Even the idea of public utility as the final test and standard of morality is derived3 from Beccaria, and the famous expression, ‘the greatest happiness of the greatest number,’ occurs, in capital letters, in the very first page of the ‘Delitti e delle Pene.’[30] Bentham himself fully4 acknowledged this. ‘Priestley was the first,’ he says, ‘unless it was Beccaria, who taught my lips to pronounce this sacred truth: that the[47] greatest happiness of the greatest number is the foundation of morals and happiness.’ And with reference to his idea of the measurable value of different pains and pleasures, he says: ‘It was from Beccaria’s little treatise5 on Crimes and Punishments that I drew, as I well remember, the first hint of this principle, by which the precision and clearness and incontestableness of mathematical calculations are introduced for the first time into the field of morals.’
English philosophy and legislation, therefore, owe enough to Beccaria for his treatise never to be forgotten among us. Standing6, as it does, in reference to law as Bacon’s ‘Novum Organon’ to science, or Descartes’ ‘Principia’ to philosophy, and representing a return to first principles and rejection7 of mere8 precedent9 in the matter of penal laws, it will never fail to gratify those who, with little admiration11 for law in the concrete, can yet find pleasure in studying it in the abstract. Most men will turn readily from a system built up, as our own is, of unintelligible13 distinctions, and based on authority rather than on experience, to a system where no distinctions exist save those which are derived from the nature of things and are founded on the real differences that distinguish the moral actions of mankind.
The first trace of Beccaria’s influence in England appeared in the first edition of Blackstone’s Commentaries, of which the book on the Criminal Laws[48] was published the very next year after the appearance of the Italian treatise. That Blackstone was well acquainted with it is proved by his frequent reference to it in treating of crimes. From Beccaria he argues that the certainty of punishments is more effectual than their severity, and finds it absurd to apply the same punishment to crimes of different malignity14. Blackstone was also the first professional lawyer to find fault with the frequency of capital punishment in England, and to point out as ‘a melancholy15 truth’ the presence of 160 actions in the statute16 book which were felonies without benefit of clergy17.
But there was one great fallacy, pervading18 our whole criminal law, which Blackstone left undetected and untouched. This was, that the severity of punishment must be augmented19 in proportion to the increase of temptation, and that the measure of the guilt21 of a crime lay in the facility with which it might be committed. ‘Among crimes of an equal malignity,’ says Blackstone, ‘those [deserve most punishment, as most injurious] which a man has the most frequent and easy opportunities of committing, which cannot so easily be guarded against as others, and which, therefore, the offender22 has the strongest inducement to commit.’ And on this principle he finds it reasonable, that, while the theft of a pocket-handkerchief should be a capital crime, the theft of a load of hay should only involve transportation.
[49]
There was not an anomaly in our old criminal practice which was not based on this theory—a theory which had, indeed, its precedent in the old Hebrew law that punished more severely23 a theft from a field than a theft from a house; and the first writer who protested against it was Eden, afterwards Lord Auckland, who in 1771 published his ‘Principles of Penal Law,’ one of the best books ever written on the subject. The influence of Beccaria is apparent in Eden’s work, not only by his direct reference to it, but by his spirit of declared opposition24 to the actual practice of the law. Two instances of its tendency will suffice. ‘Imprisonment25, inflicted26 by law as a punishment, is not according to the principles of wise legislation. It sinks useful subjects into burthens on the community, and has always a bad effect on their morals; nor can it communicate the benefit of example, being in its nature secluded27 from the eye of the people.’ And again: ‘Whatever exceeds simple death is mere cruelty. Every step beyond is a trace of ancient barbarity, tending only to distract the attention of the spectators and to lessen28 the solemnity of the example. There is no such thing as vindictive29 justice; the idea is shocking.’
Men of letters as a rule did not speak with this boldness, but in conscious opposition to professional and popular feeling expressed their doubts with a hesitation30 that was almost apologetic. So, for example,[50] Goldsmith could not ‘avoid even questioning the validity of that right which social combinations have assumed of capitally punishing offences of a slight nature.’[31] Strange, that in England such an argument should ever have seemed a daring novelty, a thing to be said tentatively and with reserve!
Lord Kames attacked our criminal law in a still more indirect way, by tracing punishment historically to the revenge of individuals for their private injuries, and by extolling31 the excellence32 of the criminal law of the ancient Egyptians. They, he said, avoided capital punishments as much as possible, preferring others which equally prevented the recommission of crimes. Such punishments effected their end ‘with less harshness and severity than is found in the laws of any other nation, ancient or modern.’[32]
Nothing could be more interesting than Lord Kames’ account of the growth of criminal law, from the rude revenges of savages33 to the legal punishments of civilised States; but it was probably intended by its author less as an historical treatise than as a veiled attack upon the penal system of his country. It is, therefore, a good illustration of the timidity of the Theoretical school against the overwhelming forces of the Practical school of law, which, of course, included[51] the great body of the legal profession; and it is the first sign of an attempt to apply the experience of other countries and times to the improvement of our own jurisprudence.
It certainly should moderate our reverence34 for ancestral wisdom to find even a man like Fielding, the novelist, speaking, in his Charge to the Grand Jury of Middlesex, of the pillory35 and the loss of a man’s ears as ‘an extremely mild’ punishment for a bad case of libel, or declaring our punishments of that time to be ‘the mildest and most void of terror of any other in the known world.’ Yet Fielding recognised several of the true principles of punishment. He attributed the increase of crime to the great abuse of pardons, which, he said, had brought many more men to the gallows36 than they had saved from it. He also advocated the diminution37 of the number of executions, their greater privacy and solemnity, whilst he recommended their following as closely as possible on conviction, that pity for the criminal might be lost in detestation for his crime.[33]
But that the humanity of the speculative38 school of law was not without some influence on public opinion, as well as to a certain extent a reflection of it, is proved by a few abortive39 attempts in Parliament to mitigate40 the severity of our penal code in the latter half of the last century. Even so early as 1752[52] the Commons agreed to commute41 the punishment of felony in certain cases to hard labour in the docks; but the Lords refused their consent, as from that time onward42 for more than eighty years they regularly continued to refuse it to all mitigation of the laws affecting crime. It must ever remain a matter of regret, that the r?le of the House of Lords in the matter of criminal law reform should have continued from 1752 to 1832 to be one of systematic43 and obstinate44 opposition to change, and an opposition which had no justification45 in the general level of national enlightenment.
The chief honour of the earliest attempt at law reform belongs to Sir William Meredith, who in 1770 moved for a committee of inquiry46 into the state of the criminal laws. This committee proposed in its report of the following year the repeal47 of a few Acts which made certain offences capital; and accordingly the Commons in 1772 agreed, that it should no longer be punishable as high treason to make an attempt on the life of a Privy48 Councillor, that desertion of officers or soldiers should no longer be capital, nor the belonging to people who called themselves Egyptians. Some other proposals were negatived, such as a repeal of the hard law of James I. against infanticide; but the House of Lords refused their assent49 even to the slight changes passed by the Commons. ‘It was an innovation, they said, and subversion50 of the law.’[34][53] It is no reproach to Meredith, Burke, and Fox that they ceased to waste their strength against Conservatism such as this. All hope of reform was out of the question; and the most dreadful atrocities52 were suffered or defended. In 1777 a girl of 14 lay in Newgate under sentence to be burnt alive for false coinage, because some whitewashed53 farthings, that were to pass for sixpences, were found on her person; and a reprieve54 only came just as the cart was ready to take her to the stake. Not till 1790 was the law abolished by which women were liable to be burnt publicly for high or petit treason.[35]
But whatever tendency might have been arising in theory or in practice about this time to mitigate the severity of our laws was destined55 to receive a dead check from the publication in 1784 and 1785 respectively of two books which deserve historical recollection. The first was Madan’s ‘Thoughts on Executive Justice,’ in which the author, adopting Beccaria’s principle of the certainty of punishment as the best check on crime, advocated an unflinching carrying out of the laws as they stood. ‘It was,’ says Romilly, ‘a strong and vehement56 censure57 upon the judges and the ministers for their mode of administering the law, and for the frequency of the pardons which they granted. It was very much read, and certainly was followed by the sacrifice of many lives.’
[54]
The year before its publication 51 malefactors were executed in London, the year after 97, whilst not long afterwards was seen the rare spectacle of nearly 20 criminals hung at a time. Romilly was so much shocked at what he considered the folly59 and inhumanity of Madan’s book that he wrote a short tract12 of observations upon it, of which he sent a copy to each of the judges. But it is characteristic of the feeling of that time that only a hundred copies of his tract were sold. It was, however, from that time that Romilly began to make the criminal law his special study, so that to Madan indirectly60 our country owes the efforts of Romilly.
The other book was from a man whom above all others our forefathers61 delighted to honour. This was Archdeacon Paley, who in 1785 published his ‘Moral and Political Philosophy,’ and dedicated62 it to the then Bishop63 of Carlisle. Nor is this fact of the dedication64 immaterial, for the said Bishop was the father of the future Lord Chief Justice Ellenborough, who enjoys the melancholy fame of having been the inveterate65 and successful opponent of nearly every movement made in his time, in favour of the mitigation of our penal laws. The chapter on Crimes and Punishments in Paley and the speeches of Lord Ellenborough on the subject in the House of Lords are, in point of fact, the same thing; so that Paley’s chapter is of distinct historical importance, as the[55] chief cause of the obstruction66 of reform, and as the best expression of the philosophy of his day. If other countries adopted Beccaria’s principles more quickly than our own, it was simply that those principles found no opponents anywhere equal to Archdeacon Paley and his pupil, Lord Ellenborough.
Paley, of course, defended the thing he found established; nor, considering the system he had to defend, did he state the case for it without ingenuity67. He had, indeed, nothing to add to what Blackstone had said regarding punishment, namely, that it was inflicted, not in proportion to the real guilt of an offence, but in proportion to its facility of commission and difficulty of detection. To steal from a shop was not more criminal than to steal from a house, but, as it was more difficult to detect, it was more severely punished. Sheep, horses, and cloth on bleaching-grounds were more exposed to thieves than other kinds of property; therefore their theft required a stronger deterrent68 penalty.
There was only one offence which Paley thought the English law punished too severely, and that was the offence of privately69 stealing from the person. In all other cases he defended the application of the capital penalty. It was, he thought, the peculiar70 merit of the English law that it swept into the net every crime which under any possible circumstance might merit death, whilst it only singled out a few[56] cases in each class of crime for actual punishment; so that whilst few really suffered death, the dread51 and danger of it hung over the crimes of many. The law was not cruel, for it was never meant to be indiscriminately executed, but left a large margin71 for the exercise of mercy.
Paley agreed with Beccaria that the certainty of punishment was of more consequence than its severity. For this reason he recommended ‘undeviating impartiality72 in carrying the laws into execution;’ he blamed the ‘weak timidity’ of juries, leading them to be over-scrupulous about the certainty of their evidence, and protested against the maxim73 that it was better for ten guilty men to escape than for one innocent man to perish. A man who fell by a mistaken sentence might, he argued, be considered as falling for his country, because he was the victim of a system of laws which maintained the safety of the community.
Such was the reasoning which for nearly half a century governed the course of English history, and which for all that time it was a heresy74 to dispute.
Barbarous spectacles were, Paley thought, justly found fault with, as tending to demoralise public feeling. ‘But,’ he continued, ‘if a mode of execution could be devised which would augment20 the horror of the punishment, without offending or impairing75 the public sensibility by cruel or unseemly exhibitions of death, it might add something to the efficacy of[57] example; and by being reserved for a few atrocious crimes might also enlarge the scale of punishment, an addition to which seems wanting, for as the matter remains76 at present you hang a malefactor58 for a simple robbery, and can do no more to the villain77 who has poisoned his father. Something of the sort we have been describing was the proposal, not long since suggested, of casting murderers into a den10 of wild beasts, where they would perish in a manner dreadful to the imagination, yet concealed78 from the view.’ It is interesting after this to learn, that Paley thought torture properly exploded from ‘the mild and cautious system of penal jurisprudence established in this country,’ and that (to do him justice) he urged private persons to be tender in prosecuting79, out of regard for the difficulty of prisoners to obtain an honest means of livelihood80 after their discharge.
Howard’s book on the Lazarettos of Europe appeared four years after Paley’s work. Although it did not deal directly with crimes, it indirectly treated of their connection with punishment. Howard was able to show that whilst in Middlesex alone 467 persons had been executed in nine years, only six had been executed in Amsterdam; that for a hundred years the average number of executions had been one a year at Utrecht and that for twenty-four years there had not even been one there. The inference therefore was that the diminution of punishment had a direct[58] effect in diminishing crime. Howard also advocated the restriction81 of capital punishment to cases of murder, arson82, and burglary; highwaymen, footpads, and habitual83 thieves should, he thought, end their days in a penitentiary84 rather than on the gallows. Even this was a bold proposal, in a state of society yet in bondage85 to Paley.
Something, however, occurred more fatal to the reform of our penal laws than even the philosophy of Paley, and that was the French Revolution. Before 1790 there had been 115 capital offences in France; so that to alter the criminal law in England was to follow a precedent of unpleasant auspices86. Reform not unnaturally87 savoured of revolution, and especially a reform of the penal laws. In 1808 Romilly said he would advise anyone, who desired to realise the mischievous88 effects of the French Revolution in England to attempt some legislative89 reform on humane90 and liberal principles. With bitterness he tells the story of a young nobleman, who, addressing him insolently91 at the bar of the House of Commons, informed him that he for his part was for hanging all criminals. Romilly observed that he supposed he meant punishments should be certain and the laws executed, whatever they were. ‘No, no,’ was the reply, ‘it isn’t that. There is no good done by mercy. They only get worse: I would hang them all up at once.’ And this represented the prevalent[59] opinion. Windham, in a speech against the Shoplifting Bill, inquired, ‘Had not the French Revolution begun with the abolition92 of capital punishment in every case?… Was such a system as this was to be set up without consideration against that of Dr. Paley!’[36]
Romilly’s first idea with respect to the reform of the criminal law was a sufficiently93 humble94 one. It was nothing more than to raise the amount of the value of the property, the theft of which should expose a man to death. Twelvepence, as fixed95 by the statute of Elizabeth, originally signified a much greater theft than it had come to signify after a lapse96 of two centuries. Romilly had at first no idea of removing the death penalty for theft; his only hope was to get it affixed97 to a graver theft than the larceny98 of a shilling. Yet even so he could not bring himself to consult with the judges on the subject of his intended bill, for ‘he had not the least hope they would approve of the measure.’
It was by the advice of Scarlett, Lord Abinger, that he ventured to aim at the repeal of all statutes99 punishing mere theft with death; but, deeming it hopeless to urge their abolition all at once, he resolved to begin with that famous statute of Elizabeth which made it a capital crime to steal a handkerchief or anything else from the person of another which was of the value of a shilling. His bill to effect this[60] passed both Houses the same year it was introduced (1808), in spite of the strong opposition of the great legal dignitaries in either House. The statute was based, said Judge Burton, on the experience of two and a half centuries. The alternative punishment of transportation for seven years, said the Attorney-General, would be too short; it should be for more years than seven, if not for life. If any change of punishment were necessary, said Lord Ellenborough, it should be transportation for life.
Such was legal opinion generally as expressed by its ablest representatives with respect to the due punishment for pocket-picking not a hundred years ago. It is easy now to smile at such errors, and, at the barren waste of wisdom spent in their defence, but what weight after that can be attached, on subjects of the general policy of the law, to the opinion of its chief professors? Can it be too much regretted that Lord Chief Justice Ellenborough should have sacrificed to his own authority, whilst alive, the authority of all judges ever destined to succeed him?
The success which attended Romilly’s Privately Stealing Bill and the failure which attended almost all his other efforts was probably due to the fact that larceny from the person without violence was, as has been said, the one single kind of offence which had Paley’s sanction for ceasing to be capital. But the[61] very success of his first bill was the chief cause of the failure of his subsequent ones. For, capital punishment having been removed for mere pilfering100, prosecutions101 became more frequent, and the opponents of reform were thus able to declare that an increase of theft had been the direct consequence of the abolition of the capital penalty. It was in vain to point out, that the apparent increase of theft was due to the greater readiness of individuals to prosecute102 and of juries to convict, when a verdict of guilt no longer involved death as the consequence.
Romilly also injured his cause by a pamphlet on the criminal law, in which he criticised severely the doctrines103 of Paley. So strongly was this resented, that in 1810 his bill to abolish capital punishment for stealing forty shillings from a dwelling-house did not even pass the Commons, being generally opposed, as it was by Windham, because the maintenance of Paley’s reputation was regarded as a great object of national concern.[37] That is to say, men voted not so much against the bill as against the author of a heresy against Paley.
In those days to steal five shillings’ worth of goods from a shop was a capital offence, and Paley had explained the philosophy of the punishment. It would be tedious to follow the course of Romilly’s bill against this law, called the Shoplifting Act,[62] through the details of its history. Suffice it to say that it passed the Commons in 1810, 1811, 1813, 1816, but was regularly thrown out by the Lords, and only definitely became law many years later. But though the debates on the subject no longer possess the vivid interest that once belonged to them, and are best left to the oblivion that enshrouds them, it is instructive to take just one sample of the eloquence104 and arguments, that once led Lords and Bishops105 captive and expressed the highest legal wisdom obtainable in England.
Lord Ellenborough, on the last day but one of May 1810, appealed to their lordships to pause, before they passed the Shoplifting Bill and gave their assent to the repeal of a law which had so long been held necessary for the security of the public. No one, he insisted, was more disposed than himself to the exercise of clemency106, but there was not the slightest ground for the insinuations of cruelty that had been cast on the administration of the law. If shoplifting did not require the penalty of death, the same rule would have to apply to horse- and sheep-stealing; and, in spite of all that was said in favour of this speculative humanity, they must all agree, that prevention of crime should be the chief object of the law, and that terror alone could prevent the crime in question. Those who were thus speculating in modern legislation urged that punishment should[63] be certain and proportionate; but he could satisfy the House that any attempt to apply a punishment in exact conformity107 to the offence would be perfectly108 ludicrous. He had consulted with the other judges, and they were unanimously of opinion that it would not be expedient109 to remit110 this part of the severity of the criminal law.[38] He therefore entreated111 them to pause.
Need it be said that the House of Lords paused, as they were entreated to do, and that they paused and paused again, in a manner more suggestive of the full stop than the comma, generally out of deference112 to the same authority? Romilly was indignant that so many prelates voted against his bills; but could they have done otherwise, when the best legal authorities in England urged that it would be fatal to vote for them?—when they were gravely told that if a certain bill passed, they would not know whether they stood on their heads or on their feet?
Lord Ellenborough was so hard upon ‘speculative humanity,’ as opposed to real practical common sense, that the speculative school are never likely to forget him. But they owe too much to him not to forgive him; since he is the standing proof, that in matters of the general policy of the law professional opinion is a less trustworthy guide than popular sentiment,[64] and that in questions of law reform it is best to neglect the fossil-wisdom of forgotten judges, and to seek the opinion of Jones round the corner as readily as that of Jones upon the Bench.
A strong feeling against the pillory was aroused by the sentence passed against Lord Cochrane in 1814, by which, for supposed complicity in a plot to raise the price of the Funds, he was condemned113 to a year’s imprisonment, to a fine of 1000l., and to stand in the pillory. A bill for the abolition of the pillory accordingly passed the Commons the very next year, but Lord Ellenborough succeeded again in bringing the Upper House to a pause: the pillory forsooth was as old as 1269; it was spoken of by the old historians; it was not confined to this country, for Du Cange spoke114 of it on the Continent. For these reasons the pillory remained a legal punishment down to the first year of the present reign115.
Yet Lord Ellenborough was one of the best judges known to English history; he was, according to his biographer, a man ‘of gigantic intellect,’ and one of the best classical scholars of his day; and if he erred2, it was with all honesty and goodness of purpose. The same must be said of Lord Chief Justice Tenterden’s opposition to any change in the law of forgery116. His great merits too as a judge are matter of history, yet when the Commons had passed the bill for the abolition of capital punishment for forgery, Lord Tenterden[65] assured the House of Lords that they could not ‘without great danger take away the punishment of death.’ ‘When it was recollected117 how many thousand pounds, and even tens of thousands, might be abstracted from a man by a deep-laid scheme of forgery, he thought that this crime ought to be visited with the utmost extent of punishment which the law then wisely allowed.’ The House of Lords again paused in submission118 to judicial119 authority.
Sir James Mackintosh, who succeeded Romilly as law reformer, in 1820 introduced with success six penal reform bills into the House of Commons; but the Lords assented120 to none of them that were of any practical importance to the country. They agreed, indeed, that it should no longer be a capital offence for an Egyptian to reside one year in the country, or for a man to be found disguised in the Mint, or to injure Westminster Bridge; but they did not agree to remove the capital penalty for such offences as wounding cattle, destroying trees, breaking down the banks of rivers, or sending threatening letters. It was feared that if the punishment were mitigated121, the whole of Lincolnshire might be submerged, whole forests cut down, and whole herds122 destroyed. As to the Shoplifting Bill, they would not let death be abolished for stealing in shops altogether, but only where the value of the theft was under 10l. That seemed the limit of safe concession123.
[66]
Sir Robert Peel, who was the first Ministerial law reformer, succeeded in getting the death penalty repealed124 for several crimes which were practically obsolete125, but forty kinds of forgery alone still remained capital offences.
So great, however, did the changes appear to be, that Sir James Mackintosh declared, towards the close of his life, that it was as if he had lived in two different countries, such was the contrast between the past and the present. Yet Sir James died in the very year that the first Reform Bill passed, and it was not till after that event that any really great progress was made towards ameliorating the penal laws.
It is well known that Lord Tenterden refused ever to sit again in the House of Lords if the Reform Bill became law, and that he predicted that that measure would amount to the political extinction126 of the Upper House. As regards the history of our criminal law Lord Tenterden was right, for the period of long pauses had passed away, and rapid changes were made with but short intervals127 of breathing-time. From the year the Reform Bill passed the school of Beccaria and Bentham achieved rapid successes in England. In 1832 it ceased to be capital to steal a horse or a sheep, in 1833 to break into a house, in 1834 to return prematurely128 from transportation, in 1835 to commit sacrilege or to steal a letter. But[67] even till 1837 there were still 37 capital offences on the statute-book; and now there are only two, murder and treason. Hanging in chains was abolished in 1834; the pillory was wholly abolished in 1837; and the same year Ewart, after many years’ struggle, obtained for prisoners on trial for felony the right (still merely a nominal129 one)[39] of being defended by counsel.
Thus it has come about that, after steady opposition and fierce conflict, English law finds itself at the very point which Johnson and Goldsmith had attained130 a hundred years before; so true is it, as Beccaria has said, that the enlightenment of a nation is always a century in advance of its practice. The victory has conclusively131 been with the ultra-philosophers, as they were once called, with the speculative humanitarians132, for whom good Lord Ellenborough had so honest a contempt. Paley’s philosophy has long since been forgotten, and if it affords any lesson at all, it lies chiefly in a comparison between his gloomy predictions and the actual results of the changes he deprecated. The practical and professional school of law has yielded on all the most important points to the dissolving influence of Beccaria’s treatise; and the growing demand for increasing the security of human life by the institution[68] of a penalty, more effective because more certain, than that at present in force, points to the still further triumph of Beccaria’s principles, likely before long to mark the progress of his influence in England.
点击收听单词发音
1 penal | |
adj.刑罚的;刑法上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 erred | |
犯错误,做错事( err的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 treatise | |
n.专著;(专题)论文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 standing | |
n.持续,地位;adj.永久的,不动的,直立的,不流动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 rejection | |
n.拒绝,被拒,抛弃,被弃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 precedent | |
n.先例,前例;惯例;adj.在前的,在先的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 den | |
n.兽穴;秘密地方;安静的小房间,私室 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 admiration | |
n.钦佩,赞美,羡慕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 tract | |
n.传单,小册子,大片(土地或森林) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 unintelligible | |
adj.无法了解的,难解的,莫明其妙的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 malignity | |
n.极度的恶意,恶毒;(病的)恶性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 melancholy | |
n.忧郁,愁思;adj.令人感伤(沮丧)的,忧郁的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 statute | |
n.成文法,法令,法规;章程,规则,条例 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 clergy | |
n.[总称]牧师,神职人员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 pervading | |
v.遍及,弥漫( pervade的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 Augmented | |
adj.增音的 动词augment的过去式和过去分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 augment | |
vt.(使)增大,增加,增长,扩张 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 guilt | |
n.犯罪;内疚;过失,罪责 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 offender | |
n.冒犯者,违反者,犯罪者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 severely | |
adv.严格地;严厉地;非常恶劣地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 imprisonment | |
n.关押,监禁,坐牢 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 inflicted | |
把…强加给,使承受,遭受( inflict的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 secluded | |
adj.与世隔绝的;隐退的;偏僻的v.使隔开,使隐退( seclude的过去式和过去分词) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 lessen | |
vt.减少,减轻;缩小 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 vindictive | |
adj.有报仇心的,怀恨的,惩罚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 hesitation | |
n.犹豫,踌躇 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 extolling | |
v.赞美( extoll的现在分词 );赞颂,赞扬,赞美( extol的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 excellence | |
n.优秀,杰出,(pl.)优点,美德 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 savages | |
未开化的人,野蛮人( savage的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 reverence | |
n.敬畏,尊敬,尊严;Reverence:对某些基督教神职人员的尊称;v.尊敬,敬畏,崇敬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 pillory | |
n.嘲弄;v.使受公众嘲笑;将…示众 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 gallows | |
n.绞刑架,绞台 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 diminution | |
n.减少;变小 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 speculative | |
adj.思索性的,暝想性的,推理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 abortive | |
adj.不成功的,发育不全的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 mitigate | |
vt.(使)减轻,(使)缓和 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 commute | |
vi.乘车上下班;vt.减(刑);折合;n.上下班交通 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 onward | |
adj.向前的,前进的;adv.向前,前进,在先 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 systematic | |
adj.有系统的,有计划的,有方法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 obstinate | |
adj.顽固的,倔强的,不易屈服的,较难治愈的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 justification | |
n.正当的理由;辩解的理由 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 repeal | |
n.废止,撤消;v.废止,撤消 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 privy | |
adj.私用的;隐密的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 assent | |
v.批准,认可;n.批准,认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 subversion | |
n.颠覆,破坏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 dread | |
vt.担忧,忧虑;惧怕,不敢;n.担忧,畏惧 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 atrocities | |
n.邪恶,暴行( atrocity的名词复数 );滔天大罪 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 whitewashed | |
粉饰,美化,掩饰( whitewash的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 reprieve | |
n.暂缓执行(死刑);v.缓期执行;给…带来缓解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 vehement | |
adj.感情强烈的;热烈的;(人)有强烈感情的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 censure | |
v./n.责备;非难;责难 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 malefactor | |
n.罪犯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 folly | |
n.愚笨,愚蠢,蠢事,蠢行,傻话 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 indirectly | |
adv.间接地,不直接了当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 forefathers | |
n.祖先,先人;祖先,祖宗( forefather的名词复数 );列祖列宗;前人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 dedicated | |
adj.一心一意的;献身的;热诚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 bishop | |
n.主教,(国际象棋)象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 dedication | |
n.奉献,献身,致力,题献,献辞 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 inveterate | |
adj.积习已深的,根深蒂固的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 obstruction | |
n.阻塞,堵塞;障碍物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 ingenuity | |
n.别出心裁;善于发明创造 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 deterrent | |
n.阻碍物,制止物;adj.威慑的,遏制的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 privately | |
adv.以私人的身份,悄悄地,私下地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 margin | |
n.页边空白;差额;余地,余裕;边,边缘 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 impartiality | |
n. 公平, 无私, 不偏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 maxim | |
n.格言,箴言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 heresy | |
n.异端邪说;异教 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 impairing | |
v.损害,削弱( impair的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 villain | |
n.反派演员,反面人物;恶棍;问题的起因 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 concealed | |
a.隐藏的,隐蔽的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 prosecuting | |
检举、告发某人( prosecute的现在分词 ); 对某人提起公诉; 继续从事(某事物); 担任控方律师 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 livelihood | |
n.生计,谋生之道 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 restriction | |
n.限制,约束 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 arson | |
n.纵火,放火 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 habitual | |
adj.习惯性的;通常的,惯常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 penitentiary | |
n.感化院;监狱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 bondage | |
n.奴役,束缚 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 auspices | |
n.资助,赞助 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 unnaturally | |
adv.违反习俗地;不自然地;勉强地;不近人情地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 mischievous | |
adj.调皮的,恶作剧的,有害的,伤人的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 legislative | |
n.立法机构,立法权;adj.立法的,有立法权的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 humane | |
adj.人道的,富有同情心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 insolently | |
adv.自豪地,自傲地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 abolition | |
n.废除,取消 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 humble | |
adj.谦卑的,恭顺的;地位低下的;v.降低,贬低 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 lapse | |
n.过失,流逝,失效,抛弃信仰,间隔;vi.堕落,停止,失效,流逝;vt.使失效 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 affixed | |
adj.[医]附着的,附着的v.附加( affix的过去式和过去分词 );粘贴;加以;盖(印章) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 larceny | |
n.盗窃(罪) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 statutes | |
成文法( statute的名词复数 ); 法令; 法规; 章程 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 pilfering | |
v.偷窃(小东西),小偷( pilfer的现在分词 );偷窃(一般指小偷小摸) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 prosecutions | |
起诉( prosecution的名词复数 ); 原告; 实施; 从事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 prosecute | |
vt.告发;进行;vi.告发,起诉,作检察官 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 doctrines | |
n.教条( doctrine的名词复数 );教义;学说;(政府政策的)正式声明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 eloquence | |
n.雄辩;口才,修辞 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 bishops | |
(基督教某些教派管辖大教区的)主教( bishop的名词复数 ); (国际象棋的)象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 clemency | |
n.温和,仁慈,宽厚 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 conformity | |
n.一致,遵从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 expedient | |
adj.有用的,有利的;n.紧急的办法,权宜之计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 remit | |
v.汇款,汇寄;豁免(债务),免除(处罚等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 entreated | |
恳求,乞求( entreat的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 deference | |
n.尊重,顺从;敬意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 condemned | |
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 spoke | |
n.(车轮的)辐条;轮辐;破坏某人的计划;阻挠某人的行动 v.讲,谈(speak的过去式);说;演说;从某种观点来说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 reign | |
n.统治时期,统治,支配,盛行;v.占优势 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 forgery | |
n.伪造的文件等,赝品,伪造(行为) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 recollected | |
adj.冷静的;镇定的;被回忆起的;沉思默想的v.记起,想起( recollect的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 submission | |
n.服从,投降;温顺,谦虚;提出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 judicial | |
adj.司法的,法庭的,审判的,明断的,公正的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 assented | |
同意,赞成( assent的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 mitigated | |
v.减轻,缓和( mitigate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 herds | |
兽群( herd的名词复数 ); 牧群; 人群; 群众 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 concession | |
n.让步,妥协;特许(权) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 repealed | |
撤销,废除( repeal的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 obsolete | |
adj.已废弃的,过时的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 extinction | |
n.熄灭,消亡,消灭,灭绝,绝种 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 intervals | |
n.[军事]间隔( interval的名词复数 );间隔时间;[数学]区间;(戏剧、电影或音乐会的)幕间休息 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 prematurely | |
adv.过早地,贸然地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 nominal | |
adj.名义上的;(金额、租金)微不足道的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 conclusively | |
adv.令人信服地,确凿地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 humanitarians | |
n.慈善家( humanitarian的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |