THERE is, in Dr. Tillotson's writings, an argument against the real presence, which is as concise1, and elegant, and strong as any argument can possibly be supposed against a doctrine2, so little worthy3 of a serious refutation. It is acknowledged on all hands, says that learned prelate, that the authority, either of the scripture4 or of tradition, is founded merely in the testimony6 of the Apostles, who were eye-witnesses to those miracles of our Saviour7, by which he proved his divine mission. Our evidence, then, for, the truth of the Christian8 religion is less than the evidence for the truth of our senses; because, even in the first authors of our religion, it was no greater; and it is evident it must diminish in passing from them to their disciples9; nor can any one rest such confidence in their testimony, as in the immediate10 object of his senses. But a weaker evidence can never destroy a stronger; and therefore, were the doctrine of the real presence ever so clearly revealed in scripture, it were directly contrary to the rules of just reasoning to give our assent11 to it. It contradicts sense, though both the scripture and tradition, on which it is supposed to be built, carry not such evidence with them as sense; when they are considered merely as external evidences, and are not brought home to every one's breast, by the immediate operation of the Holy Spirit.
Nothing is so convenient as a decisive argument of this kind, which must at least silence the most arrogant12 bigotry13 and superstition14, and free us from their impertinent solicitations. I flatter myself, that I have discovered an argument of a like nature, which, if just, will, with the wise and learned, be an everlasting15 check to all kinds of superstitious16 delusion17, and consequently, will be useful as long as the world endures. For so long, I presume, will the accounts of miracles and prodigies18 be found in all history, sacred and profane19.
Though experience be our only guide in reasoning concerning matters of fact; it must be acknowledged, that this guide is not altogether infallible, but in some cases is apt to lead us into errors. One, who in our climate, should expect better weather in any week of June than in one of December, would reason justly, and conformably to experience; but it is certain, that he may happen, in the event, to find himself mistaken. However, we may observe, that, in such a case, he would have no cause to complain of experience; because it commonly informs us beforehand of the uncertainty20, by that contrariety of events, which we may learn from a diligent21 observation. All effects follow not with like certainty from their supposed causes. Some events are found, in all countries and all ages, to have been constantly conjoined together: Others are found to have been more variable, and sometimes to disappoint our expectations; so that, in our reasonings concerning matter of fact, there are all imaginable degrees of assurance, from the highest certainty to the lowest species of moral evidence.
A wise man, therefore, proportions his belief to the evidence. In such conclusions as are founded on an infallible experience, he expects the event with the last degree of assurance, and regards his past experience as a full proof of the future existence of that event. In other cases, he proceeds with more caution: he weighs the opposite experiments: he considers which side is supported by the greater number of experiments: to that side he inclines, with doubt and hesitation22; and when at last he fixes his judgement, the evidence exceeds not what we properly call probability. All probability, then, supposes an opposition23 of experiments and observations, where the one side is found to overbalance the other, and to produce a degree of evidence, proportioned to the superiority. A hundred instances or experiments on one side, and fifty on another, afford a doubtful expectation of any event; though a hundred uniform experiments, with only one that is contradictory24, reasonably beget25 a pretty strong degree of assurance. In all cases, we must balance the opposite experiments, where they are opposite, and deduct26 the smaller number from the greater, in order to know the exact force of the superior evidence.
To apply these principles to a particular instance; we may observe, that there is no species of reasoning more common, more useful, and even necessary to human life, than that which is derived27 from the testimony of men, and the reports of eye-witnesses and spectators. This species of reasoning, perhaps, one may deny to be founded on the relation of cause and effect. I shall not dispute about a word. It will be sufficient to observe that our assurance in any argument of this kind is derived from no other principle than our observation of the veracity28 of human testimony, and of the usual conformity29 of facts to the reports of witnesses. It being a general maxim30, that no objects have any discoverable connexion together, and that all the inferences, which we can draw from one to another, are founded merely on our experience of their constant and regular conjunction; it is evident, that we ought not to make an exception to this maxim in favour of human testimony, whose connexion with any event seems, in itself, as little necessary as any other. Were not the memory tenacious31 to a certain degree; had not men commonly an inclination32 to truth and a principle of probity33; were they not sensible to shame, when detected in a falsehood: were not these, I say, discovered by experience to be qualities, inherent in human nature, we should never repose34 the least confidence in human testimony. A man delirious35, or noted36 for falsehood and villainy, has no manner of authority with us.
And as the evidence, derived from witnesses and human testimony, is founded on past experience, so it varies with the experience, and is regarded either as a proof or a probability, according as the conjunction between any particular kind of report and any kind of object has been found to be constant or variable. There are a number of circumstances to be taken into consideration in all judgements of this kind; and the ultimate standard, by which we determine all disputes, that may arise concerning them, is always derived from experience and observation. Where this experience is not entirely37 uniform on any side, it is attended with an unavoidable contrariety in our judgements, and with the same opposition and mutual38 destruction of argument as in every other kind of evidence. We frequently hesitate concerning the reports of others. We balance the opposite circumstances, which cause any doubt or uncertainty; and when we discover a superiority on any side, we incline to it; but still with a diminution39 of assurance, in proportion to the force of its antagonist40.
This contrariety of evidence, in the present case, may be derived from several different causes; from the opposition of contrary testimony; from the character or number of the witnesses; from the manner of their delivering their testimony; or from the union of all these circumstances. We entertain a suspicion concerning any matter of fact, when the witnesses contradict each other; when they are but few, or of a doubtful character; when they have an interest in what they affirm; when they deliver their testimony with hesitation, or on the contrary, with too violent asseverations. There are many other particulars of the same kind, which may diminish or destroy the force of any argument, derived from human testimony.
Suppose, for instance, that the fact, which the testimony endeavours to establish, partakes of the extraordinary and the marvellous; in that case, the evidence, resulting from the testimony, admits of a diminution, greater or less, in proportion as the fact is more or less unusual. The reason why we place any credit in witnesses and historians, is not derived from any connexion, which we perceive a priori, between testimony and reality, but because we are accustomed to find a conformity between them. But when the fact attested41 is such a one as has seldom fallen under our observation, here is a contest of two opposite experiences; of which the one destroys the other, as far as its force goes, and the superior can only operate on the mind by the force, which remains42. The very same principle of experience, which gives us a certain degree of assurance in the testimony of witnesses, gives us also, in this case, another degree of assurance against the fact, which they endeavour to establish; from which contradiction there necessarily arises a counterpoize, and mutual destruction of belief and authority.
I should not believe such a story were it told me by Cato, was a proverbial saying in Rome, even during the lifetime of that philosophical43 patriot44.20 The incredibility of a fact, it was allowed, might invalidate so great an authority.
The Indian prince, who refused to believe the first relations concerning the effects of frost, reasoned justly; and it naturally required very strong testimony to engage his assent to facts, that arose from a state of nature, with which he was unacquainted, and which bore so little analogy to those events, of which he had had constant and uniform experience. Though they were not contrary to his experience, they were not conformable to it.21
But in order to encrease the probability against the testimony of witnesses, let us suppose, that the fact, which they affirm, instead of being only marvellous, is really miraculous45; and suppose also, that the testimony considered apart and in itself, amounts to an entire proof; in that case, there is proof against proof, of which the strongest must prevail, but still with a diminution of its force, in proportion to that of its antagonist.
A miracle is a violation46 of the laws of nature; and as a firm and unalterable experience has established these laws, the proof against a miracle, from the very nature of the fact, is as entire as any argument from experience can possibly be imagined. Why is it more than probable, that all men must die; that lead cannot, of itself, remain suspended in the air; that fire consumes wood, and is extinguished by water; unless it be, that these events are found agreeable to the laws of nature, and there is required a violation of these laws, or in other words, a miracle to prevent them? Nothing is esteemed48 a miracle, if it ever happen in the common course of nature. It is no miracle that a man, seemingly in good health, should die on a sudden: because such a kind of death, though more unusual than any other, has yet been frequently observed to happen. But it is a miracle, that a dead man should come to life; because that has never been observed in any age or country. There must, therefore, be a uniform experience against every miraculous event, otherwise the event would not merit that appellation49. And as a uniform experience amounts to a proof, there is here a direct and full proof, from the nature of the fact, against the existence of any miracle; nor can such a proof be destroyed, or the miracle rendered credible50, but by an opposite proof, which is superior.22
The plain consequence is (and it is a general maxim worthy of our attention), 'that no testimony is sufficient to establish a miracle, unless the testimony be of such a kind, that its falsehood would be more miraculous, than the fact, which it endeavors to establish; and even in that case there is a mutual destruction of arguments, and the superior only gives us an assurance suitable to that degree of force, which remains, after deducting51 the inferior.' When anyone tells me, that he saw a dead man restored to life, I immediately consider with myself, whether it be more probable, that this person should either deceive or be deceived, or that the fact, which he relates, should really have happened. I weigh the one miracle against the other; and according to the superiority, which I discover, I pronounce my decision, and always reject the greater miracle. If the falsehood of his testimony would be more miraculous, than the event which he relates; then, and not till then, can he pretend to command my belief or opinion.
Part II
IN the foregoing reasoning we have supposed, that the testimony, upon which a miracle is founded, may possibly amount to an entire proof, and that the falsehood of that testimony would be a real prodigy52: but it is easy to shew, that we have been a great deal too liberal in our concession53, and that there never was a miraculous event established on so full an evidence.
For first, there is not to be found, in all history, any miracle attested by a sufficient number of men, of such unquestioned good-sense, education, and learning, as to secure us against all delusion in themselves; of such undoubted integrity, as to place them beyond all suspicion of any design to deceive others; of such credit and reputation in the eyes of mankind, as to have a great deal to lose in case of their being detected in any falsehood; and at the same time, attesting54 facts performed in such a public manner and in so celebrated55 a part of the world, as to render the detection unavoidable: all which circumstances are requisite56 to give us a full assurance in the testimony of men.
Secondly57. We may observe in human nature a principle which, if strictly58 examined, will be found to diminish extremely the assurance, which we might, from human testimony, have in any kind of prodigy. The maxim, by which we commonly conduct ourselves in our reasonings, is, that the objects, of which we have no experience, resembles those, of which we have; that what we have found to be most usual is always most probable; and that where there is an opposition of arguments, we ought to give the preference to such as are founded on the greatest number of past observations. But though, in proceeding59 by this rule, we readily reject any fact which is unusual and incredible in an ordinary degree; yet in advancing farther, the mind observes not always the same rule; but when anything is affirmed utterly60 absurd and miraculous, it rather the more readily admits of such a fact, upon account of that very circumstance, which ought to destroy all its authority. The passion of surprise and wonder, arising from miracles, being an agreeable emotion, gives a sensible tendency towards the belief of those events, from which it is derived. And this goes so far, that even those who cannot enjoy this pleasure immediately, nor can believe those miraculous events, of which they are informed, yet love to partake of the satisfaction at second-hand61 or by rebound62, and place a pride and delight in exciting the admiration63 of others.
With what greediness are the miraculous accounts of travellers received, their descriptions of sea and land monsters, their relations of wonderful adventures, strange men, and uncouth64 manners? But if the spirit of religion join itself to the love of wonder, there is an end of common sense; and human testimony, in these circumstances, loses all pretensions65 to authority. A religionist may be an enthusiast66, and imagine he sees what has no reality: he may know his narrative67 to be false, and yet persevere68 in it, with the best intentions in the world, for the sake of promoting so holy a cause: or even where this delusion has not place, vanity, excited by so strong a temptation, operates on him more powerfully than on the rest of mankind in any other circumstances; and self-interest with equal force. His auditors69 may not have, and commonly have not, sufficient judgement to canvass70 his evidence: what judgement they have, they renounce71 by principle, in these sublime72 and mysterious subjects: or if they were ever so willing to employ it, passion and a heated imagination disturb the regularity73 of its operations. their credulity increases his impudence74: and his impudence overpowers their credulity.
Eloquence75, when at its highest pitch, leaves little room for reason or reflection; but addressing itself entirely to the fancy or the affections, captivates the willing hearers, and subdues76 their understanding. Happily, this pitch it seldom attains77. But what a Tully or a Demosthenes could scarcely effect over a Roman or Athenian audience, every Capuchin, every itinerant79 or stationary80 teacher can perform over the generality of mankind, and in a higher degree, by touching81 such gross and vulgar passions.
The many instances of forged miracles, and prophecies, and supernatural events, which, in all ages, have either been detected by contrary evidence, or which detect themselves by their absurdity82, prove sufficiently83 the strong propensity84 of mankind to the extraordinary and the marvellous, and ought reasonably to beget a suspicion against all relations of this kind. This is our natural way of thinking, even with regard to the most common and most credible events. For instance: There is no kind of report which rises so easily, and spreads so quickly, especially in country places and provincial85 towns, as those concerning marriages; insomuch that two young persons of equal condition never see each other twice, but the whole neighbourhood immediately join them together. The pleasure of telling a piece of news so interesting, of propagating it, and of being the first reporters of it, spreads the intelligence. And this is so well known, that no man of sense gives attention to these reports, till he find them confirmed by some greater evidence. Do not the same passions, and others still stronger, incline the generality of mankind to believe and report, with the greatest vehemence86 and assurance, all religious miracles?
Thirdly. It forms a strong presumption87 against all supernatural and miraculous relations, that they are observed chiefly to abound88 among ignorant and barbarous nations; or if a civilized89 people has ever given admission to any of them, that people will be found to have received them from ignorant and barbarous ancestors, who transmitted them with that inviolable sanction and authority, which always attend received opinions. When we peruse90 the first histories of all nations, we are apt to imagine ourselves transported into some new world; where the whole frame of nature is disjointed, and every element performs its operations in a different manner, from what it does at present. Battles, revolutions, pestilence91, famine and death, are never the effect of those natural causes, which we experience. Prodigies, omens92, oracles93, judgements, quite obscure the few natural events, that are intermingled with them. But as the former grow thinner every page, in proportion as we advance nearer the enlightened ages, we soon learn, that there is nothing mysterious or supernatural in the case, but that all proceeds from the usual propensity of mankind towards the marvellous, and that, though this inclination may at intervals94 receive a check from sense and learning, it can never be thoroughly95 extirpated96 from human nature.
It is strange, a judicious97 reader is apt to say, upon the perusal98 of these wonderful historians, that such prodigious99 events never happen in our days. But it is nothing strange, I hope, that men should lie in all ages. You must surely have seen instances enough of that frailty100. You have yourself heard many such marvellous relations started, which, being treated with scorn by all the wise and judicious, have at last been abandoned even by the vulgar. Be assured, that those renowned101 lies, which have spread and flourished to such a monstrous102 height, arose from like beginnings; but being sown in a more proper soil, shot up at last into prodigies almost equal to those which they relate.
It was a wise policy in that false prophet, Alexander, who though now forgotten, was once so famous, to lay the first scene of his impostures in Paphlagonia, where, as Lucian tells us, the people were extremely ignorant and stupid, and ready to swallow even the grossest delusion. People at a distance, who are weak enough to think the matter at all worth enquiry, have no opportunity of receiving better information. The stories come magnified to them by a hundred circumstances. Fools are industrious104 in propagating the imposture103; while the wise and learned are contented105, in general, to deride106 its absurdity, without informing themselves of the particular facts, by which it may be distinctly refuted. And thus the impostor above mentioned was enabled to proceed, from his ignorant Paphlagonians, to the enlisting107 of votaries108, even among the Grecian philosophers, and men of the most eminent109 rank and distinction in Rome; nay110, could engage the attention of that sage111 emperor Marcus Aurelius; so far as to make him trust the success of a military expedition to his delusive112 prophecies.
The advantages are so great, of starting an imposture among an ignorant people, that, even though the delusion should be too gross to impose on the generality of them (which, though seldom, is sometimes the case) it has a much better chance for succeeding in remote countries, than if the first scene had been laid in a city renowned for arts and knowledge. The most ignorant and barbarous of these barbarians113 carry the report abroad. None of their countrymen have a large correspondence, or sufficient credit and authority to contradict and beat down the delusion. Men's inclination to the marvellous has full opportunity to display itself. And thus a story, which is universally exploded in the place where it was first started, shall pass for certain at a thousand miles distance. But had Alexander fixed114 his residence at Athens, the philosophers of that renowned mart of learning had immediately spread, throughout the whole Roman empire, their sense of the matter; which, being supported by so great authority, and displayed by all the force of reason and eloquence, had entirely opened the eyes of mankind. It is true; Lucian, passing by chance through Paphlagonia, had an opportunity of performing this good office. But, though much to be wished, it does not always happen, that every Alexander meets with a Lucian, ready to expose and detect his impostures.
I may add as a fourth reason, which diminishes the authority of prodigies, that there is no testimony for any, even those which have not been expressly detected, that is not opposed by an infinite number of witnesses; so that not only the miracle destroys the credit of testimony, but the testimony destroys itself. To make this the better understood, let us consider, that, in matters of religion, whatever is different is contrary; and that it is impossible the religions of ancient Rome, of Turkey, of Siam, and of China should, all of them, be established on any solid foundation. Every miracle, therefore, pretended to have been wrought115 in any of these religions (and all of them abound in miracles), as its direct scope is to establish the particular system to which it is attributed; so has it the same force, though more indirectly116, to overthrow117 every other system. In destroying a rival system, it likewise destroys the credit of those miracles, on which that system was established; so that all the prodigies of different religions are to be regarded as contrary facts, and the evidences of these prodigies, whether weak or strong, as opposite to each other. According to this method of reasoning, when we believe any miracle of Mahomet or his successors, we have for our warrant the testimony of a few barbarous Arabians: and on the other hand, we are to regard the authority of Titus Livius, Plutarch, Tacitus, and, in short, of all the authors and witnesses, Grecian, Chinese, and Roman Catholic, who have related any miracle in their particular religion; I say, we are to regard their testimony in the same light as if they had mentioned that Mahometan miracle, and had in express terms contradicted it, with the same certainty as they have for the miracle they relate. This argument may appear over subtile and refined; but is not in reality different from the reasoning of a judge, who supposes, that the credit of two witnesses, maintaining a crime against any one, is destroyed by the testimony of two others, who affirm him to have been two hundred leagues distant, at the same instant when the crime is said to have been committed.
One of the best attested miracles in all profane history, is that which Tacitus reports of Vespasian, who cured a blind man in Alexandria, by means of his spittle, and a lame118 man by the mere5 touch of his foot; in obedience119 to a vision of the god Serapis, who had enjoined120 them to have recourse to the Emperor, for these miraculous cures. The story may be seen in that fine historian23; where every circumstance seems to add weight to the testimony, and might be displayed at large with all the force of argument and eloquence, if any one were now concerned to enforce the evidence of that exploded and idolatrous superstition. The gravity, solidity, age, and probity of so great an emperor, who, through the whole course of his life, conversed121 in a familiar manner with his friends and courtiers, and never affected122 those extraordinary airs of divinity assumed by Alexander and Demetrius. The historian, a contemporary writer, noted for candour and veracity, and withal, the greatest and most penetrating123 genius, perhaps, of all antiquity124; and so free from any tendency to credulity, that he even lies under the contrary imputation125, of atheism126 and profaneness127: The persons, from whose authority he related the miracle, of established character for judgement and veracity, as we may well presume; eye-witnesses of the fact, and confirming their testimony, after the Flavian family was despoiled128 of the empire, and could no longer give any reward, as the price of a lie. Utrumque, qui interfuere, nunc quoque memorant, postquam nullum mendacio pretium. To which if we add the public nature of the facts, as related, it will appear, that no evidence can well be supposed stronger for so gross and so palpable a falsehood.
There is also a memorable129 story related by Cardinal130 de Retz, which may well deserve our consideration. When that intriguing131 politician fled into Spain, to avoid the persecution132 of his enemies, he passed through Saragossa, the capital of Arragon, where he was shewn, in the cathedral, a man, who had served seven years as a doorkeeper, and was well known to every body in town, that had ever paid his devotions at that church. He had been seen, for so long a time, wanting a leg; but recovered that limb by the rubbing of holy oil upon the stump133; and the cardinal assures us that he saw him with two legs. This miracle was vouched134 by all the canons of the church; and the whole company in town were appealed to for a confirmation135 of the fact; whom the cardinal found, by their zealous136 devotion, to be thorough believers of the miracle. Here the relater was also contemporary to the supposed prodigy, of an incredulous and libertine137 character, as well as of great genius; the miracle of so singular a nature as could scarcely admit of a counterfeit138, and the witnesses very numerous, and all of them, in a manner, spectators of the fact, to which they gave their testimony. And what adds mightily139 to the force of the evidence, and may double our surprise on this occasion, is, that the cardinal himself, who relates the story, seems not to give any credit to it, and consequently cannot be suspected of any concurrence140 in the holy fraud. He considered justly, that it was not requisite, in order to reject a fact of this nature, to be able accurately141 to disprove the testimony, and to trace its falsehood, through all the circumstances of knavery142 and credulity which produced it. He knew, that, as this was commonly altogether impossible at any small distance of time and place; so was it extremely difficult, even where one was immediately present, by reason of the bigotry, ignorance, cunning, and roguery of a great part of mankind. He therefore concluded, like a just reasoner, that such an evidence carried falsehood upon the very face of it, and that a miracle, supported by any human testimony, was more properly a subject of derision than of argument.
There surely never was a greater number of miracles ascribed to one person, than those, which were lately said to have been wrought in France upon the tomb of Abbe Paris, the famous Jansenist, with whose sanctity the people were so long deluded143. The curing of the sick, giving hearing to the deaf, and sight to the blind, were every where talked of as the usual effects of that holy sepulchre. But what is more extraordinary; many of the miracles were immediately proved upon the spot, before judges of unquestioned integrity, attested by witnesses of credit and distinction, in a learned age, and on the most eminent theatre that is now in the world. Nor is this all: a relation of them was published and dispersed144 everywhere; nor were the Jesuits, though a learned body supported by the civil magistrate145, and determined146 enemies to those opinions, in whose favour the miracles were said to have been wrought, ever able distinctly to refute or detect them.24 Where shall we find such a number of circumstances, agreeing to the corroboration147 of one fact? And what have we to oppose to such a cloud of witnesses, but the absolute impossibility or miraculous nature of the events, which they relate? And this surely, in the eyes of all reasonable people, will alone be regarded as a sufficient refutation.
Is the consequence just, because some human testimony has the utmost force and authority in some cases, when it relates the battle of Philippi or Pharsalia for instance; that therefore all kinds of testimony must, in all cases, have equal force and authority? Suppose that the Caesarean and Pompeian factions148 had, each of them, claimed the victory in these battles, and that the historians of each party had uniformly ascribed the advantage to their own side; how could mankind, at this distance, have been able to determine between them? The contrariety is equally strong between the miracles related by Herodotus or Plutarch, and those delivered by Mariana, Bede, or any monkish149 historian.
The wise lend a very academic faith to every report which favours the passion of the reporter; whether it magnifies his country, his family, or himself, or in any other way strikes in with his natural inclinations150 and propensities151. But what greater temptation than to appear a missionary152, a prophet, an ambassador from heaven? Who would not encounter many dangers and difficulties, in order to attain78 so sublime a character? Or if, by the help of vanity and a heated imagination, a man has first made a convert of himself, and entered seriously into the delusion; who ever scruples153 to make use of pious154 frauds, in support of so holy and meritorious155 a cause?
The smallest spark may here kindle156 into the greatest flame; because the materials are always prepared for it. The avidum genus auricularum25, the gazing populace, receive greedily, without examination, whatever sooths superstition, and promotes wonder.
How many stories of this nature have, in all ages, been detected and exploded in their infancy157? How many more have been celebrated for a time, and have afterwards sunk into neglect and oblivion? Where such reports, therefore, fly about, the solution of the phenomenon is obvious; and we judge in conformity to regular experience and observation, when we account for it by the known and natural principles of credulity and delusion. And shall we, rather than have a recourse to so natural a solution, allow of a miraculous violation of the most established laws of nature?
I need not mention the difficulty of detecting a falsehood in any private or even public history, at the place, where it is said to happen; much more when the scene is removed to ever so small a distance. Even a court of judicature, with all the authority, accuracy, and judgement, which they can employ, find themselves often at a loss to distinguish between truth and falsehood in the most recent actions. But the matter never comes to any issue, if trusted to the common method of altercations158 and debate and flying rumours159; especially when men's passions have taken part on either side.
In the infancy of new religions, the wise and learned commonly esteem47 the matter too inconsiderable to deserve their attention or regard. And when afterwards they would willingly detect the cheat in order to undeceive the deluded multitude, the season is now past, and the records and witnesses, which might clear up the matter, have perished beyond recovery.
No means of detection remain, but those which must be drawn160 from the very testimony itself of the reporters: and these, though always sufficient with the judicious and knowing, are commonly too fine to fall under the comprehension of the vulgar.
Upon the whole, then, it appears, that no testimony for any kind of miracle has ever amounted to a probability, much less to a proof; and that, even supposing it amounted to a proof, it would be opposed by another proof; derived from the very nature of the fact, which it would endeavour to establish. It is experience only, which gives authority to human testimony; and it is the same experience, which assures us of the laws of nature. When, therefore, these two kinds of experience are contrary, we have nothing to do but subtract the one from the other, and embrace an opinion, either on one side or the other, with that assurance which arises from the remainder. But according to the principle here explained, this subtraction161, with regard to all popular religions, amounts to an entire annihilation; and therefore we may establish it as a maxim, that no human testimony can have such force as to prove a miracle, and make it a just foundation for any such system of religion.
I beg the limitations here made may be remarked, when I say, that a miracle can never be proved, so as to be the foundation of a system of religion. For I own, that otherwise, there may possibly be miracles, or violations162 of the usual course of nature, of such a kind as to admit of proof from human testimony; though, perhaps, it will be impossible to find any such in all the records of history. Thus, suppose, all authors, in all languages, agree, that, from the first of January, 1600, there was a total darkness over the whole earth for eight days: suppose that the tradition of this extraordinary event is still strong and lively among the people: that all travellers, who return from foreign countries, bring us accounts of the same tradition, without the least variation or contradiction: it is evident, that our present philosophers, instead of doubting the fact, ought to receive it as certain, and ought to search for the causes whence it might be derived. The decay, corruption163, and dissolution of nature, is an event rendered probable by so many analogies, that any phenomenon, which seems to have a tendency towards that catastrophe164, comes within the reach of human testimony, if that testimony be very extensive and uniform.
But suppose, that all the historians who treat of England, should agree, that, on the first of January, 1600, Queen Elizabeth died; that both before and after her death she was seen by her physicians and the whole court, as is usual with persons of her rank; that her successor was acknowledged and proclaimed by the parliament; and that, after being interred165 a month, she again appeared, resumed the throne, and governed England for three years: I must confess that I should be surprised at the concurrence of so many odd circumstances, but should not have the least inclination to believe so miraculous an event. I should not doubt of her pretended death, and of those other public circumstances that followed it: I should only assert it to have been pretended, and that it neither was, nor possibly could be real. You would in vain object to me the difficulty, and almost impossibility of deceiving the world in an affair of such consequence; the wisdom and solid judgment166 of that renowned queen; with the little or no advantage which she could reap from so poor an artifice167: all this might astonish me; but I would still reply, that the knavery and folly168 of men are such common phenomena169, that I should rather believe the most extraordinary events to arise from their concurrence, than admit of so signal a violation of the laws of nature.
But should this miracle be ascribed to any new system of religion; men, in all ages, have been so much imposed on by ridiculous stories of that kind, that this very circumstance would be a full proof of a cheat, and sufficient, with all men of sense, not only to make them reject the fact, but even reject it without farther examination. Though the Being to whom the miracle is ascribed, be, in this case, Almighty170, it does not, upon that account, become a whit171 more probable; since it is impossible for us to know the attributes or actions of such a Being, otherwise than from the experience which we have of his productions, in the usual course of nature. This still reduces us to past observation, and obliges us to compare the instances of the violation of truth in the testimony of men, with those of the violation of the laws of nature by miracles, in order to judge which of them is most likely and probable. As the violations of truth are more common in the testimony concerning religious miracles, than in that concerning any other matter of fact; this must diminish very much the authority of the former testimony, and make us form a general resolution, never to lend any attention to it, with whatever specious172 pretence173 it may be covered.
Lord Bacon seems to have embraced the same principles of reasoning. 'We ought,' says he, 'to make a collection or particular history of all monsters and prodigious births or productions, and in a word of every thing new, rare, and extraordinary in nature. But this must be done with the most severe scrutiny174, lest we depart from truth. Above all, every relation must be considered as suspicious, which depends in any degree upon religion, as the prodigies of Livy: and no less so, everything that is to be found in the writers of natural magic or alchimy, or such authors, who seem, all of them, to have an unconquerable appetite for falsehood and fable175.26
I am the better pleased with the method of reasoning here delivered, as I think it may serve to confound those dangerous friends or disguised enemies to the Christian Religion, who have undertaken to defend it by the principles of human reason. Our most holy religion is founded on Faith, not on reason; and it is a sure method of exposing it to put it to such a trial as it is, by no means, fitted to endure. To make this more evident, let us examine those miracles, related in scripture; and not to lose ourselves in too wide a field, let us confine ourselves to such as we find in the Pentateuch, which we shall examine, according to the principles of these pretended Christians176, not as the word or testimony of God himself, but as the production of a mere human writer and historian. Here then we are first to consider a book, presented to us by a barbarous and ignorant people, written in an age when they were still more barbarous, and in all probability long after the facts which it relates, corroborated177 by no concurring178 testimony, and resembling those fabulous179 accounts, which every nation gives of its origin. Upon reading this book, we find it full of prodigies and miracles. It gives an account of a state of the world and of human nature entirely different from the present: of our fall from that state: of the age of man, extended to near a thousand years: of the destruction of the world by a deluge180: of the arbitrary choice of one people, as the favourites of heaven; and that people the countrymen of the author: of their deliverance from bondage181 by prodigies the most astonishing imaginable: I desire any one to lay his hand upon his heart, and after a serious consideration declare, whether he thinks that the falsehood of such a book, supported by such a testimony, would be more extraordinary and miraculous than all the miracles it relates; which is, however, necessary to make it be received, according to the measures of probability above established.
What we have said of miracles may be applied182, without any variation, to prophecies; and indeed, all prophecies are real miracles, and as such only, can be admitted as proofs of any revelation. If it did not exceed the capacity of human nature to foretell183 future events, it would be absurd to employ any prophecy as an argument for a divine mission or authority from heaven. So that, upon the whole, we may conclude, that the Christian Religion not only was at first attended with miracles, but even at this day cannot be believed by any reasonable person without one. Mere reason is insufficient184 to convince us of its veracity: and whoever is moved by Faith to assent to it, is conscious of a continued miracle in his own person, which subverts185 all the principles of his understanding, and gives him a determination to believe what is most contrary to custom and experience.
点击收听单词发音
1 concise | |
adj.简洁的,简明的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 worthy | |
adj.(of)值得的,配得上的;有价值的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 scripture | |
n.经文,圣书,手稿;Scripture:(常用复数)《圣经》,《圣经》中的一段 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 testimony | |
n.证词;见证,证明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 saviour | |
n.拯救者,救星 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 Christian | |
adj.基督教徒的;n.基督教徒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 disciples | |
n.信徒( disciple的名词复数 );门徒;耶稣的信徒;(尤指)耶稣十二门徒之一 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 assent | |
v.批准,认可;n.批准,认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 arrogant | |
adj.傲慢的,自大的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 bigotry | |
n.偏见,偏执,持偏见的行为[态度]等 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 superstition | |
n.迷信,迷信行为 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 everlasting | |
adj.永恒的,持久的,无止境的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 superstitious | |
adj.迷信的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 delusion | |
n.谬见,欺骗,幻觉,迷惑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 prodigies | |
n.奇才,天才(尤指神童)( prodigy的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 profane | |
adj.亵神的,亵渎的;vt.亵渎,玷污 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 uncertainty | |
n.易变,靠不住,不确知,不确定的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 diligent | |
adj.勤勉的,勤奋的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 hesitation | |
n.犹豫,踌躇 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 contradictory | |
adj.反驳的,反对的,抗辩的;n.正反对,矛盾对立 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 beget | |
v.引起;产生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 deduct | |
vt.扣除,减去 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 veracity | |
n.诚实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 conformity | |
n.一致,遵从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 maxim | |
n.格言,箴言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 tenacious | |
adj.顽强的,固执的,记忆力强的,粘的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 inclination | |
n.倾斜;点头;弯腰;斜坡;倾度;倾向;爱好 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 probity | |
n.刚直;廉洁,正直 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 repose | |
v.(使)休息;n.安息 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 delirious | |
adj.不省人事的,神智昏迷的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 noted | |
adj.著名的,知名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 mutual | |
adj.相互的,彼此的;共同的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 diminution | |
n.减少;变小 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 antagonist | |
n.敌人,对抗者,对手 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 attested | |
adj.经检验证明无病的,经检验证明无菌的v.证明( attest的过去式和过去分词 );证实;声称…属实;使宣誓 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 patriot | |
n.爱国者,爱国主义者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 miraculous | |
adj.像奇迹一样的,不可思议的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 violation | |
n.违反(行为),违背(行为),侵犯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 esteem | |
n.尊敬,尊重;vt.尊重,敬重;把…看作 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 esteemed | |
adj.受人尊敬的v.尊敬( esteem的过去式和过去分词 );敬重;认为;以为 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 appellation | |
n.名称,称呼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 credible | |
adj.可信任的,可靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 deducting | |
v.扣除,减去( deduct的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 prodigy | |
n.惊人的事物,奇迹,神童,天才,预兆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 concession | |
n.让步,妥协;特许(权) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 attesting | |
v.证明( attest的现在分词 );证实;声称…属实;使宣誓 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 celebrated | |
adj.有名的,声誉卓著的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 requisite | |
adj.需要的,必不可少的;n.必需品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 secondly | |
adv.第二,其次 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 proceeding | |
n.行动,进行,(pl.)会议录,学报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 utterly | |
adv.完全地,绝对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 second-hand | |
adj.用过的,旧的,二手的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 rebound | |
v.弹回;n.弹回,跳回 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 admiration | |
n.钦佩,赞美,羡慕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 uncouth | |
adj.无教养的,粗鲁的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 pretensions | |
自称( pretension的名词复数 ); 自命不凡; 要求; 权力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 enthusiast | |
n.热心人,热衷者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 narrative | |
n.叙述,故事;adj.叙事的,故事体的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 persevere | |
v.坚持,坚忍,不屈不挠 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 auditors | |
n.审计员,稽核员( auditor的名词复数 );(大学课程的)旁听生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 canvass | |
v.招徕顾客,兜售;游说;详细检查,讨论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 renounce | |
v.放弃;拒绝承认,宣布与…断绝关系 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 sublime | |
adj.崇高的,伟大的;极度的,不顾后果的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 regularity | |
n.规律性,规则性;匀称,整齐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 impudence | |
n.厚颜无耻;冒失;无礼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 eloquence | |
n.雄辩;口才,修辞 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 subdues | |
征服( subdue的第三人称单数 ); 克制; 制服 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 attains | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的第三人称单数 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 itinerant | |
adj.巡回的;流动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 stationary | |
adj.固定的,静止不动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 touching | |
adj.动人的,使人感伤的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 absurdity | |
n.荒谬,愚蠢;谬论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 propensity | |
n.倾向;习性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 provincial | |
adj.省的,地方的;n.外省人,乡下人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 vehemence | |
n.热切;激烈;愤怒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 presumption | |
n.推测,可能性,冒昧,放肆,[法律]推定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 abound | |
vi.大量存在;(in,with)充满,富于 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 civilized | |
a.有教养的,文雅的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 peruse | |
v.细读,精读 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 pestilence | |
n.瘟疫 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 omens | |
n.前兆,预兆( omen的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 oracles | |
神示所( oracle的名词复数 ); 神谕; 圣贤; 哲人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 intervals | |
n.[军事]间隔( interval的名词复数 );间隔时间;[数学]区间;(戏剧、电影或音乐会的)幕间休息 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 thoroughly | |
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 extirpated | |
v.消灭,灭绝( extirpate的过去式和过去分词 );根除 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 judicious | |
adj.明智的,明断的,能作出明智决定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 perusal | |
n.细读,熟读;目测 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 prodigious | |
adj.惊人的,奇妙的;异常的;巨大的;庞大的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 frailty | |
n.脆弱;意志薄弱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 renowned | |
adj.著名的,有名望的,声誉鹊起的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 monstrous | |
adj.巨大的;恐怖的;可耻的,丢脸的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 imposture | |
n.冒名顶替,欺骗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 industrious | |
adj.勤劳的,刻苦的,奋发的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 contented | |
adj.满意的,安心的,知足的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 deride | |
v.嘲弄,愚弄 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 enlisting | |
v.(使)入伍, (使)参军( enlist的现在分词 );获得(帮助或支持) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 votaries | |
n.信徒( votary的名词复数 );追随者;(天主教)修士;修女 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 eminent | |
adj.显赫的,杰出的,有名的,优良的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 nay | |
adv.不;n.反对票,投反对票者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 sage | |
n.圣人,哲人;adj.贤明的,明智的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 delusive | |
adj.欺骗的,妄想的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 barbarians | |
n.野蛮人( barbarian的名词复数 );外国人;粗野的人;无教养的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 wrought | |
v.引起;以…原料制作;运转;adj.制造的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 indirectly | |
adv.间接地,不直接了当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 overthrow | |
v.推翻,打倒,颠覆;n.推翻,瓦解,颠覆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 lame | |
adj.跛的,(辩解、论据等)无说服力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 obedience | |
n.服从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 enjoined | |
v.命令( enjoin的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 conversed | |
v.交谈,谈话( converse的过去式 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 affected | |
adj.不自然的,假装的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 penetrating | |
adj.(声音)响亮的,尖锐的adj.(气味)刺激的adj.(思想)敏锐的,有洞察力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 antiquity | |
n.古老;高龄;古物,古迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 imputation | |
n.归罪,责难 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 atheism | |
n.无神论,不信神 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 profaneness | |
n.渎神,污秽 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 despoiled | |
v.掠夺,抢劫( despoil的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 memorable | |
adj.值得回忆的,难忘的,特别的,显著的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 cardinal | |
n.(天主教的)红衣主教;adj.首要的,基本的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 intriguing | |
adj.有趣的;迷人的v.搞阴谋诡计(intrigue的现在分词);激起…的好奇心 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 persecution | |
n. 迫害,烦扰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 stump | |
n.残株,烟蒂,讲演台;v.砍断,蹒跚而走 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 vouched | |
v.保证( vouch的过去式和过去分词 );担保;确定;确定地说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 confirmation | |
n.证实,确认,批准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 zealous | |
adj.狂热的,热心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 libertine | |
n.淫荡者;adj.放荡的,自由思想的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 counterfeit | |
vt.伪造,仿造;adj.伪造的,假冒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 mightily | |
ad.强烈地;非常地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 concurrence | |
n.同意;并发 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141 accurately | |
adv.准确地,精确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142 knavery | |
n.恶行,欺诈的行为 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143 deluded | |
v.欺骗,哄骗( delude的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144 dispersed | |
adj. 被驱散的, 被分散的, 散布的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145 magistrate | |
n.地方行政官,地方法官,治安官 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147 corroboration | |
n.进一步的证实,进一步的证据 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148 factions | |
组织中的小派别,派系( faction的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149 monkish | |
adj.僧侣的,修道士的,禁欲的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150 inclinations | |
倾向( inclination的名词复数 ); 倾斜; 爱好; 斜坡 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151 propensities | |
n.倾向,习性( propensity的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
152 missionary | |
adj.教会的,传教(士)的;n.传教士 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
153 scruples | |
n.良心上的不安( scruple的名词复数 );顾虑,顾忌v.感到于心不安,有顾忌( scruple的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
154 pious | |
adj.虔诚的;道貌岸然的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
155 meritorious | |
adj.值得赞赏的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
156 kindle | |
v.点燃,着火 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
157 infancy | |
n.婴儿期;幼年期;初期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
158 altercations | |
n.争辩,争吵( altercation的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
159 rumours | |
n.传闻( rumour的名词复数 );风闻;谣言;谣传 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
160 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
161 subtraction | |
n.减法,减去 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
162 violations | |
违反( violation的名词复数 ); 冒犯; 违反(行为、事例); 强奸 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
163 corruption | |
n.腐败,堕落,贪污 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
164 catastrophe | |
n.大灾难,大祸 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
165 interred | |
v.埋,葬( inter的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
166 judgment | |
n.审判;判断力,识别力,看法,意见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
167 artifice | |
n.妙计,高明的手段;狡诈,诡计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
168 folly | |
n.愚笨,愚蠢,蠢事,蠢行,傻话 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
169 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
170 almighty | |
adj.全能的,万能的;很大的,很强的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
171 whit | |
n.一点,丝毫 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
172 specious | |
adj.似是而非的;adv.似是而非地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
173 pretence | |
n.假装,作假;借口,口实;虚伪;虚饰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
174 scrutiny | |
n.详细检查,仔细观察 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
175 fable | |
n.寓言;童话;神话 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
176 Christians | |
n.基督教徒( Christian的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
177 corroborated | |
v.证实,支持(某种说法、信仰、理论等)( corroborate的过去式 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
178 concurring | |
同时发生的,并发的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
179 fabulous | |
adj.极好的;极为巨大的;寓言中的,传说中的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
180 deluge | |
n./vt.洪水,暴雨,使泛滥 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
181 bondage | |
n.奴役,束缚 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
182 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
183 foretell | |
v.预言,预告,预示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
184 insufficient | |
adj.(for,of)不足的,不够的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
185 subverts | |
v.颠覆,破坏(政治制度、宗教信仰等)( subvert的第三人称单数 );使(某人)道德败坏或不忠 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |