Now, it is clear that the book with the most mysterious, startling, or suggestive title, will always stand the best chance of being purchased by those who have no other criteria6 to guide them in their choice than the aspect of a title-page; and this explains why “Thus Spake Zarathustra” is almost always the first and often the only one of Nietzsche’s books that falls into the hands of the uninitiated.
The title suggests all kinds of mysteries; a glance at the chapter-headings quickly confirms the suspicions already aroused, and the sub-title: “A Book for All and None”, generally succeeds in dissipating the last doubts the prospective7 purchaser may entertain concerning his fitness for the book or its fitness for him. And what happens?
“Thus Spake Zarathustra” is taken home; the reader, who perchance may know no more concerning Nietzsche than a magazine article has told him, tries to read it and, understanding less than half he reads, probably never gets further than the second or third part,—and then only to feel convinced that Nietzsche himself was “rather hazy” as to what he was talking about. Such chapters as “The Child with the Mirror”, “In the Happy Isles”, “The Grave-Song,” “Immaculate Perception,” “The Stillest Hour”, “The Seven Seals”, and many others, are almost utterly8 devoid9 of meaning to all those who do not know something of Nietzsche’s life, his aims and his friendships.
As a matter of fact, “Thus Spake Zarathustra”, though it is unquestionably Nietzsche’s opus magnum, is by no means the first of Nietzsche’s works that the beginner ought to undertake to read. The author himself refers to it as the deepest work ever offered to the German public, and elsewhere speaks of his other writings as being necessary for the understanding of it. But when it is remembered that in Zarathustra we not only have the history of his most intimate experiences, friendships, feuds10, disappointments, triumphs and the like, but that the very form in which they are narrated11 is one which tends rather to obscure than to throw light upon them, the difficulties which meet the reader who starts quite unprepared will be seen to be really formidable.
Zarathustra, then,—this shadowy, allegorical personality, speaking in allegories and parables12, and at times not even refraining from relating his own dreams—is a figure we can understand but very imperfectly if we have no knowledge of his creator and counterpart, Friedrich Nietzsche; and it were therefore well, previous to our study of the more abstruse13 parts of this book, if we were to turn to some authoritative14 book on Nietzsche’s life and works and to read all that is there said on the subject. Those who can read German will find an excellent guide, in this respect, in Frau Foerster-Nietzsche’s exhaustive and highly interesting biography of her brother: “Das Leben Friedrich Nietzsche’s” (published by Naumann); while the works of Deussen, Raoul Richter, and Baroness16 Isabelle von Unger-Sternberg, will be found to throw useful and necessary light upon many questions which it would be difficult for a sister to touch upon.
In regard to the actual philosophical17 views expounded18 in this work, there is an excellent way of clearing up any difficulties they may present, and that is by an appeal to Nietzsche’s other works. Again and again, of course, he will be found to express himself so clearly that all reference to his other writings may be dispensed19 with; but where this is not the case, the advice he himself gives is after all the best to be followed here, viz.:—to regard such works as: “Joyful Science”, “Beyond Good and Evil”, “The Genealogy21 of Morals”, “The Twilight22 of the Idols”, “The Antichrist”, “The Will to Power”, etc., etc., as the necessary preparation for “Thus Spake Zarathustra”.
These directions, though they are by no means simple to carry out, seem at least to possess the quality of definiteness and straightforwardness23. “Follow them and all will be clear,” I seem to imply. But I regret to say that this is not really the case. For my experience tells me that even after the above directions have been followed with the greatest possible zeal24, the student will still halt in perplexity before certain passages in the book before us, and wonder what they mean. Now, it is with the view of giving a little additional help to all those who find themselves in this position that I proceed to put forth25 my own personal interpretation26 of the more abstruse passages in this work.
In offering this little commentary to the Nietzsche student, I should like it to be understood that I make no claim as to its infallibility or indispensability. It represents but an attempt on my part—a very feeble one perhaps—to give the reader what little help I can in surmounting27 difficulties which a long study of Nietzsche’s life and works has enabled me, partially28 I hope, to overcome.
...
Perhaps it would be as well to start out with a broad and rapid sketch29 of Nietzsche as a writer on Morals, Evolution, and Sociology, so that the reader may be prepared to pick out for himself, so to speak, all passages in this work bearing in any way upon Nietzsche’s views in those three important branches of knowledge.
(A.) Nietzsche and Morality.
In morality, Nietzsche starts out by adopting the position of the relativist. He says there are no absolute values “good” and “evil”; these are mere30 means adopted by all in order to acquire power to maintain their place in the world, or to become supreme31. It is the lion’s good to devour32 an antelope33. It is the dead-leaf butterfly’s good to tell a foe15 a falsehood. For when the dead-leaf butterfly is in danger, it clings to the side of a twig34, and what it says to its foe is practically this: “I am not a butterfly, I am a dead leaf, and can be of no use to thee.” This is a lie which is good to the butterfly, for it preserves it. In nature every species of organic being instinctively35 adopts and practises those acts which most conduce to the prevalence or supremacy36 of its kind. Once the most favourable37 order of conduct is found, proved efficient and established, it becomes the ruling morality of the species that adopts it and bears them along to victory. All species must not and cannot value alike, for what is the lion’s good is the antelope’s evil and vice20 versa.
Concepts of good and evil are therefore, in their origin, merely a means to an end, they are expedients39 for acquiring power.
Applying this principle to mankind, Nietzsche attacked Christian40 moral values. He declared them to be, like all other morals, merely an expedient38 for protecting a certain type of man. In the case of Christianity this type was, according to Nietzsche, a low one.
Conflicting moral codes have been no more than the conflicting weapons of different classes of men; for in mankind there is a continual war between the powerful, the noble, the strong, and the well-constituted on the one side, and the impotent, the mean, the weak, and the ill-constituted on the other. The war is a war of moral principles. The morality of the powerful class, Nietzsche calls NOBLE- or MASTER-MORALITY; that of the weak and subordinate class he calls SLAVE-MORALITY. In the first morality it is the eagle which, looking down upon a browsing41 lamb, contends that “eating lamb is good.” In the second, the slave-morality, it is the lamb which, looking up from the sward, bleats42 dissentingly: “Eating lamb is evil.”
(B.) The Master- and Slave-Morality Compared.
The first morality is active, creative, Dionysian. The second is passive, defensive43,—to it belongs the “struggle for existence.”
Where attempts have not been made to reconcile the two moralities, they may be described as follows:—All is GOOD in the noble morality which proceeds from strength, power, health, well-constitutedness, happiness, and awfulness; for, the motive2 force behind the people practising it is “the struggle for power.” The antithesis44 “good and bad” to this first class means the same as “noble” and “despicable.” “Bad” in the master-morality must be applied45 to the coward, to all acts that spring from weakness, to the man with “an eye to the main chance,” who would forsake46 everything in order to live.
With the second, the slave-morality, the case is different. There, inasmuch as the community is an oppressed, suffering, unemancipated, and weary one, all THAT will be held to be good which alleviates47 the state of suffering. Pity, the obliging hand, the warm heart, patience, industry, and humility—these are unquestionably the qualities we shall here find flooded with the light of approval and admiration48; because they are the most USEFUL qualities—; they make life endurable, they are of assistance in the “struggle for existence” which is the motive force behind the people practising this morality. To this class, all that is AWFUL is bad, in fact it is THE evil par4 excellence49. Strength, health, superabundance of animal spirits and power, are regarded with hate, suspicion, and fear by the subordinate class.
Now Nietzsche believed that the first or the noble-morality conduced to an ascent50 in the line of life; because it was creative and active. On the other hand, he believed that the second or slave-morality, where it became paramount51, led to degeneration, because it was passive and defensive, wanting merely to keep those who practised it alive. Hence his earnest advocacy of noble-morality.
(C.) Nietzsche and Evolution.
Nietzsche as an evolutionist I shall have occasion to define and discuss in the course of these notes (see Notes on Chapter LVI., par.10, and on Chapter LVII.). For the present let it suffice for us to know that he accepted the “Development Hypothesis” as an explanation of the origin of species: but he did not halt where most naturalists52 have halted. He by no means regarded man as the highest possible being which evolution could arrive at; for though his physical development may have reached its limit, this is not the case with his mental or spiritual attributes. If the process be a fact; if things have BECOME what they are, then, he contends, we may describe no limit to man’s aspirations53. If he struggled up from barbarism, and still more remotely from the lower Primates54, his ideal should be to surpass man himself and reach Superman (see especially the Prologue).
(D.) Nietzsche and Sociology.
Nietzsche as a sociologist55 aims at an aristocratic arrangement of society. He would have us rear an ideal race. Honest and truthful56 in intellectual matters, he could not even think that men are equal. “With these preachers of equality will I not be mixed up and confounded. For thus speaketh justice unto ME: ‘Men are not equal.’” He sees precisely in this inequality a purpose to be served, a condition to be exploited. “Every elevation57 of the type ‘man,’” he writes in “Beyond Good and Evil”, “has hitherto been the work of an aristocratic society—and so will it always be—a society believing in a long scale of gradations of rank and differences of worth among human beings.”
Those who are sufficiently58 interested to desire to read his own detailed59 account of the society he would fain establish, will find an excellent passage in Aphorism60 57 of “The Antichrist”.
...
点击收听单词发音
1 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 par | |
n.标准,票面价值,平均数量;adj.票面的,平常的,标准的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 sensational | |
adj.使人感动的,非常好的,轰动的,耸人听闻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 criteria | |
n.标准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 prospective | |
adj.预期的,未来的,前瞻性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 utterly | |
adv.完全地,绝对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 devoid | |
adj.全无的,缺乏的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 feuds | |
n.长期不和,世仇( feud的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 narrated | |
v.故事( narrate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 parables | |
n.(圣经中的)寓言故事( parable的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 abstruse | |
adj.深奥的,难解的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 authoritative | |
adj.有权威的,可相信的;命令式的;官方的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 foe | |
n.敌人,仇敌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 baroness | |
n.男爵夫人,女男爵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 expounded | |
论述,详细讲解( expound的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 dispensed | |
v.分配( dispense的过去式和过去分词 );施与;配(药) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 genealogy | |
n.家系,宗谱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 twilight | |
n.暮光,黄昏;暮年,晚期,衰落时期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 straightforwardness | |
n.坦白,率直 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 zeal | |
n.热心,热情,热忱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 interpretation | |
n.解释,说明,描述;艺术处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 surmounting | |
战胜( surmount的现在分词 ); 克服(困难); 居于…之上; 在…顶上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 partially | |
adv.部分地,从某些方面讲 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 sketch | |
n.草图;梗概;素描;v.素描;概述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 devour | |
v.吞没;贪婪地注视或谛听,贪读;使着迷 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 antelope | |
n.羚羊;羚羊皮 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 twig | |
n.小树枝,嫩枝;v.理解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 instinctively | |
adv.本能地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 supremacy | |
n.至上;至高权力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 favourable | |
adj.赞成的,称赞的,有利的,良好的,顺利的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 expedient | |
adj.有用的,有利的;n.紧急的办法,权宜之计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 expedients | |
n.应急有效的,权宜之计的( expedient的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 Christian | |
adj.基督教徒的;n.基督教徒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 browsing | |
v.吃草( browse的现在分词 );随意翻阅;(在商店里)随便看看;(在计算机上)浏览信息 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 bleats | |
v.(羊,小牛)叫( bleat的第三人称单数 );哭诉;发出羊叫似的声音;轻声诉说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 defensive | |
adj.防御的;防卫的;防守的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 antithesis | |
n.对立;相对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 forsake | |
vt.遗弃,抛弃;舍弃,放弃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 alleviates | |
减轻,缓解,缓和( alleviate的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 admiration | |
n.钦佩,赞美,羡慕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 excellence | |
n.优秀,杰出,(pl.)优点,美德 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 ascent | |
n.(声望或地位)提高;上升,升高;登高 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 paramount | |
a.最重要的,最高权力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 naturalists | |
n.博物学家( naturalist的名词复数 );(文学艺术的)自然主义者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 aspirations | |
强烈的愿望( aspiration的名词复数 ); 志向; 发送气音; 发 h 音 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 primates | |
primate的复数 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 sociologist | |
n.研究社会学的人,社会学家 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 truthful | |
adj.真实的,说实话的,诚实的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 elevation | |
n.高度;海拔;高地;上升;提高 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 detailed | |
adj.详细的,详尽的,极注意细节的,完全的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 aphorism | |
n.格言,警语 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |