All the varieties of attack directed against the poets by the lovers of naked truth may be repelled2 by a two-fold defence: either that even in an unseemly subject-matter we may learn a charming fashion of speech, or that where a fictitious3 but becoming subject is handled, natural or historical truth is pursued under the guise4 of allegorical fiction.
Although it is true that all men naturally desire knowledge, yet they do not all take the same pleasure in learning. On the contrary, when they have experienced the labour of study and find their senses wearied, most men inconsiderately fling away the nut, before they have broken the shell and reached the kernel5. For man is naturally fond of two things, namely, freedom from control and some pleasure in his activity; for which reason no one without reason submits himself to the control of others, or willingly engages in any tedious task. For pleasure crowns activity, as beauty is a crown to youth, as Aristotle truly asserts in the tenth book of the Ethics7. Accordingly the wisdom of the ancients devised a remedy by which to entice8 the wanton minds of men by a kind of pious9 fraud, the delicate Minerva secretly lurking10 beneath the mask of pleasure. We are wont11 to allure12 children by rewards, that they may cheerfully learn what we force them to study even though they are unwilling13. For our fallen nature does not tend to virtue14 with the same enthusiasm with which it rushes into vice15. Horace has expressed this for us in a brief verse of the Ars Poetica, where he says:
All poets sing to profit or delight.
And he has plainly intimated the same thing in another verse of the same book, where he says:
He hits the mark, who mingles16 joy with use.
How many students of Euclid have been repelled by the Pons Asinorum, as by a lofty and precipitous rock, which no help of ladders could enable them to scale! THIS IS A HARD SAYING, they exclaim, AND WHO CAN RECEIVE IT. The child of inconstancy, who ended by wishing to be transformed into an ass6, would perhaps never have given up the study of philosophy, if he had met him in friendly guise veiled under the cloak of pleasure; but anon, astonished by Crato’s chair and struck dumb by his endless questions, as by a sudden thunderbolt, he saw no refuge but in flight.
So much we have alleged17 in defence of the poets; and now we proceed to show that those who study them with proper intent are not to be condemned18 in regard to them. For our ignorance of one single word prevents the understanding of a whole long sentence, as was assumed in the previous chapter. As now the sayings of the saints frequently allude19 to the inventions of the poets, it must needs happen that through our not knowing the poem referred to, the whole meaning of the author is completely obscured, and assuredly, as Cassiodorus says in his book Of the Institutes of Sacred Literature: Those things are not to be considered trifles without which great things cannot come to pass. It follows therefore that through ignorance of poetry we do not understand Jerome, Augustine, Boethius, Lactantius, Sidonius, and very many others, a catalogue of whom would more than fill a long chapter.
The Venerable Bede has very clearly discussed and determined20 this doubtful point, as is related by that great compiler Gratian, the repeater of numerous authors, who is as confused in form as he was eager in collecting matter for his compilation21. Now he writes in his 37th section: Some read secular22 literature for pleasure, taking delight in the inventions and elegant language of the poets; but others study this literature for the sake of scholarship, that by their reading they may learn to detest23 the errors of the Gentiles and may devoutly24 apply what they find useful in them to the use of sacred learning. Such men study secular literature in a laudable manner. So far Bede.
Taking this salutary instruction to heart, let the detractors of those who study the poets henceforth hold their peace, and let not those who are ignorant of these things require that others should be as ignorant as themselves, for this is the consolation25 of the wretched. And therefore let every man see that his own intentions are upright, and he may thus make of any subject, observing the limitations of virtue, a study acceptable to God. And if he have found profit in poetry, as the great Virgil relates that he had done in Ennius, he will not have done amiss.
点击收听单词发音
1 fables | |
n.寓言( fable的名词复数 );神话,传说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 repelled | |
v.击退( repel的过去式和过去分词 );使厌恶;排斥;推开 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 fictitious | |
adj.虚构的,假设的;空头的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 guise | |
n.外表,伪装的姿态 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 kernel | |
n.(果实的)核,仁;(问题)的中心,核心 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 ass | |
n.驴;傻瓜,蠢笨的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 ethics | |
n.伦理学;伦理观,道德标准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 entice | |
v.诱骗,引诱,怂恿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 pious | |
adj.虔诚的;道貌岸然的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 lurking | |
潜在 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 wont | |
adj.习惯于;v.习惯;n.习惯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 allure | |
n.诱惑力,魅力;vt.诱惑,引诱,吸引 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 unwilling | |
adj.不情愿的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 mingles | |
混合,混入( mingle的第三人称单数 ); 混进,与…交往[联系] | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 alleged | |
a.被指控的,嫌疑的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 condemned | |
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 allude | |
v.提及,暗指 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 compilation | |
n.编译,编辑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 secular | |
n.牧师,凡人;adj.世俗的,现世的,不朽的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 detest | |
vt.痛恨,憎恶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 devoutly | |
adv.虔诚地,虔敬地,衷心地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 consolation | |
n.安慰,慰问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |