquity | |
n.古老;高龄;古物,古迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 eloquence | |
n.雄辩;口才,修辞 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 poetical | |
adj.似诗人的;诗一般的;韵文的;富有诗意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 elevation | |
n.高度;海拔;高地;上升;提高 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 prosaic | |
adj.单调的,无趣的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 aridity | |
n.干旱,乏味;干燥性;荒芜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 fabulous | |
adj.极好的;极为巨大的;寓言中的,传说中的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 frivolous | |
adj.轻薄的;轻率的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 docile | |
adj.驯服的,易控制的,容易教的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 polemic | |
n.争论,论战 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 narratives | |
记叙文( narrative的名词复数 ); 故事; 叙述; 叙述部分 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 worthy | |
adj.(of)值得的,配得上的;有价值的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 narrated | |
v.故事( narrate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 philologists | |
n.语文学( philology的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 fugitive | |
adj.逃亡的,易逝的;n.逃犯,逃亡者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 patrimony | |
n.世袭财产,继承物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 cult | |
n.异教,邪教;时尚,狂热的崇拜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 ethic | |
n.道德标准,行为准则 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 illuminated | |
adj.被照明的;受启迪的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 epoch | |
n.(新)时代;历元 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 rendering | |
n.表现,描写 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 modernizing | |
使现代化,使适应现代需要( modernize的现在分词 ); 现代化,使用现代方法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 travesty | |
n.歪曲,嘲弄,滑稽化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 sketch | |
n.草图;梗概;素描;v.素描;概述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 interpretations | |
n.解释( interpretation的名词复数 );表演;演绎;理解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 cosmos | |
n.宇宙;秩序,和谐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 orientation | |
n.方向,目标;熟悉,适应,情况介绍 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 discoursing | |
演说(discourse的现在分词形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 barbarians | |
n.野蛮人( barbarian的名词复数 );外国人;粗野的人;无教养的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 repugnance | |
n.嫌恶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 rites | |
仪式,典礼( rite的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 transparent | |
adj.明显的,无疑的;透明的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 analogous | |
adj.相似的;类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 artistic | |
adj.艺术(家)的,美术(家)的;善于艺术创作的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 refinements | |
n.(生活)风雅;精炼( refinement的名词复数 );改良品;细微的改良;优雅或高贵的动作 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 explicit | |
adj.详述的,明确的;坦率的;显然的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 poetically | |
adv.有诗意地,用韵文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 accurately | |
adv.准确地,精确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 synonyms | |
同义词( synonym的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 physiology | |
n.生理学,生理机能 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 precepts | |
n.规诫,戒律,箴言( precept的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 engrossed | |
adj.全神贯注的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 explicitly | |
ad.明确地,显然地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 formulated | |
v.构想出( formulate的过去式和过去分词 );规划;确切地阐述;用公式表示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 maturity | |
n.成熟;完成;(支票、债券等)到期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 binds | |
v.约束( bind的第三人称单数 );装订;捆绑;(用长布条)缠绕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 concord | |
n.和谐;协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 mythologies | |
神话学( mythology的名词复数 ); 神话(总称); 虚构的事实; 错误的观点 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 infinitely | |
adv.无限地,无穷地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 enigma | |
n.谜,谜一样的人或事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 guise | |
n.外表,伪装的姿态 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 doctrines | |
n.教条( doctrine的名词复数 );教义;学说;(政府政策的)正式声明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 temperaments | |
性格( temperament的名词复数 ); (人或动物的)气质; 易冲动; (性情)暴躁 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 infancy | |
n.婴儿期;幼年期;初期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 decrepitude | |
n.衰老;破旧 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 immutable | |
adj.不可改变的,永恒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 providence | |
n.深谋远虑,天道,天意;远见;节约;上帝 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 pious | |
adj.虔诚的;道貌岸然的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 submission | |
n.服从,投降;温顺,谦虚;提出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 vengeance | |
n.报复,报仇,复仇 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 uncertainty | |
n.易变,靠不住,不确知,不确定的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 confession | |
n.自白,供认,承认 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 inundates | |
v.淹没( inundate的第三人称单数 );(洪水般地)涌来;充满;给予或交予(太多事物)使难以应付 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 professing | |
声称( profess的现在分词 ); 宣称; 公开表明; 信奉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 austere | |
adj.艰苦的;朴素的,朴实无华的;严峻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 victorious | |
adj.胜利的,得胜的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 lament | |
n.悲叹,悔恨,恸哭;v.哀悼,悔恨,悲叹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141 corruption | |
n.腐败,堕落,贪污 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142 trampled | |
踩( trample的过去式和过去分词 ); 践踏; 无视; 侵犯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143 triumphant | |
adj.胜利的,成功的;狂欢的,喜悦的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144 melancholy | |
n.忧郁,愁思;adj.令人感伤(沮丧)的,忧郁的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145 meditations | |
默想( meditation的名词复数 ); 默念; 沉思; 冥想 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146 monarchies | |
n. 君主政体, 君主国, 君主政治 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147 outspoken | |
adj.直言无讳的,坦率的,坦白无隐的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148 pessimism | |
n.悲观者,悲观主义者,厌世者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149 turbulence | |
n.喧嚣,狂暴,骚乱,湍流 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151 undertaking | |
n.保证,许诺,事业 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
152 inert | |
adj.无活动能力的,惰性的;迟钝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
153 grandiose | |
adj.宏伟的,宏大的,堂皇的,铺张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
154 prologue | |
n.开场白,序言;开端,序幕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
155 foretell | |
v.预言,预告,预示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
156 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
157 contradictory | |
adj.反驳的,反对的,抗辩的;n.正反对,矛盾对立 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
158 unity | |
n.团结,联合,统一;和睦,协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
159 penetrated | |
adj. 击穿的,鞭辟入里的 动词penetrate的过去式和过去分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
160 deception | |
n.欺骗,欺诈;骗局,诡计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
161 incapable | |
adj.无能力的,不能做某事的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
162 conformity | |
n.一致,遵从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
163 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
164 minor | |
adj.较小(少)的,较次要的;n.辅修学科;vi.辅修 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
165 memorable | |
adj.值得回忆的,难忘的,特别的,显著的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
166 adorns | |
装饰,佩带( adorn的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
167 mingling | |
adj.混合的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
168 orations | |
n.(正式仪式中的)演说,演讲( oration的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
169 perversion | |
n.曲解;堕落;反常 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
170 vigilant | |
adj.警觉的,警戒的,警惕的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
171 dispense | |
vt.分配,分发;配(药),发(药);实施 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
172 metaphor | |
n.隐喻,暗喻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
173 megalopolis | |
n.特大城市 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
174 purgatory | |
n.炼狱;苦难;adj.净化的,清洗的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
175 envisage | |
v.想象,设想,展望,正视 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
176 consign | |
vt.寄售(货品),托运,交托,委托 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
177 limbo | |
n.地狱的边缘;监狱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
178 touching | |
adj.动人的,使人感伤的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |