In my last address I left Doctor Franklin predicting to the discouraged remnant of the constitutional convention that the nation then formed would be a "rising sun" in the constellation1 of the nations. The sun, however, was destined2 to rise through a bank of dark and murky3 clouds, for the Constitution could not take effect until it was ratified4 by nine of the thirteen States; and when it was submitted to the people, who selected State conventions for the purpose of ratifying5 or rejecting the proposed plan of government, a bitter controversy6 at once ensued between two political parties, then in process of formation, one called the Constitution ratified without controversy. In the remaining ten the struggle was long and arduous7, and nearly a year passed before the requisite8 nine States gave their assent9. Two of the States refused to become parts of the new nation, even after it began, and three years passed before the thirteen States were re-united under the Constitution.
It could not have been ratified had there not been an assurance that there would be immediate10 amendments12 to provide a Bill of Rights to safeguard the individual. Thus came into existence the first ten amendments to the Constitution, with their perpetual guaranty of the fundamental rights of religion, freedom of speech and of the Press, the right of assemblage, the immunity14 from unreasonable16 searches and seizures17, the right of trial by jury, and similar guarantees of fundamental individual rights.
Distrustful as the American people were of the new Constitution, they yet had the political sagacity to prefer its imperfections, whatever they imagined them to be, to the mad spirit of innovation; and in order that the great instrument should not, through the excesses of party passion or the temporary caprices of fleeting18 generations, speedily become a mere19 "scrap20 of paper" they very wisely provided that no amendment11 should, in the future, be made unless it was proposed by at least two-thirds of the Senate and the House of Representatives and ratified by three-fourths of the States through their legislatures or through special conventions. This was only one of many striking negations of the principle of majority rule. As a result of this provision, if we count the first ten amendments as virtually part of the original document, only nine amendments have been adopted in 185 years, and of these, excepting the amendments which ended slavery as the result of the Civil War, only the last three, passed in recent years partly through the relaxing influence of the world war, mark a serious departure from the basic principles of the Constitution.
This stability is the more remarkable22 when we recall the profound and revolutionary change that has taken place in the social life of man since the Constitution was adopted. It was framed at the very end of the pastoral-agricultural age of humanity. The industrial revolution, which has more profoundly affected23 man in the last century and a half than all the changes which had theretofore taken place in the life of man since the cave-dweller, was only then beginning. Measured in terms of mechanical power, men when the Constitution was formed were Lilliputians as compared with the Brobdingnagians of our day, when man outflies the eagle, outswims the fish, and by his conquest and utilization24 of the invisible forces of nature has become the superman; and yet the Constitution of 1787 is, in most of its essential principles, still the Constitution of 1922. This surely marks it as a marvel25 in statecraft and can only be explained by the fact that the Constitution was developed by a people who, as "children brave and free of the great mother-tongue," had a real genius for self-government and its essential element, the spirit of self-restraint.
While it is true that the text of the instrument has suffered almost as little change as the Nicene Creed26, yet it would be manifest error to suggest that in its development by practical application the Constitution has not undergone great changes.
The first and greatest of all its expounders, Chief Justice Marshall, said, in one of his greatest opinions, that the Constitution was—
"intended to endure for ages to come, and consequently to be adapted to the various crises of human affairs. To have prescribed the means by which government should in all future times execute its powers would have been to change entirely27 the character of the instrument and to give it the properties of a legal code. It would have been an unwise attempt to provide by immutable28 rules for exigencies29 which, if foreseen at all, must have been foreseen dimly, and can best be provided for as they occur."
In this great purpose of enumerating30 rather than defining the powers of government its framers were supremely31 wise. While it was marvellously sagacious in what it provided, it was wise to the point of inspiration in what it left unprovided.
Nothing is more admirable than the self-restraint of men who, venturing upon an untried experiment, and after debating for four months upon the principles of government, were content to embody33 their conclusions in not more than four thousand words. To this we owe the elasticity34 of the instrument. Its vitality35 is due to the fact that, by usage, judicial36 interpretation37, and, when necessary, formal amendment, it can be thus adapted to the ever-accelerating changes of the most progressive age in history, and that a people have administered the Constitution who, in the process of such adaptation, have generally shown the same spirit of conservative self-restraint as did the men who framed it.
The Constitution is neither, on the one hand, a Gibraltar rock, which wholly resists the ceaseless washing of time or circumstance, nor is it, on the other hand, a sandy beach, which is slowly destroyed by the erosion of the waves. It is rather to be likened to a floating dock, which, while firmly attached to its moorings, and not therefore the caprice of the waves, yet rises and falls with the tide of time and circumstance.
While in its practical adaptation to this complex age the men who framed it, if they could "revisit the glimpses of the moon," would as little recognize their own handiwork as their own nation, yet they would still be able to find in successful operation the essential principles which they embodied38 in the document more than a century ago.
Its success is also due to the fact that its framers were little influenced by the spirit of doctrinarianism. They were not empiricists, but very practical men. This is the more remarkable because they worked in a period of an emotional fermentation of human thought. The long-repressed intellect of man had broken into a violent eruption39 like that of a seemingly extinct volcano.
From the middle of the eighteenth century until the end of the French Revolution the masses everywhere were influenced by the emotional, and at times hysterical40, abstractions of the French encyclopedists; and that these had influenced thought in the American colonies is readily shown in the preamble41 of the Declaration of Independence, with its unqualified assertion of the equality of men and the absolute right of self-determination. The Declaration sought in its noble idealism to make the "world safe for democracy," but the Constitution attempted the greater task of making democracy safe for the world by inducing a people to impose upon themselves salutary restraints upon majority rule.
Fortunately, the framers of the Constitution had learned a rude and terrible lesson in the anarchy43 that had followed the War of Independence. They were not so much concerned about the rights of man as about his duties, and their great purpose was to substitute for the visionary idealism of a rampant44 individualism the authority of law. Of the hysteria of that time, which was about to culminate45 in the French Revolution, there is no trace in the Constitution.
They were less concerned about Rousseau's social contract than to restore law and order. Hard realities and not generous and impossible abstractions interested them. They had suffered grievously for more than ten years from misrule and had a distaste for mere phrase-making, of which they had had a satiety46, for the Constitution, in which there is not a wasted word, is as cold and dry a document as a problem in mathematics or a manual of parliamentary law. Its mandates47 have the simplicity49 and directness of the Ten Commandments, and, like the Decalogue, it consists more of what shall not be done than what shall be done. In this freedom from empiricism and sturdy adherence50 to the realities of life, it can be profitably commended to all nations which may attempt a similar task.
While the Constitution apparently51 only deals with the practical and essential details of government, yet underlying52 these simply but wonderfully phrased delegations53 of power is a broad and accurate political philosophy, which goes far to state the "law and the prophets" of free government.
These essential principles of the Constitution may be briefly54 summarized as follows:
1.
The first is representative government.
Nothing is more striking in the debates of the convention than the distrust of its members, with few exceptions, of what they called "democracy." By this term they meant the power of the people to legislate55 directly and without the intervention56 of chosen representatives. They believed that the utmost concession57 that could be safely made to democracy was the power to select suitable men to legislate for the common good, and nothing is more striking in the Constitution than the care with which they sought to remove the powers of legislation from the direct action of the people. Nowhere in the instrument is there a suggestion of the initiative or referendum.
Even an amendment to the Constitution could not be directly proposed by the people in the exercise of their residual58 power or adopted by them. As previously59 said, it could only be proposed by two-thirds of the House and the Senate, and then could only become effective, if ratified by three-fourths of the States, acting60, not by a popular vote, but through their chosen representatives either in their legislatures or special conventions. Thus they denied the power of a majority to alter even the form of government. Moreover, they gave to the President the power to nullify laws passed by a majority of the House and Senate by his simple veto, and yet, fearful of an unqualified power of the President in this respect, they provided that the veto itself should be vetoed, if two-thirds of the Senate and House concurred62 in such action. Moreover, the great limitations of the Constitution, which forbid the majority, or even the whole body of the House and Senate, to pass laws either for want of authority or because they impair63 fundamental rights of individuals, are as emphatic64 a negation21 of an absolute democracy as can be found in any form of government.
Measured by present-day conventions of democracy, the Constitution is an undemocratic document. The framers believed in representative government, to which they gave the name "Republicanism" as the antithesis66 to "democracy." The members of the Senate were to be selected by State legislatures, and the President himself was, as originally planned, to be selected by an electoral college similar to the College of Cardinals67.
The debates are full of utterances68 which explain this attitude of mind. Mr. Gerry said: "The evils we experience flow from the excesses of democracy. The people are the dupes of pretended patriots69." Mr. Randolph, the author of the Virginia plan, observed that the general object of the Constitution was to provide a cure for the evils under which the United States laboured; that in tracing these evils to their origin every man had found it in the tribulation70 and follies71 of democracy; that some check, therefore, was to be sought for against this tendency of our Government.
Alexander Hamilton remarked, on June 18, that—
"the members most tenacious72 of republicanism were as loud as any in declaiming against the evils of democracy."
He added:
"Give all the power to the many and they will oppress the few. Give all the power to the few and they will oppress the many. Both ought, therefore, to have the power that each may defend itself against the other."
Perhaps the attitude of the members is thus best expressed by James
Madison, in the 10th of the Federalist papers:
"A pure democracy, by which I mean a State consisting of a small number of citizens, who assemble and administer the government in person, can admit of no cure for the mischiefs73 of faction74. Such democracies have ever been spectacles of turbulence75 and contention76, and have often been found incompatible77 with the personal security and rights of property, and have generally been as short in their lives as they have been violent in their deaths."
Undoubtedly78, the framers of the Constitution in thus limiting popular rule did not take sufficient account of the genius of an English-speaking people. A few of their number recognized this. Franklin, a self-made man, believed in democracy and doubted the efficacy of the Constitution unless it was, like a pyramid, broad-based upon the will of the people.
Colonel Mason, of Virginia, who was also of the Jeffersonian school of political philosophy, said:
"Notwithstanding the oppression and injustice79 experienced among us from democracy, the genius of the people is in favour of it, and the genius of the people must be consulted."
In this they were true prophets, for the American people have refused to limit democracy as narrowly and rigidly80 as the framers of the Constitution clearly intended. The most notable illustration of this is the selection of the President. It was never contemplated81 that the people should directly select the President, but that a chosen body of electors should, with careful deliberation, make this momentous82 choice. While, in form, the system persists to this day, from the very beginning the electors simply vote as the people who select them desire. It should here be noted83 that Thomas Jefferson, the great Democrat65 and draftsman of the Declaration of Independence, was not a member of the convention. During its sessions he was in France. He was instrumental in securing the first ten Amendments and the subsequent adaptation of the Constitution to meet the democratic instincts of the American people is largely due to his great leadership.
Moreover, the spirit of representative government has greatly changed since the Constitution was adopted. The ideal of the earlier time was that so nobly expressed by Edmund Burke in his address to the electors of Bristol, for the framers believed that a representative held a judicial position of the most sacred character, and that he should vote as his judgment84 and conscience dictated85 without respect to the wishes of his constituents86. To-day, and notably88 in the last half century, the contrary belief, due largely to Jefferson's political ideals, has so influenced American politics that the representatives of the people, either in the legislature or the executive departments of the government, are considered by the masses as only the mouthpieces of the people who select them, and to ignore their wishes is regarded as virtually a betrayal of a trust and the negation of democracy.
For this change in attitude there has been much justification89, for in my country, as elsewhere, the people do not always select their best men as representatives, and, with the imperfections of human nature, there has been so much of ignorance and, at times, venality90, that the instinct of the people is to take the conduct of affairs into their own hands. On the other hand, this change of attitude has led, in many instances, to government by organized minorities, for, with the division of the masses into political parties, it is easy for an organized minority to hold the balance of power, and thus impress its will upon majorities. Time may yet vindicate91 the theory of the framers that the limit of democracy is the selection of true and tried representatives.
2.
The second and most novel principle of the Constitution is its dual13 form of Government.
This did constitute a unique contribution to the science of politics. This was early recognized by de Tocqueville, one of the most acute students of the Constitution, who said that it was based "upon a wholly, novel theory, which may be considered a great discovery in modern political science."
Previous to the Constitution it had not been thought possible to divide sovereignty, or at least to have two different sovereignties moving as planets in the same orbit. Therefore, all previous federated governments had been based upon the plan that a league could only effect its will through the constituent87 States and that the citizens in these States owed no direct allegiance to the league, but only to the States of which they were members. The Constitution, however, developed the idea of a dual citizenship92. While the people remained citizens of their respective States in the sphere of government which was reserved to the States, yet they directly became citizens of the central government, and, as such, ceased to be citizens of the several States in the sphere of government delegated to the central power; and this allegiance was enforced by the direct action of the central government on the citizens as individuals. Thus has been developed one of the most intricately complex governmental systems in the world.
At the time of the adoption93 of the Constitution this division of jurisdiction94 was quite feasible, for, geographically95, the various States were widely separated, and the lack of economic contact made it easy for each government to function without serious conflict. The framers, however, did not sufficiently96 reckon with the mechanical changes in society that were then beginning. They did not anticipate, and could not have anticipated, the centripetal97 influences of steam and electricity which have woven the American people into an indissoluble unit for commercial and many other purposes. As a result many laws of the Federal Government, in their incidences in this complex age, directly impinge upon rights of the State governments, and vice98 versa, and the practical application of the Constitution has required a very subtle adaptation of a form of government which was enacted99 in a primitive100 age to a form of government of a complex age.
Take, for example, the power over commerce. According to the Constitution, the Federal Government had plenary power over foreign commerce and commerce between the States, but the power over commerce within a State was reserved to State governments. This presupposed the power of Government to divide commerce into two water-tight compartments101, or, at least, to regard the two spheres of power as parallel lines that would never meet; whereas with the coming of the railroad, steamship102 and the telegraph commerce has become so unified103 that the parallel lines have become lines of interlacing zigzags104. To adapt the commerce clause of the Constitution to these changed conditions has required, in the highest degree, the constructive105 genius of the Supreme32 Court of the United States, and, in a series of very remarkable decisions, which are contained in 256 volumes of the official reports, that great tribunal has tried to draw a line between inter-State and domestic commerce as nearly to the original plans of the framers as it was possible; but obviously there has been so much adaptation to make this possible that if Washington, Franklin, Madison and Hamilton could revisit the nation they created they would not recognize their own handiwork.
For the same reason, the dual system of government has been profoundly modified by the great elemental forces of our mechanical age, so that the scales, which try to hold in nice equipoise the Federal Government on the one hand and the States on the other, have been greatly disturbed. Originally, the States were the powerful political entities106, and the central government a mere agent for certain specific purposes; but, in the development of the Constitution, the nation has naturally become of overshadowing importance, while the States have relatively107 steadily108 diminished in power and prestige.
These inevitable109 tendencies in American politics are called "centralization," and while for nearly a century a great political party bitterly contested its steady progress, due to the centripetal influences above indicated, yet the contest was long since abandoned as a hopeless one, and the struggle to-day is rather to keep, so far as possible, the inevitable tendency measurably in check.
Nevertheless, it would be erroneous to suggest that the dual system of government is a failure. It still endures in providing a large measure of authority to the States in their purely110 domestic concerns, and, in a country that extends from the Atlantic to the Pacific, and from the Lakes to the Gulf111, whose northern border is not very far from the Arctic Circle, and whose southern border is not many degrees from the Equator, there are such differences in the habits, conventions, and ideals of the people that without this dual form of government the Constitution would long since have broken down. It is not too much to say that the success with which the framers of the Constitution reconciled national supremacy112 and efficiency with local self-government is one of the great achievements in the history of mankind.
3.
The third principle was the guaranty of individual liberty through constitutional limitations.
This marked another great contribution of America to the science of government. In all previous government building, the State was regarded as a sovereign, which could grant to individuals or classes, out of its plenary power, certain privileges or exemptions113, which were called "liberties." Thus the liberties which the barons114 wrung115 from King John at Runnymede were virtually exemptions from the power of government. Our fathers did not believe in the sovereignty of the State in the sense of absolute power, nor did they believe in the sovereignty of the people in that sense. The word "sovereignty" will not be found in the Constitution or the Declaration of Independence. They believed that each individual, as a responsible moral being, had certain "inalienable rights" which neither the State nor the people could rightfully take from him.
This conception of individualism, enforced in courts of law against executives and legislatures, was wholly new and is the distinguishing characteristic of American constitutionalism. As to such reserved rights, guaranteed by Constitutional limitations, and largely by the first ten amendments to the Constitution, a man, by virtue116 of his inherent and God-given dignity as a human soul, has rights, such as freedom of the Press, liberty of speech, property rights, and religious freedom, which even one hundred millions of people cannot rightfully take from him, without amending117 the Constitution. The framers did not believe that the oil of anointing that was supposed to sanctify the monarch118 and give him infallibility had fallen upon the "multitudinous tongue" of the people to give it either infallibility or omnipotence119. They believed in individualism. They were animated120 by a sleepless121 jealousy122 of governmental power. They believed that the greater such power, the greater the danger of its abuse. They felt that the individual could generally best work out his own salvation123, and that his constant prayer to Government was that of Diogenes to Alexander: "Keep out of my sunlight." The worth and dignity of the human soul, the free competition of man and man, the nobility of labour, the right to work, free from the tyranny of state or class, this was their gospel. Socialism was to them abhorrent124.
This theory of government gave a new dignity to manhood. It said to the State: "There is a limit to your power. Thus far and no further, and here shall thy proud waves be stayed."
4.
Closely allied125 to this doctrine126 of limited governmental powers, even by a majority, is the fourth principle of an independent judiciary.
It is the balance wheel of the Constitution, and to function it must be beyond the possibility of attack and destruction. My country was founded upon the rock of property rights and the sanctity of contracts. Both the nation and the several States are forbidden to impair the obligation of contracts, or take away life, liberty, or property "without due process of law." The guarantee is as old as Magna Charta; for "due process of law" is but a paraphrase127 of "the law of the land," without which no freeman could be deprived of his liberties or possessions.
"Due process of law" means that there are certain fundamental principles of liberty, not defined or even enumerated128 in the Constitution, but having their sanction in the free and enlightened conscience of just men, and that no man can be deprived of life, liberty, or property, except in conformity129 with these fundamental decencies of liberty. To protect these even against the will of a majority, however large, the judiciary was given unprecedented130 powers. It threw about the individual the solemn circle of the law. It made the judiciary the final conscience of the nation. Your nation cherishes the same primal131 verities132 of liberty, but with you, the people in Parliament, is the final judge. We, however, are not content that a majority of the Legislature shall override133 inviolable individual rights, about which the judiciary is empowered to throw the solemn circle of the law.
This august power has won the admiration134 of the world, and by many is regarded as a novel contribution to the science of government. The idea, however, was not wholly novel. As previously shown, four Chief Justices of England had declared that an Act of Parliament, if against common right and reason, could be treated as null and void; while in France the power of the judiciary to refuse efficacy to a law, unless sanctioned by the judiciary, had been the cause of a long struggle for at least three centuries between the French monarch and the courts of France. However, in England the doctrine of the common law yielded to the later doctrine of the omnipotence of Parliament, while in France the revisory power of the judiciary was terminated by the French Revolution.
The United States, however, embodied it in its form of government and thus made the judiciary, and especially the Supreme Court, the balance wheel of the Constitution. Without such power the Constitution could never have lasted, for neither executive officers nor legislatures are good judges of the extent of their own powers.
Nothing more strikingly shows the spirit of unity15 which the Constitution brought into being than the unbroken success with which the Supreme Court has discharged this difficult and most delicate duty. The President is the Commander-in-Chief of the Army and the Navy and can call them to his aid. The legislature has almost unlimited135 power through its control of the public purse. The States have their power reinforced by armed forces, and some of them are as great in population and resources as many of the nations of Europe. The Supreme Court, however, has only one officer to execute its decrees, called the United States Marshal; and yet, without sword or purse, and with only a high sheriff to enforce its mandates, when the Supreme Court says to a President or to a Congress or to the authorities of a great—and, in some respects, sovereign—State that they must do this or must refrain from doing that, the mandate48 is at once obeyed. Here, indeed, is the American ideal of "a government of laws and not of men" most strikingly realized; and if the American Constitution, as formulated136 and developed, had done nothing else than to establish in this manner the supremacy of law, even as against the overwhelming sentiment of the people, it would have justified137 the well-known encomium138 of Mr. Gladstone.
It must be added, however, that in one respect this function of the judiciary has had an unfortunate effect in lessening139 rather than developing in the people the sense of constitutional morality. In your country the power of Parliament is omnipotent140, and yet in its legislation it voluntarily observes these great fundamental decencies of liberty which in the American Constitution are protected by formal guarantees. This can only be true because either your representatives in Parliament have a deep sense of constitutional morality, or that the constituencies which select them have so much sense of constitutional justice that their representatives dare not disregard these fundamental decencies of liberty.
In the United States, however, the confidence that the Supreme Court will itself protect these guaranties of liberty has led to a diminution141 of the sense of constitutional morality, both in the people and their representatives. It abates142 the vigilance which is said to be ever the price of liberty.
Laws are passed which transgress143 the limitations of the Constitution without adequate discussion as to their unconstitutional character, for the reason that the determination of this fact is erroneously supposed to be the exclusive function of the judiciary.
The judiciary, contrary to the common supposition, has no plenary power to nullify unconstitutional laws. It can only do so when there is an irreconcilable144 and indubitable repugnancy between a law and the Constitution; but obviously laws can be passed from motives145 that are anti-constitutional, and there is a wide sphere of political discretion147 in which many acts can be done which, while politically anti-constitutional, are not juridically unconstitutional. For this reason, the undue148 dependence42 upon the judiciary to nullify every law which either in form, necessary operation, or motive146 transgresses149 the Constitution has so far lessened150 the vigilance of the people to protect their own Constitution as to lead to its serious impairment.
5.
The fifth fundamental principle was a system of governmental checks and balances.
The founders151 of the Republic were not enamoured of power. As they viewed human history, the worst evils of government were due to excessive concentration of power, which like Othello's jealousy "makes the meat it feeds on."
This system of checks and balances again illustrates152 that the Constitution is the great negation of unrestrained democracy. The framers believed that a people was best governed that was least governed. Therefore, their purpose was not so much to promote efficiency in legislation as to put a brake upon precipitate153 action.
Time does not suffice to state the intricate system of checks and balances whereby the legislature acts as a check upon the executive and the executive upon the legislature, and the Supreme Court upon both. When the Republic was small, and its public affairs were few, this system of checks and balances worked admirably, but to-day, when the nation is one of the greatest in the world, and its public affairs are of the most important and complicated character, and often require speedy action, it may be questioned whether the system is not now an undue brake upon governmental efficiency, and does not require some modification154 to ensure efficiency. Indeed, it is a serious question with many thoughtful Americans whether the growth of the United States has not put an excessive strain upon its governmental machinery155.
This system was in part due to the confident belief of the framers of the Constitution in the Montesquieu doctrine of the division of government into three independent departments—legislative156, executive and judicial; but experience has shown how difficult it is to apply this doctrine in its literal rigidity157. One result of the doctrine was the mistaken attempt to keep the legislative and the executive as far apart as possible. The Cabinet system of parliamentary government was not adopted. While the President can appear before Congress and express his views, his Cabinet is without such right. In practice, the gulf is bridged by constant contact between the Cabinet and the committees of Congress, but this does not wholly secure speedy and efficient co-operation between the two departments. As I speak, a movement is in progress, with the sanction of President Harding, to permit members of his Cabinet to appear in Congress and thus defend directly and in person the policies of the Executive.
This separation of the two departments, which causes so much friction158, has been emphasized by one feature of the Constitution which again marks its distrust of democracy, namely the fixed159 tenure160 of office. The Constitution did not intend that public officials should rise or fall with the fleeting caprices of a constituency. It preferred to give the President and the members of Congress a fixed term of office, and, however unpopular they might become temporarily, they should have the right and the opportunity to proceed even with unpopular policies, and thus challenge the final verdict of the people.
If a parliamentary form of government, immediately responsive to current opinion as registered in elections, is the great desideratum, then the fixed tenure of offices is the vulnerable Achilles-heel of our form of government. In other countries the Executive cannot survive a vote of want of confidence by the legislature. In America, the President, who is merely the Executive of the legislative will, continues for his prescribed term, though he may have wholly lost the confidence of the representatives of the people in Congress. While this makes for stability in administration and keeps the ship of state on an even keel, yet it also leads to the fatalism of our democracy, and often the "native hue161" of its resolution is thus "sicklied o'er with the pale cast of thought." Take a striking instance. I am confident that after the sinking of the Lusitania, the United States would have entered the world war, if President Wilson's tenure of power had then depended upon a vote of confidence.
6.
The sixth fundamental principle is the joint162 power of the Senate and the Executive over the foreign relations of the Government.
I need not dwell at length upon this unique feature of our constitutional system, for since the Versailles Treaty, the world has become well acquainted with our peculiar163 system under which treaties are made and war is declared or terminated. Nothing, excepting the principle of local rule, was of deeper concern to the framers of the Constitution. When it was framed, it was the accepted principle of all other nations that the control of the foreign relations of the Government was the exclusive prerogative164 of the Executive. In your country the only limitation upon that power was the control of Parliament over the purse of the nation, and some of the great struggles in your history related to the attempt of the Crown to exact money to carry on the wars without a Parliament grant.
The framers were unwilling165 to lodge166 any such power in the Executive, however great his powers in other respects. This was primarily due to the conception of the States that then prevailed. While they had created a central government for certain specified167 purposes, they yet regarded themselves as sovereign nations, and their representatives in the Senate were, in a sense, their ambassadors. They were as little inclined to permit the President of the United States to make treaties or declare war at will in their behalf as the European nations would be to-day to vest a similar authority in the League of Nations. It was, therefore, first proposed that the power to make treaties and appoint diplomatic representatives should be vested exclusively in the Senate, but as that body was not always in session, this plan was so far modified as to give the President, who is always acting, the power to negotiate treaties "with the advice and consent of the Senate." As to making war, the framers were not willing to entrust168 the power even to the President and the Senators, and it was therefore expressly provided that only Congress could take this momentous step.
Here, again, the theory of the Constitution was necessarily somewhat modified in practical administration, for under the power of nominating diplomatic representatives, negotiating treaties, and in general, of executing the laws of the nation, the principle was soon evolved that the conduct of foreign affairs was primarily the function of the President, with the limitation that the Senate must concur61 in diplomatic appointments and in the validity of treaties, and that only both Houses of Congress could jointly169 declare war. This cumbrous system necessarily required that the President in conducting the foreign relations of the Government should keep in touch with the Senate, and such was the accepted procedure throughout the history of the nation until President Wilson saw fit to ignore the Senate, even when the Senate had indicated its dissent170 in advance to some of his policies at the Versailles Conference.
I suppose that since that conference no part of our constitutional system has caused more adverse171 comment in Europe than this system. It often handicaps the United States from taking a speedy and effectual part in international negotiations172, although if the President and the Senate be in harmony and collaborate173 in this joint responsibility, there is no necessary reason why this should be so.
I share the view of many Americans that this provision of the Constitution was wise and salutary, especially at this time, when the United States has taken such an important position in the councils of civilization. The President is a very powerful Executive, and his tenure, while short, is fixed. Generally he is elected by little more than a majority of the people, and sometimes through the curious workings of the electoral college system, he has been only the choice of a minority of the electorate174. For these reasons, the framers of the Constitution were unwilling to vest in the President exclusively the immeasurable power of pledging the faith, man-power, and resources of the nation and of declaring war. The heterogeneous175 character of our population especially emphasizes the wisdom of this course, for it would be difficult, if not impossible, for an American President to make an offensive and defensive176 alliance with any nation or declare war against another nation without running counter to the racial interests and passions of a substantial part of the American nation. For better or worse, the United States has limited, but not destroyed, as the world war showed, its freedom to antagonize powerful nations from whose people it has drawn177 large numbers of its own citizenship. The domestic harmony of the nation requires that before the United States assumes treaty obligations or makes war such policy shall represent the largely preponderating178 sentiment of its people, and nothing could more effectually secure this end than to require the President, before making a treaty, to secure the assent of two-thirds of the Senate and a majority of both Houses of Congress before making war.
While this may lead, as it has in recent years, to temporary and regrettable embarrassments179, yet in the long run, it is not only better for the United States, but it is even to the best interests of other nations, for in this way they are safeguarded against the possible action of an Executive with whom racial instincts might still be very influential180. In your country, where the Government of the day is subject to immediate dismissal for want of confidence, such power over foreign relations can be safely entrusted181 to a few men, but in the United States, with its fixed tenures of office, a President could pledge the faith and involve his nation in war against the interests and will of the people. Suppose the President had unlimited power over our foreign relations and that within the next ten years an American, whose parents were born in any European nation, was elected on purely domestic issues, he could, with his assured four years of power, bring about a new alignment182 of nations and shake the political equilibrium183 of the world. The Constitution wisely refused to grant such a power. Hence the provision for the concurrence184 of the legislative representatives of the nation. At all events, it constitutes a system which, as the last presidential election showed, the American people will not willingly forgo185. It is true that this system makes it difficult for the United States to participate effectively in the main purpose of the League of Nations to enforce peace by joint action at Geneva, but to ask the United States to surrender a vital part of its constitutional system, upon which its domestic peace so largely depends, in order to promote the League, seems to me as unreasonable as it would be to ask your country to abolish the Crown, to which it is sincerely attached as a vital part of its system, as a contribution towards international co-operation. You would not surrender such an integral part of your system, and therefore it is not reasonable to expect a similar sacrifice on our part, even though the meritorious186 purposes of the League be freely recognized.
I have thus summarized briefly and most inadequately187 some of the essential principles of the Constitution. I have only been able to suggest very impressionistically what they are and the lessons to be drawn from them. If I were able to deliver a dozen addresses on the subject in this historic Hall and with this indulgent audience I would not scratch even the surface. To understand the Constitution of the United States you must not only read the text but the thousands of opinions rendered in the last 130 years by the Supreme Court in its great task of interpreting this wonderful document. Few documents have been the subject of more extended commentaries. The four thousand words have been meticulously188 examined through intellectual microscopes in judicial opinions, textbooks, and other commentaries which are as "thick as autumnal leaves that strow the brooks189 in Vallombrosa."
One can say of this document as Dr. Furness, in his variorum edition of Hamlet, says of the words of that character:
"No words by him let fall, no syllable190 by him uttered, but has been
caught up and pondered, as no words except those of Holy Writ191."
But what of its future and how long will the Constitution wholly resist the washing of time and circumstance? Lord Macaulay once ventured the prediction that the Constitution would prove unworkable as soon as there were no longer large areas of undeveloped land and when the United States became a nation of great cities. That period of development has arrived. In 1880 only 15 per cent. of the American population lived in the cities and the remainder were still on the farms. To-day over 52 per cent, are crowded in one hundred great cities. Lord Macaulay added:
"I believe America's fate is only deferred192 by physical causes. Institutions purely democratic will sooner or later destroy liberty or civilization, or both…. The American Constitution is all sail and no anchor."
In this last commentary Lord Macaulay was clearly mistaken. As I have shown, the Constitution is not "purely democratic." It is amazing that so great a mind should have so little understood that more than any other Constitution, that of America imposes powerful restraints on democracy. The experience of a century and a quarter has shown that while the anchor may at times drag, yet it measurably holds the ship of state to its ancient moorings. The American Constitution still remains193 in its essential principles and still enjoys not only the confidence but the affection of the great and varied194 people whom it rules. To the latter this remarkable achievement must be attributed rather than to any inherent strength in parchment or red seals, for in a democracy the living soul of any Constitution must be such belief of the people in its wisdom and justice. If it should perish to-morrow, it would yet have enjoyed a life and growth of which any nation or age might be justly proud. Moreover, it could claim with truth, if it finally perished, that it had been subjected to conditions for which it was never intended and that some of its essential principles had been ignored.
The Constitution is something more than a written formula of government—it is a great spirit. It is a high and noble assertion, and, indeed, vindication195, of the morality of government. It "renders unto Caesar [the political state] the things that are Caesar's," but in safeguarding the fundamental moral rights of the people, it "renders unto God the things that are God's."
In concluding, I cannot refrain from again reminding you that this consummate196 work of statecraft was the work of the English-speaking race, and that your people can therefore justly share in the pride which it awakens197. It is not only one of the great achievements of that gens aeterna, but also one of the great monuments of human progress. It illustrates the possibilities of true democracy in its best estate. When the moral anarchy out of which it was born is called to mind, it can be truly said that while "sown in weakness, it was raised in power."
To the succeeding ages, it will be a flaming beacon198, and everywhere men, who are confronted with the acute problems of this complex age, can take encouragement from the fact that a small and weak people, when confronted with similar problems, had the strength and will to impose restraint upon themselves by peacefully proclaiming in the simple words of the noble preamble to the Constitution:
"We, the people of the United States, in order to form a more perfect union, establish justice, ensure domestic tranquillity199, provide for the common defence, promote the general welfare, and secure the blessings200 of liberty to ourselves and our posterity201, do ordain202 and establish this Constitution for the United States of America."
Note the words "ordain and establish." They imply perpetuity. They make no provision for the secession of any State, even if it deems itself aggrieved203 by federal action. And yet the right to secede204 was urged for many years, but Lincoln completed the work of Washington, Franklin, Madison and Hamilton by establishing that "a government for the people, by the people and of the people should not perish from the earth."
点击收听单词发音
1 constellation | |
n.星座n.灿烂的一群 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 murky | |
adj.黑暗的,朦胧的;adv.阴暗地,混浊地;n.阴暗;昏暗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 ratified | |
v.批准,签认(合约等)( ratify的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 ratifying | |
v.批准,签认(合约等)( ratify的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 controversy | |
n.争论,辩论,争吵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 arduous | |
adj.艰苦的,费力的,陡峭的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 requisite | |
adj.需要的,必不可少的;n.必需品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 assent | |
v.批准,认可;n.批准,认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 amendment | |
n.改正,修正,改善,修正案 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 amendments | |
(法律、文件的)改动( amendment的名词复数 ); 修正案; 修改; (美国宪法的)修正案 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 dual | |
adj.双的;二重的,二元的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 immunity | |
n.优惠;免除;豁免,豁免权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 unity | |
n.团结,联合,统一;和睦,协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 unreasonable | |
adj.不讲道理的,不合情理的,过度的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 seizures | |
n.起获( seizure的名词复数 );没收;充公;起获的赃物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 fleeting | |
adj.短暂的,飞逝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 scrap | |
n.碎片;废料;v.废弃,报废 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 negation | |
n.否定;否认 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 remarkable | |
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 affected | |
adj.不自然的,假装的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 utilization | |
n.利用,效用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 marvel | |
vi.(at)惊叹vt.感到惊异;n.令人惊异的事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 creed | |
n.信条;信念,纲领 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 immutable | |
adj.不可改变的,永恒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 exigencies | |
n.急切需要 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 enumerating | |
v.列举,枚举,数( enumerate的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 supremely | |
adv.无上地,崇高地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 embody | |
vt.具体表达,使具体化;包含,收录 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 elasticity | |
n.弹性,伸缩力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 vitality | |
n.活力,生命力,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 judicial | |
adj.司法的,法庭的,审判的,明断的,公正的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 interpretation | |
n.解释,说明,描述;艺术处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 embodied | |
v.表现( embody的过去式和过去分词 );象征;包括;包含 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 eruption | |
n.火山爆发;(战争等)爆发;(疾病等)发作 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 hysterical | |
adj.情绪异常激动的,歇斯底里般的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 preamble | |
n.前言;序文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 dependence | |
n.依靠,依赖;信任,信赖;隶属 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 anarchy | |
n.无政府状态;社会秩序混乱,无秩序 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 rampant | |
adj.(植物)蔓生的;狂暴的,无约束的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 culminate | |
v.到绝顶,达于极点,达到高潮 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 satiety | |
n.饱和;(市场的)充分供应 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 mandates | |
托管(mandate的第三人称单数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 mandate | |
n.托管地;命令,指示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 simplicity | |
n.简单,简易;朴素;直率,单纯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 adherence | |
n.信奉,依附,坚持,固着 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 apparently | |
adv.显然地;表面上,似乎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 underlying | |
adj.在下面的,含蓄的,潜在的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 delegations | |
n.代表团( delegation的名词复数 );委托,委派 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 briefly | |
adv.简单地,简短地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 legislate | |
vt.制定法律;n.法规,律例;立法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 intervention | |
n.介入,干涉,干预 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 concession | |
n.让步,妥协;特许(权) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 residual | |
adj.复播复映追加时间;存留下来的,剩余的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 acting | |
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 concur | |
v.同意,意见一致,互助,同时发生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 concurred | |
同意(concur的过去式与过去分词形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 impair | |
v.损害,损伤;削弱,减少 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 emphatic | |
adj.强调的,着重的;无可置疑的,明显的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 democrat | |
n.民主主义者,民主人士;民主党党员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 antithesis | |
n.对立;相对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 cardinals | |
红衣主教( cardinal的名词复数 ); 红衣凤头鸟(见于北美,雄鸟为鲜红色); 基数 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 utterances | |
n.发声( utterance的名词复数 );说话方式;语调;言论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 patriots | |
爱国者,爱国主义者( patriot的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 tribulation | |
n.苦难,灾难 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 follies | |
罪恶,时事讽刺剧; 愚蠢,蠢笨,愚蠢的行为、思想或做法( folly的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 tenacious | |
adj.顽强的,固执的,记忆力强的,粘的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 mischiefs | |
损害( mischief的名词复数 ); 危害; 胡闹; 调皮捣蛋的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 faction | |
n.宗派,小集团;派别;派系斗争 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 turbulence | |
n.喧嚣,狂暴,骚乱,湍流 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 contention | |
n.争论,争辩,论战;论点,主张 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 incompatible | |
adj.不相容的,不协调的,不相配的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 undoubtedly | |
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 injustice | |
n.非正义,不公正,不公平,侵犯(别人的)权利 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 rigidly | |
adv.刻板地,僵化地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 contemplated | |
adj. 预期的 动词contemplate的过去分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 momentous | |
adj.重要的,重大的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 noted | |
adj.著名的,知名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 judgment | |
n.审判;判断力,识别力,看法,意见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 dictated | |
v.大声讲或读( dictate的过去式和过去分词 );口授;支配;摆布 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 constituents | |
n.选民( constituent的名词复数 );成分;构成部分;要素 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 constituent | |
n.选民;成分,组分;adj.组成的,构成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 notably | |
adv.值得注意地,显著地,尤其地,特别地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 justification | |
n.正当的理由;辩解的理由 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 venality | |
n.贪赃枉法,腐败 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 vindicate | |
v.为…辩护或辩解,辩明;证明…正确 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 citizenship | |
n.市民权,公民权,国民的义务(身份) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 adoption | |
n.采用,采纳,通过;收养 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 jurisdiction | |
n.司法权,审判权,管辖权,控制权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 geographically | |
adv.地理学上,在地理上,地理方面 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 centripetal | |
adj.向心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 enacted | |
制定(法律),通过(法案)( enact的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 compartments | |
n.间隔( compartment的名词复数 );(列车车厢的)隔间;(家具或设备等的)分隔间;隔层 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 steamship | |
n.汽船,轮船 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 unified | |
(unify 的过去式和过去分词); 统一的; 统一标准的; 一元化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 zigzags | |
n.锯齿形的线条、小径等( zigzag的名词复数 )v.弯弯曲曲地走路,曲折地前进( zigzag的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 constructive | |
adj.建设的,建设性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 entities | |
实体对像; 实体,独立存在体,实际存在物( entity的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 relatively | |
adv.比较...地,相对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 steadily | |
adv.稳定地;不变地;持续地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 inevitable | |
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 purely | |
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 gulf | |
n.海湾;深渊,鸿沟;分歧,隔阂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 supremacy | |
n.至上;至高权力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 exemptions | |
n.(义务等的)免除( exemption的名词复数 );免(税);(收入中的)免税额 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 barons | |
男爵( baron的名词复数 ); 巨头; 大王; 大亨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 wrung | |
绞( wring的过去式和过去分词 ); 握紧(尤指别人的手); 把(湿衣服)拧干; 绞掉(水) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 amending | |
改良,修改,修订( amend的现在分词 ); 改良,修改,修订( amend的第三人称单数 )( amends的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 monarch | |
n.帝王,君主,最高统治者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 omnipotence | |
n.全能,万能,无限威力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 animated | |
adj.生气勃勃的,活跃的,愉快的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 sleepless | |
adj.不睡眠的,睡不著的,不休息的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 jealousy | |
n.妒忌,嫉妒,猜忌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 salvation | |
n.(尤指基督)救世,超度,拯救,解困 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 abhorrent | |
adj.可恶的,可恨的,讨厌的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 allied | |
adj.协约国的;同盟国的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 paraphrase | |
vt.将…释义,改写;n.释义,意义 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 enumerated | |
v.列举,枚举,数( enumerate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 conformity | |
n.一致,遵从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 unprecedented | |
adj.无前例的,新奇的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 primal | |
adj.原始的;最重要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 verities | |
n.真实( verity的名词复数 );事实;真理;真实的陈述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 override | |
vt.不顾,不理睬,否决;压倒,优先于 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 admiration | |
n.钦佩,赞美,羡慕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 unlimited | |
adj.无限的,不受控制的,无条件的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 formulated | |
v.构想出( formulate的过去式和过去分词 );规划;确切地阐述;用公式表示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 justified | |
a.正当的,有理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 encomium | |
n.赞颂;颂词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 lessening | |
减轻,减少,变小 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 omnipotent | |
adj.全能的,万能的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141 diminution | |
n.减少;变小 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142 abates | |
减少( abate的第三人称单数 ); 减去; 降价; 撤消(诉讼) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143 transgress | |
vt.违反,逾越 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144 irreconcilable | |
adj.(指人)难和解的,势不两立的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147 discretion | |
n.谨慎;随意处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148 undue | |
adj.过分的;不适当的;未到期的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149 transgresses | |
n.超越( transgress的名词复数 );越过;违反;违背v.超越( transgress的第三人称单数 );越过;违反;违背 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150 lessened | |
减少的,减弱的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151 founders | |
n.创始人( founder的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
152 illustrates | |
给…加插图( illustrate的第三人称单数 ); 说明; 表明; (用示例、图画等)说明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
153 precipitate | |
adj.突如其来的;vt.使突然发生;n.沉淀物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
154 modification | |
n.修改,改进,缓和,减轻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
155 machinery | |
n.(总称)机械,机器;机构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
156 legislative | |
n.立法机构,立法权;adj.立法的,有立法权的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
157 rigidity | |
adj.钢性,坚硬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
158 friction | |
n.摩擦,摩擦力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
159 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
160 tenure | |
n.终身职位;任期;(土地)保有权,保有期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
161 hue | |
n.色度;色调;样子 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
162 joint | |
adj.联合的,共同的;n.关节,接合处;v.连接,贴合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
163 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
164 prerogative | |
n.特权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
165 unwilling | |
adj.不情愿的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
166 lodge | |
v.临时住宿,寄宿,寄存,容纳;n.传达室,小旅馆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
167 specified | |
adj.特定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
168 entrust | |
v.信赖,信托,交托 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
169 jointly | |
ad.联合地,共同地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
170 dissent | |
n./v.不同意,持异议 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
171 adverse | |
adj.不利的;有害的;敌对的,不友好的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
172 negotiations | |
协商( negotiation的名词复数 ); 谈判; 完成(难事); 通过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
173 collaborate | |
vi.协作,合作;协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
174 electorate | |
n.全体选民;选区 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
175 heterogeneous | |
adj.庞杂的;异类的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
176 defensive | |
adj.防御的;防卫的;防守的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
177 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
178 preponderating | |
v.超过,胜过( preponderate的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
179 embarrassments | |
n.尴尬( embarrassment的名词复数 );难堪;局促不安;令人难堪或耻辱的事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
180 influential | |
adj.有影响的,有权势的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
181 entrusted | |
v.委托,托付( entrust的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
182 alignment | |
n.队列;结盟,联合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
183 equilibrium | |
n.平衡,均衡,相称,均势,平静 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
184 concurrence | |
n.同意;并发 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
185 forgo | |
v.放弃,抛弃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
186 meritorious | |
adj.值得赞赏的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
187 inadequately | |
ad.不够地;不够好地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
188 meticulously | |
adv.过细地,异常细致地;无微不至;精心 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
189 brooks | |
n.小溪( brook的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
190 syllable | |
n.音节;vt.分音节 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
191 writ | |
n.命令状,书面命令 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
192 deferred | |
adj.延期的,缓召的v.拖延,延缓,推迟( defer的过去式和过去分词 );服从某人的意愿,遵从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
193 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
194 varied | |
adj.多样的,多变化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
195 vindication | |
n.洗冤,证实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
196 consummate | |
adj.完美的;v.成婚;使完美 [反]baffle | |
参考例句: |
|
|
197 awakens | |
v.(使)醒( awaken的第三人称单数 );(使)觉醒;弄醒;(使)意识到 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
198 beacon | |
n.烽火,(警告用的)闪火灯,灯塔 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
199 tranquillity | |
n. 平静, 安静 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
200 blessings | |
n.(上帝的)祝福( blessing的名词复数 );好事;福分;因祸得福 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
201 posterity | |
n.后裔,子孙,后代 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
202 ordain | |
vi.颁发命令;vt.命令,授以圣职,注定,任命 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
203 aggrieved | |
adj.愤愤不平的,受委屈的;悲痛的;(在合法权利方面)受侵害的v.令委屈,令苦恼,侵害( aggrieve的过去式);令委屈,令苦恼,侵害( aggrieve的过去式和过去分词) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
204 secede | |
v.退出,脱离 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |