Now, as a matter of fact, these relations are in a very unsettled condition to-day. Public order is unstable7, revolutions are frequent, suffering is excessive. Are we to lay the blame upon public institutions? They are rather an effect than a cause. In order to understand the present condition it is necessary to grasp the law of the general evolution of humanity, and in particular that of European Society. It then320 becomes apparent that the actual disturbances8 proceed from the great conflict inaugurated by the French revolution. This conflict is still going on. The old régime has not yet quite disappeared, and the régime which is to take its place is not yet organised. The struggle is prolonged between the theologico-metaphysical spirit and the positive spirit, between revealed belief which is becoming weaker and demonstrated belief which is being formed, and finally between the old economic landmarks11 and an industrial activity whose laws have not yet been discovered.
The relations between masters and workmen are at the present time “anarchical.” The advance of industry, as it grows, oppresses the majority of those whose co-operation in it is indispensable. And the ever more strongly marked division between “brains and hands” is far more due to the political incapacity, the social thoughtlessness, and especially to the blind selfishness of the masters than to the inordinate12 demands of the workmen.333 The capitalists have not dreamt of organising a liberal education for the people to defend it against the seductions of the revolutionary propaganda. They seem to fear that the people should receive instruction. As far as they can, they take the place of the ancient chiefs whose social rank they covet13. But they do not inherit their generosity14. They do not understand that “noblesse oblige.” In this way the great masters of industry too often tend to utilise their political influence to the detriment15 of the public, to appropriate important monopolies and to take the advantage of the power of capital to make the claims of the masters predominate over those of the workers, without any regard for equity16, since the right of coalition17 which is allowed to the former is refused to the latter.
Comte saw the bourgeoisie at work during Louis-Philippe’s reign18, and he passes severe judgment19 upon it. Its political321 conceptions, he says, refer not to the aim and exercise of power, but especially to its possession. It regards the revolution as terminated by the establishment of the parliamentary régime, whereas this is only an “equivocal halting place.” A complete social reorganisation is not less feared by this middle class than by the old upper classes. Although filled with the critical spirit of the XVIII. century, even under a Republican form it would prolong a system of theological hypocrisy21, by means of which the respectful submission22 of the masses is insured, while no strict duty is imposed upon the leaders.334 This is hard upon the proletariat, whose condition is far from improving. It “establishes dungeons23 for those who ask for bread.”335 It believes that these millions of men will be able to remain indefinitely “encamped” in modern society without being properly settled in it with definite and respected rights.336 The capital which it holds in its hands, after having been an instrument of emancipation24, has become one of oppression. It is thus that, by a paradox25 difficult to uphold, the invention of machinery26, which a priori, one would be led to believe, would soften27 the condition of the proletariat, has, on the contrary, been a new cause of suffering to them, and has made their lot a doubly hard one.337
Here, in brief, we have a formidable indictment28 against the middle classes, and in particular against the political economy which has nourished them. Comte has in view sometimes the classical economists29 of the end of the XVIII. century, sometimes their orthodox successors in the XIX. Those of the XVIII. he regards as having collaborated30 in the great revolutionary work. They took part in the diffusion31 of critical doctrines32 and of negative philosophy. In this capacity they have, no doubt, rendered certain services. They contributed to the decomposition34 of the old régime. Political economy322 had succeeded in convincing the governments themselves of their unfitness to direct the commercial and industrial movement.338
The affinities35 between the philosophers and the economists of the XVIII. century are evident enough: is it necessary to recall the spirit of “individualism” of the economists, and their characteristic tendency to restrict the functions of government as much as possible? Despite the efforts of a great number among them, conservatives by temperament36 or by political tendencies, the logical consequences of their principles were bound to come to light. Thus “the superfluity of all regular moral teaching, the suppression of all official encouragement of science and the fine arts; even the recent attacks against the fundamental institution of property find their origin in economical metaphysics.” It was with this doctrine33 as with the other parts of negative philosophy; after having accomplished37 its work of destruction, it sought to transform its critical principles into organic ones, without realising that this amounted to repudiating38 beforehand any positive organisation20.
The famous formula, “Laissez faire, laissez passer,” is no more a real principle in political economy than liberty itself is one in politics properly so-called. Comte vigorously opposes the dogma of non-intervention. Because in some particular and secondary cases political economy has ascertained39 “the natural tendencies of societies in the direction of a certain necessary order, it concluded from this that any special institution is useless.” But this order is extremely imperfect. The knowledge of sociological laws will give us the power of improving it, as we already do in the case of medicine and surgery. Merely to admit the degree of order which is spontaneously established in practice is equivalent to “a solemn dismissal in the case of every difficulty which arises.” Look at the social crisis brought about by the323 development of machinery. In reply to the just and urgent claims of the workmen suddenly deprived of their means of livelihood41, and unable in a day to find another, our economists can only repeat, “with merciless pedantry,” their barren aphorism42 about absolute industrial liberty. To all complaints they dare to answer that it is a question of time! And this to men who require food to-day! “Such a theory proclaims its own social impotence.”339
And so neither is political economy a science yet, nor, so far, are economists men of science. Originally being nearly all barristers or men of letters, they were strangers to the idea of scientific observation, to the precise notion of a natural law, and finally to the sense of what constitutes a demonstration43. If we make an exception of Adam Smith and of a few others, how could they apply the positive method which they did not know to the most difficult cases of analysis? Destutt de Tracy placed political economy between logic10 and ethics. And this was not without reason: for it is nearer to metaphysics than to positive science. In it, work preserves its personal character, schools contend with each other, the discussions as to the elementary notions of value, of utility, etc., savour of scholasticism. The very idea of studying economical phenomena44 separately is not scientific, since the various “social series” are interdependent, and since in sociology more particular laws depend upon more general laws.340 There is no scientific study of economical facts unless we first look at them from the sociological point of view. We can no more isolate45 the laws which regulate the material existence of societies than we can describe man as an essentially46 calculating being, only actuated by the motive47 of personal interest.
The same objections naturally hold good against the adversaries48 of the economists, since, in general, socialists49 and communists have confined themselves to an analogous324 conception of their science. However, while criticising them, Comte recognises the fact that they have established some truths. Everything they say is not false. Thus, they justly claim the right for the government to intervene in economical relations. And, if it be absurd to wish to abolish private property, as certain sects51 demanded, it is very true that property is of a social nature, and that it is necessary to regulate it.341 To endow it with an absolute character is, says Comte, an “anti-social” theory. No property can be created, nor even transmitted, by its mere40 possessor without the concurrence53 of society. Thus always and everywhere the community has intervened in the exercise of the right of property. The tax makes the public a partner in every private fortune.
In discussing the essential problems of property, the communists (whom Comte confuses with the socialists), to-day render an important service. The very dangers called forth54 by the solution they propose concur52 in fixing the general attention upon this great subject, “without which the metaphysical empiricism and the aristocratic selfishness of the leading classes would cause it to be set aside or disdained55.” Merely to state the problem without the solution with which the communists associate it, would not suffice. Our weak intellect does not fasten upon a question for long, unless a reply to it, be it true or false, which we must accept or reject is forthcoming at the same time. Moreover, are the communist “aberrations” more useless, and at bottom, more dangerous than the current illusion according to which the Revolution is ended by the establishment of the parliamentary régime?342
But, this being admitted the innovating56 schools have all fallen into grave mistakes. In general, being devoid57 of the historic sense, and on the other hand, ignoring the325 principles of social statics, they do not see that man’s action upon social phenomena is only usefully exercised within certain limits. The idea that a revolution can, in a moment, transform the régime of property and all the social conditions which depend upon it is destined58 to disappear, when the “positive mode of thought” shall have extended to the social phenomena in the same way as it has to all others. Then the “extravagant proposals” of the socialists will find no adherents59, and the demand for what is recognised as impossible will no longer be made by anyone.343
Finally, Comte reproaches communism with its tendency to restrain individuality. This objection, coming from him, is remarkable60, for it has very often been made in his own case. As an organiser of despotism, John Stuart Mill has compared him to Ignatius of Loyola. But Comte reminds us that, according to him, the collective organism, or society, differs from the individual organisms, or living beings, by the fact that in it the elements live an independent life. The problem consists in conciliating, as much as possible, this free division with the convergence of the activities. Neither of the two must be sacrificed to the other. To restrain individualities would tend to destroy the dignity of man by doing away with his responsibility, while the want of independence, and the subjection to a community indifferent to him would make life intolerable. “Such is the immense danger of all utopias which sacrifice real liberty to an anarchical equality, or even to an exaggerated fraternity.”344 On this point, positive philosophy on its own account takes up again the “decisive criticism” of communism made by our economists.
326
II.
Positive philosophy does not confine itself to refuting the orthodox economists and the socialists by the help of their own arguments. In its turn it takes up all the questions raised by them, and, for their solution, takes its stand upon the results obtained by sociology.
In the first place it states the problem of “social reorganisation” in its most general form. Socialists, in the same way as their adversaries, are only concerned with riches as if they were the only ill-divided and ill-administered social forces. But there are others. The reform of economical conditions depends, in conclusion, upon that of morals. Before all things then we must “reorganise” morals. We must determine the rights and mutual duties of citizens, and inspire everyone with the feeling of his duty and with respect for the rights of others.
The two ideas of right and of duty are not dealt with by Comte in the same manner. He accepts the idea of duty without subjecting it to a special criticism. Duty is the rule of action prescribed to each one both by feeling and by reason. It is our duty to do what we recognise as most suitable to our individual and social nature. On the contrary, the idea of right “disappears” in the positive state. The word “right” must be removed from political language, in the same way as the word “cause” is from philosophical61 language. They are two metaphysical notions. Everyone has duties, and towards all. No one has any right properly so-called. “The idea of right is as false as it is immoral62, because it presupposes an absolute individuality.”345
These formul? called forth strong protests, particularly from M. Renouvier and his disciples63. Indeed, in the constitution of civil society, they appear to neglect justice327 entirely64, to establish the relations between men merely upon charity and feeling. However, if we look into it closely, Comte’s thought as is often the case, has been forced and warped65, by its expression. But the comparison between the ideas of right and of cause suggested by him, satisfactorily throws a light upon his meaning.
Positive science has given up the search after causes, in order to confine itself to establishing the invariable relations between phenomena. But these relations correspond to what was formerly66 called causal action. They represent what was real in this supposed action. The only difference—but it is important—consists in the fact that the human mind has forsaken67 the absolute point of view for the relative one, and is henceforth content to establish the connection between phenomena, without imagining “connecting entities68” according to Malebranche’s strong expression.
The idea of right has gone through an analogous50 transformation69. In the same way as the idea of cause, it was theological for a long time, and then metaphysical. In antiquity70 it was closely allied71 to religion. In modern times the rights of peoples, and even the rights of individuals, are conceived according to the ancient standard of the rights of princes and masters. But, having become established by triumphing over the rights of princes, the rights of peoples and individuals ultimately rest, as they did, upon a supernatural and mystical basis. The rights which every citizen claims are the change in small coin of the absolute right formerly possessed72 by the sovereign who represented the whole nation. Having become metaphysical in the XVIII. century, the idea of absolute, intangible, indefeasible right, which attaches to the human person, has been most useful for the decomposition of the old régime. But, once this work has been accomplished, it cannot be made use of in the work of reorganisation any more than the other metaphysical principles. Positive philosophy328 admits nothing absolute. Everything in society is at once subject to conditions, and places conditions upon all things. Nothing is unconditional73; and sociology teaches that we must go not from the individual to society, but from society to the individual.
In consequence, here again we must give up endeavouring to transform a critical principle into an organic one. Undoubtedly74 rights will remain, as the constant connections between phenomena subsist75. But we shall cease to base these rights upon a metaphysical conception of human nature, in the same way as we have ceased to refer the connections between phenomena to metaphysical entities called causes. Instead of making individual duties consist in the respect of universal rights, we shall conceive inversely76 the rights of each one as the result of the duties of others towards him. In a word, duty is established before right. This principle is of the highest importance in Comte’s eyes. In it he sees an expression and a proof of the predominance of the positive over the metaphysical spirit, and of the subordination of politics to ethics. He likes to say that “the consideration of duty is bound up with the spirit of the whole.” On the contrary, the consideration of right, if it be conceived as absolute, leads to a denial of all government and of all social organisation.
The new philosophy will tend more and more to replace “the vague and stormy discussion of rights, by the calm and strict determination of respective duties.” Henceforth, the problem raised by the communists assumes a new aspect. That there should be powerful industrial masters is only an evil if they use their power to oppress the men who depend upon them. It is a good thing, on the contrary, if these masters know and fulfil their duties. It is of little consequence to popular interests in whose hands capital is accumulated, so long as the use made of it is beneficial to the social329 masses.346 Now this essential condition “depends far more upon moral than upon political measures.” The latter can undoubtedly prevent the accumulation of riches in a small number of hands, at the risk of paralysing industrial activity. But these “tyrannical” proceedings77 would be far less efficacious than the universal reproof78 inflicted79 by positive ethics upon a selfish use of the riches possessed. The reproof would be all the more irresistible80, because of the fact that the very people who would have to submit to it could not challenge its principle, inculcated in all by the common moral education.” It is thus that in the Middle Ages, excommunication was not less feared by the princes who incurred81 it than it was by the peoples who witnessed it.
Once common education was established, under the direction of the spiritual power, the tyranny of the capitalist class would be no more to be feared. Rich men would consider themselves as the moral guardians82 of public capital. It is not here a question of charity. Those who possess will have the “duty” of securing, first, education and then work for all.
These ideas seem perhaps paradoxical and chimerical83. But, says Comte, this is because modern society has not yet got its system of morality. Industrial relations which have become immensely developed in it are abandoned to a dangerous empiricism, instead of being systematised according to moral laws. War, more or less openly declared, alone regulates the relations between capital and labour. In a normal state of humanity these relations, on the contrary, are “organised.” Strength does not generate oppression. Every citizen is a “public functionary,” whose well-defined functions determine at once his obligations and his claims (that is to say his rights). Property is a function like any other, and not a privilege. It serves for the formation and administration of capital by means of which each generation330 prepares the work of the next. Those who hold it must not turn it from its public use to their own individual advantage.347
In the same way as the capitalists, the workers are public functionaries84, and they perform a no less important service. Independently of their salary, they are deserving social gratitude. Our customs already admit of this feeling in the case of the liberal professions in which the salary does not dispense85 with gratitude. This feeling will have to be extended to all work which contributes to the common weal. The service of humanity, says Comte, is a gratuitous86 one. The salary, whatever it may be, only pays for the material part in every office. It serves to repair the consumption demanded by the organ and the function. As to the essence of service itself it allows of no other reward than the very satisfaction of performing it, and the gratitude which it arouses.348
Consequently in a “truly organised” society (note this expression which M. de Bonald often uses), the vulgar distinction between public and private functionaries is destined to disappear. As, in an army, even the private soldier has his own dignity which comes from the close solidarity87 of the military organisation, and from this fact, that all share the same honour in it; so, when positive education has made evident to all the part played by each one in the social work, professions which are humblest to-day will become ennobled.349 The industrial régime of to-day, which shows us little else than the conflict of rival egoisms, is an anarchical régime, or, to put it better, an “absence of régime.”
Modern society has not yet got its morals. It will form them gradually, in the same way as military society did. Military life, more than any other, is ruled by the predominating selfish inclinations88. Nevertheless, as it could only be331 developed by the spirit of union, this condition alone sufficed for it to determine admirable devotion.350 Why should it not be the same in industrial life which rests upon the peaceful and constructing instinct? Otherwise, if the present “anarchy” of morals were to last, modern society would remain below the level of the Middle Ages, which really was organised by its spiritual power. It would even be below the level of military societies. What would be the use of substituting monopoly to conquest, and a despotism based upon the right of the richest to the despotism resting upon the right of the strongest?351
Everything then depends upon the common moral education, which itself depends upon the establishment of a spiritual power. The superiority of the positive doctrine lies in the fact that it has restored this power. The innovating schools all wish to secure normal education and regular work for the proletariat. But they want both at once, or work before education. Positivism wishes to organise9 education first.352
Naturally, in positive education duties will be presented in their social aspect. Thus the elementary virtues89 of temperance, of chastity, etc., are recommended by positive morality;—but not from the point of view of their usefulness to the individual. Even if “an exceptionally constituted nature should shield the individual from the consequences of intemperance90 or debauchery,” soberness and continence would be no less strictly91 required of him as being indispensable for the fulfilment of his social duties.353 In the same way, the object of domestic morality is not to form “a selfishness shared by several,” but to develop the sympathetic affections which, from the family will gradually extend to the social group, and then to humanity. The principle is to get man into the habit of subjecting himself to humanity, even in his smallest actions, and in all his thoughts.332 Once this point is reached, modern society will spontaneously become organised and the positive régime will of itself be established.
点击收听单词发音
1 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 ethics | |
n.伦理学;伦理观,道德标准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 gratitude | |
adj.感激,感谢 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 civic | |
adj.城市的,都市的,市民的,公民的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 mutual | |
adj.相互的,彼此的;共同的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 unstable | |
adj.不稳定的,易变的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 disturbances | |
n.骚乱( disturbance的名词复数 );打扰;困扰;障碍 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 organise | |
vt.组织,安排,筹办 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 logic | |
n.逻辑(学);逻辑性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 landmarks | |
n.陆标( landmark的名词复数 );目标;(标志重要阶段的)里程碑 ~ (in sth);有历史意义的建筑物(或遗址) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 inordinate | |
adj.无节制的;过度的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 covet | |
vt.垂涎;贪图(尤指属于他人的东西) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 generosity | |
n.大度,慷慨,慷慨的行为 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 detriment | |
n.损害;损害物,造成损害的根源 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 equity | |
n.公正,公平,(无固定利息的)股票 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 coalition | |
n.结合体,同盟,结合,联合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 reign | |
n.统治时期,统治,支配,盛行;v.占优势 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 judgment | |
n.审判;判断力,识别力,看法,意见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 organisation | |
n.组织,安排,团体,有机休 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 hypocrisy | |
n.伪善,虚伪 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 submission | |
n.服从,投降;温顺,谦虚;提出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 dungeons | |
n.地牢( dungeon的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 emancipation | |
n.(从束缚、支配下)解放 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 paradox | |
n.似乎矛盾却正确的说法;自相矛盾的人(物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 machinery | |
n.(总称)机械,机器;机构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 soften | |
v.(使)变柔软;(使)变柔和 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 indictment | |
n.起诉;诉状 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 economists | |
n.经济学家,经济专家( economist的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 collaborated | |
合作( collaborate的过去式和过去分词 ); 勾结叛国 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 diffusion | |
n.流布;普及;散漫 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 doctrines | |
n.教条( doctrine的名词复数 );教义;学说;(政府政策的)正式声明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 decomposition | |
n. 分解, 腐烂, 崩溃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 affinities | |
n.密切关系( affinity的名词复数 );亲近;(生性)喜爱;类同 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 temperament | |
n.气质,性格,性情 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 accomplished | |
adj.有才艺的;有造诣的;达到了的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 repudiating | |
v.(正式地)否认( repudiate的现在分词 );拒绝接受;拒绝与…往来;拒不履行(法律义务) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 ascertained | |
v.弄清,确定,查明( ascertain的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 livelihood | |
n.生计,谋生之道 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 aphorism | |
n.格言,警语 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 demonstration | |
n.表明,示范,论证,示威 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 isolate | |
vt.使孤立,隔离 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 adversaries | |
n.对手,敌手( adversary的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 socialists | |
社会主义者( socialist的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 analogous | |
adj.相似的;类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 sects | |
n.宗派,教派( sect的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 concur | |
v.同意,意见一致,互助,同时发生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 concurrence | |
n.同意;并发 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 disdained | |
鄙视( disdain的过去式和过去分词 ); 不屑于做,不愿意做 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 innovating | |
v.改革,创新( innovate的现在分词 );引入(新事物、思想或方法), | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 devoid | |
adj.全无的,缺乏的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 adherents | |
n.支持者,拥护者( adherent的名词复数 );党羽;徒子徒孙 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 remarkable | |
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 immoral | |
adj.不道德的,淫荡的,荒淫的,有伤风化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 disciples | |
n.信徒( disciple的名词复数 );门徒;耶稣的信徒;(尤指)耶稣十二门徒之一 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 warped | |
adj.反常的;乖戾的;(变)弯曲的;变形的v.弄弯,变歪( warp的过去式和过去分词 );使(行为等)不合情理,使乖戾, | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 formerly | |
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 Forsaken | |
adj. 被遗忘的, 被抛弃的 动词forsake的过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 entities | |
实体对像; 实体,独立存在体,实际存在物( entity的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 transformation | |
n.变化;改造;转变 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 antiquity | |
n.古老;高龄;古物,古迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 allied | |
adj.协约国的;同盟国的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 unconditional | |
adj.无条件的,无限制的,绝对的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 undoubtedly | |
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 subsist | |
vi.生存,存在,供养 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 inversely | |
adj.相反的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 proceedings | |
n.进程,过程,议程;诉讼(程序);公报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 reproof | |
n.斥责,责备 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 inflicted | |
把…强加给,使承受,遭受( inflict的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 irresistible | |
adj.非常诱人的,无法拒绝的,无法抗拒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 incurred | |
[医]招致的,遭受的; incur的过去式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 guardians | |
监护人( guardian的名词复数 ); 保护者,维护者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 chimerical | |
adj.荒诞不经的,梦幻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 functionaries | |
n.公职人员,官员( functionary的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 dispense | |
vt.分配,分发;配(药),发(药);实施 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 gratuitous | |
adj.无偿的,免费的;无缘无故的,不必要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 solidarity | |
n.团结;休戚相关 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 inclinations | |
倾向( inclination的名词复数 ); 倾斜; 爱好; 斜坡 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 virtues | |
美德( virtue的名词复数 ); 德行; 优点; 长处 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 intemperance | |
n.放纵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |