§53. Had but this one thing been well considered, without looking any deeper into the matter, it might perhaps have kept men from running into those gross mistakes, they have made, about this power of parents; which, however it might, without any great harshness, bear the name of absolute dominion10, and regal authority, when under the title of paternal power it seemed appropriated to the father, would yet have founded but oddly, and in the very name shewn the absurdity11, if this supposed absolute power over children had been called parental; and thereby12 have discovered, that it belonged to the mother too: for it will but very ill serve the turn of those men, who contend so much for the absolute power and authority of the fatherhood, as they call it, that the mother should have any share in it; and it would have but ill supported the monarchy14 they contend for, when by the very name it appeared, that that fundamental authority, from whence they would derive15 their government of a single person only, was not placed in one, but two persons jointly16. But to let this of names pass.
§54. Though I have said above, Chap. II. That all men by nature are equal, I cannot be supposed to understand all sorts of equality: age or virtue17 may give men a just precedency: excellency of parts and merit may place others above the common level: birth may subject some, and alliance or benefits others, to pay an observance to those to whom nature, gratitude18, or other respects, may have made it due: and yet all this consists with the equality, which all men are in, in respect of jurisdiction19 or dominion one over another; which was the equality I there spoke20 of, as proper to the business in hand, being that equal right, that every man hath, to his natural freedom, without being subjected to the will or authority of any other man.
§55. Children, I confess, are not born in this full state of equality, though they are born to it. Their parents have a sort of rule and jurisdiction over them, when they come into the world, and for some time after; but it is but a temporary one. The bonds of this subjection are like the swaddling clothes they art wrapt up in, and supported by, in the weakness of their infancy21: age and reason as they grow up, loosen them, till at length they drop quite off, and leave a man at his own free disposal.
§56. Adam was created a perfect man, his body and mind in full possession of their strength and reason, and so was capable, from the first instant of his being to provide for his own support and preservation22, and govern his actions according to the dictates23 of the law of reason which God had implanted in him. From him the world is peopled with his descendants, who are all born infants, weak and helpless, without knowledge or understanding: but to supply the defects of this imperfect state, till the improvement of growth and age hath removed them, Adam and Eve, and after them all parents were, by the law of nature, under an obligation to preserve, nourish, and educate the children they had begotten25; not as their own workmanship, but the workmanship of their own maker26, the Almighty27, to whom they were to be accountable for them.
§57. The law, that was to govern Adam, was the same that was to govern all his posterity28, the law of reason. But his offspring having another way of entrance into the world, different from him, by a natural birth, that produced them ignorant and without the use of reason, they were not presently under that law; for no body can be under a law, which is not promulgated29 to him; and this law being promulgated or made known by reason only, he that is not come to the use of his reason, cannot be said to be under this law; and Adam’s children, being not presently as soon as born under this law of reason, were not presently free: for law, in its true notion, is not so much the limitation as the direction of a free and intelligent agent to his proper interest, and prescribes no farther than is for the general good of those under that law: could they be happier without it, the law, as an useless thing, would of itself vanish; and that ill deserves the name of confinement30 which hedges us in only from bogs31 and precipices32. So that, however it may be mistaken, the end of law is not to abolish or restrain, but to preserve and enlarge freedom: for in all the states of created beings capable of laws, where there is no law, there is no freedom: for liberty is, to be free from restraint and violence from others; which cannot be, where there is no law: but freedom is not, as we are told, a liberty for every man to do what he lists: (for who could be free, when every other man’s humour might domineer over him?) but a liberty to dispose, and order as he lists, his person, actions, possessions, and his whole property, within the allowance of those laws under which he is, and therein not to be subject to the arbitrary will of another, but freely follow his own.
§58. The power, then, that parents have over their children, arises from that duty which is incumbent33 on them, to take care of their off-spring, during the imperfect state of childhood. To inform the mind, and govern the actions of their yet ignorant nonage, till reason shall take its place, and ease them of that trouble, is what the children want, and the parents are bound to: for God having given man an understanding to direct his actions, has allowed him a freedom of will, and liberty of acting34, as properly belonging thereunto, within the bounds of that law he is under. But whilst he is in an estate, wherein he has not understanding of his own to direct his will, he is not to have any will of his own to follow: he that understands for him, must will for him too; he must prescribe to his will, and regulate his actions; but when he comes to the estate that made his father a freeman, the son is a freeman too.
§59. This holds in all the laws a man is under, whether natural or civil. Is a man under the law of nature? What made him free of that law? what gave him a free disposing of his property, according to his own will, within the compass of that law? I answer, a state of maturity35 wherein he might be supposed capable to know that law, that so he might keep his actions within the bounds of it. When he has acquired that state, he is presumed to know how far that law is to be his guide, and how far he may make use of his freedom, and so comes to have it; till then, some body else must guide him, who is presumed to know how far the law allows a liberty. If such a state of reason, such an age of discretion36 made him free, the same shall make his son free too. Is a man under the law of England? What made him free of that law? that is, to have the liberty to dispose of his actions and possessions according to his own will, within the permission of that law? A capacity of knowing that law; which is supposed by that law, at the age of one and twenty years, and in some cases sooner. If this made the father free, it shall make the son free too. Till then we see the law allows the son to have no will, but he is to be guided by the will of his father or guardian37, who is to understand for him. And if the father die, and fail to substitute a deputy in his trust; if he hath not provided a tutor, to govern his son, during his minority, during his want of understanding, the law takes care to do it; some other must govern him, and be a will to him, till he hath attained39 to a state of freedom, and his understanding be fit to take the government of his will. But after that, the father and son are equally free as much as tutor and pupil after nonage; equally subjects of the same law together, without any dominion left in the father over the life, liberty, or estate of his son, whether they be only in the state and under the law of nature, or under the positive laws of an established government.
§60. But if, through defects that may happen out of the ordinary course of nature, any one comes not to such a degree of reason, wherein he might be supposed capable of knowing the law, and so living within the rules of it, he is never capable of being a free man, he is never let loose to the disposure of his own will (because he knows no bounds to it, has not understanding, its proper guide) but is continued under the tuition and government of others, all the time his own understanding is uncapable of that charge. And so lunatics and ideots are never set free from the government of their parents; children, who are not as yet come unto those years whereat they may have; and innocents which are excluded by a natural defect from ever having; thirdly, madmen, which for the present cannot possibly have the use of right reason to guide themselves, have for their guide, the reason that guideth other men which are tutors over them, to seek and procure40 their good for them, says Hooker, Eccl. Pol. lib. i. sec. 7. All which seems no more than that duty, which God and nature has laid on man, as well as other creatures, to preserve their offspring, till they can be able to shift for themselves, and will scarce amount to an instance or proof of parents regal authority.
§61. Thus we are born free, as we are born rational; not that we have actually the exercise of either: age, that brings one, brings with it the other too. And thus we see how natural freedom and subjection to parents may consist together, and are both founded on the same principle. A child is free by his father’s title, by his father’s understanding, which is to govern him till he hath it of his own. The freedom of a man at years of discretion, and the subjection of a child to his parents, whilst yet short of that age, are so consistent, and so distinguishable, that the most blinded contenders for monarchy, by right of fatherhood, cannot miss this difference; the most obstinate41 cannot but allow their consistency42: for were their doctrine43 all true, were the right heir of Adam now known, and by that title settled a monarch13 in his throne, invested with all the absolute unlimited44 power Sir Robert Filmer talks of; if he should die as soon as his heir were born, must not the child, notwithstanding he were never so free, never so much sovereign, be in subjection to his mother and nurse, to tutors and governors, till age and education brought him reason and ability to govern himself and others? The necessities of his life, the health of his body, and the information of his mind, would require him to be directed by the will of others, and not his own; and yet will any one think, that this restraint and subjection were inconsistent with, or spoiled him of that liberty or sovereignty he had a right to, or gave away his empire to those who had the government of his nonage? This government over him only prepared him the better and sooner for it. If any body should ask me, when my son is of age to be free? I shall answer, just when his monarch is of age to govern. But at what time, says the judicious45 Hooker, Eccl. Pol. l. i. sect. 6. a man may be said to have attained so far forth46 the use of reason, as sufficeth to make him capable of those laws whereby he is then bound to guide his actions: this is a great deal more easy for sense to discern, than for any one by skill and learning to determine.
§62. Common-wealths themselves take notice of, and allow, that there is a time when men are to begin to act like free men, and therefore till that time require not oaths of fealty47, or allegiance, or other public owning of, or submission48 to the government of their countries.
§63. The freedom then of man, and liberty of acting according to his own will, is grounded on his having reason, which is able to instruct him in that law he is to govern himself by, and make him know how far he is left to the freedom of his own will. To turn him loose to an unrestrained liberty, before he has reason to guide him, is not the allowing him the privilege of his nature to be free; but to thrust him out amongst brutes49, and abandon him to a state as wretched, and as much beneath that of a man, as their’s . This is that which puts the authority into the parents hands to govern the minority of their children. God hath made it their business to employ this care on their offspring, and hath placed in them suitable inclinations50 of tenderness and concern to temper this power, to apply it, as his wisdom designed it, to the children’s good, as long as they should need to be under it.
§64. But what reason can hence advance this care of the parents due to their off-spring into an absolute arbitrary dominion of the father, whose power reaches no farther, than by such a discipline, as he finds most effectual, to give such strength and health to their bodies, such vigour51 and rectitude to their minds, as may best fit his children to be most useful to themselves and others; and, if it be necessary to his condition, to make them work, when they are able, for their own subsistence. But in this power the mother too has her share with the father.
§65. Nay52, this power so little belongs to the father by any peculiar53 right of nature, but only as he is guardian of his children, that when he quits his care of them, he loses his power over them, which goes along with their nourishment54 and education, to which it is inseparably annexed55; and it belongs as much to the foster-father of an exposed child, as to the natural father of another. So little power does the bare act of begetting56 give a man over his issue; if all his care ends there, and this be all the title he hath to the name and authority of a father. And what will become of this paternal power in that part of the world, where one woman hath more than one husband at a time? or in those parts of America, where, when the husband and wife part, which happens frequently, the children are all left to the mother, follow her, and are wholly under her care and provision? If the father die whilst the children are young, do they not naturally every where owe the same obedience to their mother, during their minority, as to their father were he alive? and will any one say, that the mother hath a legislative57 power over her children? that she can make standing24 rules, which shall be of perpetual obligation, by which they ought to regulate all the concerns of their property, and bound their liberty all the course of their lives? or can she inforce the observation of them with capital punishments? for this is the proper power of the magistrate58, of which the father hath not so much as the shadow. His command over his children is but temporary, and reaches not their life or property: it is but a help to the weakness and imperfection of their nonage, a discipline necessary to their education: and though a father may dispose of his own possessions as he pleases, when his children are out of danger of perishing for want, yet his power extends not to the lives or goods, which either their own industry, or another’s bounty59 has made their’s; nor to their liberty neither, when they are once arrived to the infranchisement of the years of discretion. The father’s empire then ceases, and he can from thence forwards no more dispose of the liberty of his son, than that of any other man: and it must be far from an absolute or perpetual jurisdiction, from which a man may withdraw himself, having license60 from divine authority to leave father and mother, and cleave61 to his wife.
§66. But though there be a time when a child comes to be as free from subjection to the will and command of his father, as the father himself is free from subjection to the will of any body else, and they are each under no other restraint, but that which is common to them both, whether it be the law of nature, or municipal law of their country; yet this freedom exempts62 not a son from that honour which he ought, by the law of God and nature, to pay his parents. God having made the parents instruments in his great design of continuing the race of mankind, and the occasions of life to their children; as he hath laid on them an obligation to nourish, preserve, and bring up their offspring; so he has laid on the children a perpetual obligation of honouring their parents, which containing in it an inward esteem63 and reverence64 to be shewn by all outward expressions, ties up the child from any thing that may ever injure or affront65, disturb or endanger, the happiness or life of those from whom he received his; and engages him in all actions of defence, relief, assistance and comfort of those, by whose means he entered into being, and has been made capable of any enjoyments66 of life: from this obligation no state, no freedom can absolve68 children. But this is very far from giving parents a power of command over their children, or an authority to make laws and dispose as they please of their lives or liberties. It is one thing to owe honour, respect, gratitude and assistance; another to require an absolute obedience and submission. The honour due to parents, a monarch in his throne owes his mother; and yet this lessens69 not his authority, nor subjects him to her government.
§67. The subjection of a minor38 places in the father a temporary government, which terminates with the minority of the child: and the honour due from a child, places in the parents a perpetual right to respect, reverence, support and compliance70 too, more or less, as the father’s care, cost, and kindness in his education, has been more or less. This ends not with minority, but holds in all parts and conditions of a man’s life. The want of distinguishing these two powers, viz. that which the father hath in the right of tuition, during minority, and the right of honour all his life, may perhaps have caused a great part of the mistakes about this matter: for to speak properly of them, the first of these is rather the privilege of children, and duty of parents, than any prerogative71 of paternal power. The nourishment and education of their children is a charge so incumbent on parents for their children’s good, that nothing can absolve them from taking care of it: and though the power of commanding and chastising72 them go along with it, yet God hath woven into the principles of human nature such a tenderness for their off-spring, that there is little fear that parents should use their power with too much rigour; the excess is seldom on the severe side, the strong byass of nature drawing the other way. And therefore God almighty when he would express his gentle dealing73 with the Israelites, he tells them, that though he chastened them, he chastened them as a man chastens his son, Deut. viii. 5. i.e. with tenderness and affection, and kept them under no severer discipline than what was absolutely best for them, and had been less kindness to have slackened. This is that power to which children are commanded obedience, that the pains and care of their parents may not be increased, or ill rewarded.
§68. On the other side, honour and support, all that which gratitude requires to return for the benefits received by and from them, is the indispensable duty of the child, and the proper privilege of the parents. This is intended for the parents advantage, as the other is for the child’s; though education, the parents duty, seems to have most power, because the ignorance and infirmities of childhood stand in need of restraint and correction; which is a visible exercise of rule, and a kind of dominion. And that duty which is comprehended in the word honour, requires less obedience, though the obligation be stronger on grown, than younger children: for who can think the command, Children obey your parents, requires in a man, that has children of his own, the same submission to his father, as it does in his yet young children to him; and that by this precept74 he were bound to obey all his father’s commands, if, out of a conceit75 of authority, he should have the indiscretion to treat him still as a boy?
§69. The first part then of paternal power, or rather duty, which is education, belongs so to the father, that it terminates at a certain season; when the business of education is over, it ceases of itself, and is also alienable before: for a man may put the tuition of his son in other hands; and he that has made his son an apprentice76 to another, has discharged him, during that time, of a great part of his obedience both to himself and to his mother. But all the duty of honour, the other part, remains77 never the less entire to them; nothing can cancel that: it is so inseparable from them both, that the father’s authority cannot dispossess the mother of this right, nor can any man discharge his son from honouring her that bore him. But both these are very far from a power to make laws, and enforcing them with penalties, that may reach estate, liberty, limbs and life. The power of commanding ends with nonage; and though, after that, honour and respect, support and defence, and whatsoever78 gratitude can oblige a man to, for the highest benefits he is naturally capable of, be always due from a son to his parents; yet all this puts no scepter into the father’s hand, no sovereign power of commanding. He has no dominion over his son’s property, or actions; nor any right, that his will should prescribe to his son’s in all things; however it may become his son in many things, not very inconvenient79 to him and his family, to pay a deference80 to it.
§70. A man may owe honour and respect to an ancient, or wise man; defence to his child or friend; relief and support to the distressed81; and gratitude to a benefactor82, to such a degree, that all he has, all he can do, cannot sufficiently83 pay it: but all these give no authority, no right to any one, of making laws over him from whom they are owing. And it is plain, all this is due not only to the bare title of father; not only because, as has been said, it is owing to the mother too; but because these obligations to parents, and the degrees of what is required of children, may be varied84 by the different care and kindness, trouble and expence, which is often employed upon one child more than another.
§71. This shews the reason how it comes to pass, that parents in societies, where they themselves are subjects, retain a power over their children, and have as much right to their subjection, as those who are in the state of nature. Which could not possibly be, if all political power were only paternal, and that in truth they were one and the same thing: for then, all paternal power being in the prince, the subject could naturally have none of it. But these two powers, political and paternal, are so perfectly86 distinct and separate; are built upon so different foundations, and given to so different ends, that every subject that is a father, has as much a paternal power over his children, as the prince has over his: and every prince, that has parents, owes them as much filial duty and obedience, as the meanest of his subjects do to their’s; and can therefore contain not any part or degree of that kind of dominion, which a prince or magistrate has over his subject.
§72. Though the obligation on the parents to bring up their children, and the obligation on children to honour their parents, contain all the power on the one hand, and submission on the other, which are proper to this relation, yet there is another power ordinarily in the father, whereby he has a tie on the obedience of his children; which tho’ it be common to him with other men, yet the occasions of shewing it, almost constantly happening to fathers in their private families, and the instances of it elsewhere being rare, and less taken notice of, it passes in the world for a part of paternal jurisdiction. And this is the power men generally have to bestow87 their estates on those who please them best; the possession of the father being the expectation and inheritance of the children, ordinarily in certain proportions, according to the law and custom of each country; yet it is commonly in the father’s power to bestow it with a more sparing or liberal hand, according as the behaviour of this or that child hath comported88 with his will and humour.
§73. This is no small tie on the obedience of children: and there being always annexed to the enjoyment67 of land, a submission to the government of the country, of which that land is a part; it has been commonly supposed, that a father could oblige his posterity to that government, of which he himself was a subject, and that his compact held them; whereas, it being only a necessary condition annexed to the land, and the inheritance of an estate which is under that government, reaches only those who will take it on that condition, and so is no natural tie or engagement, but a voluntary submission: for every man’s children being by nature as free as himself, or any of his ancestors ever were, may, whilst they are in that freedom, choose what society they will join themselves to, what common-wealth they will put themselves under. But if they will enjoy the inheritance of their ancestors, they must take it on the same terms their ancestors had it, and submit to all the conditions annexed to such a possession. By this power indeed fathers oblige their children to obedience to themselves, even when they are past minority, and most commonly too subject them to this or that political power: but neither of these by any peculiar right of fatherhood, but by the reward they have in their hands to inforce and recompence such a compliance; and is no more power than what a French man has over an English man, who by the hopes of an estate he will leave him, will certainly have a strong tie on his obedience: and if, when it is left him, he will enjoy it, he must certainly take it upon the conditions annexed to the possession of land in that country where it lies, whether it be France or England.
§74. To conclude then, tho’ the father’s power of commanding extends no farther than the minority of his children, and to a degree only fit for the discipline and government of that age; and tho’ that honour and respect, and all that which the Latins called piety89, which they indispensably owe to their parents all their life-time, and in all estates, with all that support and defence is due to them, gives the father no power of governing, i.e. making laws and enacting90 penalties on his children; though by all this he has no dominion over the property or actions of his son: yet it is obvious to conceive how easy it was, in the first ages of the world, and in places still, where the thinness of people gives families leave to separate into unpossessed quarters, and they have room to remove or plant themselves in yet vacant habitations, for the father of the family to become the prince of* it; he had been a ruler from the beginning of the infancy of his children: and since without some government it would be hard for them to live together, it was likeliest it should, by the express or tacit consent of the children when they were grown up, be in the father, where it seemed without any change barely to continue; when indeed nothing more was required to it, than the permitting the father to exercise alone, in his family, that executive power of the law of nature, which every free man naturally hath, and by that permission resigning up to him a monarchical91 power, whilst they remained in it. But that this was not by any paternal right, but only by the consent of his children, is evident from hence, that no body doubts, but if a stranger, whom chance or business had brought to his family, had there killed any of his children, or committed any other fact, he might condemn92 and put him to death, or other-wise have punished him, as well as any of his children; which it was impossible he should do by virtue of any paternal authority over one who was not his child, but by virtue of that executive power of the law of nature, which, as a man, he had a right to: and he alone could punish him in his family, where the respect of his children had laid by the exercise of such a power, to give way to the dignity and authority they were willing should remain in him, above the rest of his family.
(*It is no improbable opinion therefore, which the archphilosopher was of, that the chief person in every houshold was always, as it were, a king: so when numbers of housholds joined themselves in civil societies together, kings were the first kind of governors amongst them, which is also, as it seemeth, the reason why the name of fathers continued still in them, who, of fathers, were made rulers; as also the ancient custom of governors to do as Melchizedec, and being kings, to exercise the office of priests, which fathers did at the first, grew perhaps by the same occasion. Howbeit, this is not the only kind of regiment93 that has been received in the world. The inconveniences of one kind have caused sundry94 others to be devised; so that in a word, all public regiment, of what kind soever, seemeth evidently to have risen from the deliberate advice, consultation95 and composition between men, judging it convenient and behoveful; there being no impossibility in nature considered by itself, but that man might have lived without any public regiment, Hooker’s Eccl. Pol. lib. i. sect. 10.)
§75. Thus it was easy, and almost natural for children, by a tacit, and scarce avoidable consent, to make way for the father’s authority and government. They had been accustomed in their childhood to follow his direction, and to refer their little differences to him, and when they were men, who fitter to rule them? Their little properties, and less covetousness96, seldom afforded greater controversies97; and when any should arise, where could they have a fitter umpire than he, by whose care they had every one been sustained and brought up, and who had a tenderness for them all? It is no wonder that they made no distinction betwixt minority and full age; nor looked after one and twenty, or any other age that might make them the free disposers of themselves and fortunes, when they could have no desire to be out of their pupilage: the government they had been under, during it, continued still to be more their protection than restraint; and they could no where find a greater security to their peace, liberties, and fortunes, than in the rule of a father.
§76. Thus the natural fathers of families, by an insensible change, became the politic85 monarchs98 of them too: and as they chanced to live long, and leave able and worthy99 heirs, for several successions, or otherwise; so they laid the foundations of hereditary100, or elective kingdoms, under several constitutions and mannors, according as chance, contrivance, or occasions happened to mould them. But if princes have their titles in their fathers right, and it be a sufficient proof of the natural right of fathers to political authority, because they commonly were those in whose hands we find, de facto, the exercise of government: I say, if this argument be good, it will as strongly prove, that all princes, nay princes only, ought to be priests, since it is as certain, that in the beginning, the father of the family was priest, as that he was ruler in his own houshold.
![](../../../skin/default/image/4.jpg)
点击
收听单词发音
![收听单词发音](/template/default/tingnovel/images/play.gif)
1
sect
![]() |
|
n.派别,宗教,学派,派系 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2
censured
![]() |
|
v.指责,非难,谴责( censure的过去式 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3
discourse
![]() |
|
n.论文,演说;谈话;话语;vi.讲述,著述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4
paternal
![]() |
|
adj.父亲的,像父亲的,父系的,父方的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5
parental
![]() |
|
adj.父母的;父的;母的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6
bind
![]() |
|
vt.捆,包扎;装订;约束;使凝固;vi.变硬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7
concurrent
![]() |
|
adj.同时发生的,一致的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8
obedience
![]() |
|
n.服从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9
testament
![]() |
|
n.遗嘱;证明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10
dominion
![]() |
|
n.统治,管辖,支配权;领土,版图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11
absurdity
![]() |
|
n.荒谬,愚蠢;谬论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12
thereby
![]() |
|
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13
monarch
![]() |
|
n.帝王,君主,最高统治者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14
monarchy
![]() |
|
n.君主,最高统治者;君主政体,君主国 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15
derive
![]() |
|
v.取得;导出;引申;来自;源自;出自 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16
jointly
![]() |
|
ad.联合地,共同地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17
virtue
![]() |
|
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18
gratitude
![]() |
|
adj.感激,感谢 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19
jurisdiction
![]() |
|
n.司法权,审判权,管辖权,控制权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20
spoke
![]() |
|
n.(车轮的)辐条;轮辐;破坏某人的计划;阻挠某人的行动 v.讲,谈(speak的过去式);说;演说;从某种观点来说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21
infancy
![]() |
|
n.婴儿期;幼年期;初期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22
preservation
![]() |
|
n.保护,维护,保存,保留,保持 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23
dictates
![]() |
|
n.命令,规定,要求( dictate的名词复数 )v.大声讲或读( dictate的第三人称单数 );口授;支配;摆布 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24
standing
![]() |
|
n.持续,地位;adj.永久的,不动的,直立的,不流动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25
begotten
![]() |
|
v.为…之生父( beget的过去分词 );产生,引起 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26
maker
![]() |
|
n.制造者,制造商 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27
almighty
![]() |
|
adj.全能的,万能的;很大的,很强的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28
posterity
![]() |
|
n.后裔,子孙,后代 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29
promulgated
![]() |
|
v.宣扬(某事物)( promulgate的过去式和过去分词 );传播;公布;颁布(法令、新法律等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30
confinement
![]() |
|
n.幽禁,拘留,监禁;分娩;限制,局限 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31
bogs
![]() |
|
n.沼泽,泥塘( bog的名词复数 );厕所v.(使)陷入泥沼, (使)陷入困境( bog的第三人称单数 );妨碍,阻碍 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32
precipices
![]() |
|
n.悬崖,峭壁( precipice的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33
incumbent
![]() |
|
adj.成为责任的,有义务的;现任的,在职的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34
acting
![]() |
|
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35
maturity
![]() |
|
n.成熟;完成;(支票、债券等)到期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36
discretion
![]() |
|
n.谨慎;随意处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37
guardian
![]() |
|
n.监护人;守卫者,保护者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38
minor
![]() |
|
adj.较小(少)的,较次要的;n.辅修学科;vi.辅修 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39
attained
![]() |
|
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40
procure
![]() |
|
vt.获得,取得,促成;vi.拉皮条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41
obstinate
![]() |
|
adj.顽固的,倔强的,不易屈服的,较难治愈的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42
consistency
![]() |
|
n.一贯性,前后一致,稳定性;(液体的)浓度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43
doctrine
![]() |
|
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44
unlimited
![]() |
|
adj.无限的,不受控制的,无条件的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45
judicious
![]() |
|
adj.明智的,明断的,能作出明智决定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46
forth
![]() |
|
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47
fealty
![]() |
|
n.忠贞,忠节 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48
submission
![]() |
|
n.服从,投降;温顺,谦虚;提出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49
brutes
![]() |
|
兽( brute的名词复数 ); 畜生; 残酷无情的人; 兽性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50
inclinations
![]() |
|
倾向( inclination的名词复数 ); 倾斜; 爱好; 斜坡 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51
vigour
![]() |
|
(=vigor)n.智力,体力,精力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52
nay
![]() |
|
adv.不;n.反对票,投反对票者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53
peculiar
![]() |
|
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54
nourishment
![]() |
|
n.食物,营养品;营养情况 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55
annexed
![]() |
|
[法] 附加的,附属的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56
begetting
![]() |
|
v.为…之生父( beget的现在分词 );产生,引起 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57
legislative
![]() |
|
n.立法机构,立法权;adj.立法的,有立法权的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58
magistrate
![]() |
|
n.地方行政官,地方法官,治安官 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59
bounty
![]() |
|
n.慷慨的赠予物,奖金;慷慨,大方;施与 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60
license
![]() |
|
n.执照,许可证,特许;v.许可,特许 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61
cleave
![]() |
|
v.(clave;cleaved)粘着,粘住;坚持;依恋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62
exempts
![]() |
|
使免除[豁免]( exempt的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63
esteem
![]() |
|
n.尊敬,尊重;vt.尊重,敬重;把…看作 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64
reverence
![]() |
|
n.敬畏,尊敬,尊严;Reverence:对某些基督教神职人员的尊称;v.尊敬,敬畏,崇敬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65
affront
![]() |
|
n./v.侮辱,触怒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66
enjoyments
![]() |
|
愉快( enjoyment的名词复数 ); 令人愉快的事物; 享有; 享受 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67
enjoyment
![]() |
|
n.乐趣;享有;享用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68
absolve
![]() |
|
v.赦免,解除(责任等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69
lessens
![]() |
|
变少( lessen的第三人称单数 ); 减少(某事物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70
compliance
![]() |
|
n.顺从;服从;附和;屈从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71
prerogative
![]() |
|
n.特权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72
chastising
![]() |
|
v.严惩(某人)(尤指责打)( chastise的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73
dealing
![]() |
|
n.经商方法,待人态度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74
precept
![]() |
|
n.戒律;格言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75
conceit
![]() |
|
n.自负,自高自大 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76
apprentice
![]() |
|
n.学徒,徒弟 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77
remains
![]() |
|
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78
whatsoever
![]() |
|
adv.(用于否定句中以加强语气)任何;pron.无论什么 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79
inconvenient
![]() |
|
adj.不方便的,令人感到麻烦的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80
deference
![]() |
|
n.尊重,顺从;敬意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81
distressed
![]() |
|
痛苦的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82
benefactor
![]() |
|
n. 恩人,行善的人,捐助人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83
sufficiently
![]() |
|
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84
varied
![]() |
|
adj.多样的,多变化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85
politic
![]() |
|
adj.有智虑的;精明的;v.从政 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86
perfectly
![]() |
|
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87
bestow
![]() |
|
v.把…赠与,把…授予;花费 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88
comported
![]() |
|
v.表现( comport的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89
piety
![]() |
|
n.虔诚,虔敬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90
enacting
![]() |
|
制定(法律),通过(法案)( enact的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91
monarchical
![]() |
|
adj. 国王的,帝王的,君主的,拥护君主制的 =monarchic | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92
condemn
![]() |
|
vt.谴责,指责;宣判(罪犯),判刑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93
regiment
![]() |
|
n.团,多数,管理;v.组织,编成团,统制 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94
sundry
![]() |
|
adj.各式各样的,种种的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95
consultation
![]() |
|
n.咨询;商量;商议;会议 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96
covetousness
![]() |
|
参考例句: |
|
|
97
controversies
![]() |
|
争论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98
monarchs
![]() |
|
君主,帝王( monarch的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99
worthy
![]() |
|
adj.(of)值得的,配得上的;有价值的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100
hereditary
![]() |
|
adj.遗传的,遗传性的,可继承的,世袭的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |