That time-sense is not a grand principle of division we also see plainly when we examine particular emotions. Thus, in the case of anger, while we can say at once that this is, in all its forms, repulse7 to injury, can we claim it is either prospective or retrospective emotion? The truth is, the thought of injury done, doing, or to be done, equally wakens anger in choleric8 individuals. The man who harmed me yesterday excites my anger, and so does the 177man whom I perceive to be now injuring me or about to injure me. The quality of the emotion is identically the same whether the object be considered as in past, present, or future. Even what seems to be a purely9 temporal emotion, like hope, which is usually regarded as wholly prospective, may yet have other temporal aspects. Thus, we sometimes say, “I hope it was not so,” where hope is obviously retrospective, or more strictly10 prospective-retrospective, having reference to expectation with desire that the event will turn out not to have happened.
But it may be said that, as emotion rests upon representation, the proper classification of the emotions will depend upon the divisions of representation which are essentially11 determined12 by the time-sense as representation of past or future. Representation with sense of representation implies a cognition of the thing as represented merely, and so as non-existent to present actual sensing, as something having been, or to be, sensed. The emotion arises thus on cognition of the experienceable, and includes always some dim impression of potency13 of object for harm or benefit at some time. However, though this may be the case, it is plain that it makes no radical14 distinction in emotion. If a man threatens me with some injury, this fires my rage, which is greatly increased if I catch him in the act of committing the injury threatened, or find that he has committed the evil deed. Change in time-sense may thus bring change in intensity15 of some emotions, but it does not determine quality of emotion. The prime factor as to kind of emotion is always, not any sense of time, but the personal value of the event, which may or may not receive a definite time determination. Indeed, a form of representation, before any sense of experience as merely subjective17 phenomenon is attained19, is a prominent feature in the direct na?ve experience which constitutes by far the greater bulk in the total existent consciousness. Before experience is aware of itself and of the experienceable 178there is a certain purely subjective mirroring of that which is not present to sense, but has been, i.e., there is a re-occurrence in consciousness which has the subjective force of reality; though the objective actuality is lacking, such re-occurrence by association without the actual presence of the object stands, however, for reality to the mind experiencing—it is a direct intuition; the object, though unreal, is perfectly20 real to consciousness, and conveys no meaning, and so is not a basis for emotion. Yet in the higher representation with a sense of experience as integral element, the representation is sometimes practically timeless, though surcharged with emotion tendency. The highest objects which the mind represents have little time quality, and all the nobler sentiments, as love of truth, justice, etc., exist with little or no reference to time. So also in the very earliest representation, the object is seen in its feeling value—emotion basis—as soon as it is perceived as object; but this is as an immediate21 subjective realizing in which time-sense plays very little part. The conscious interpretation22 of past and future as a conscious connecting of the two is certainly not a primitive23 function. The time form is, then, on the whole, merely incidental in emotion, and is by no means a fundamental principle determining classification.
Yet, though we must reject time as a cardinal24 principle of division in emotion, still we must acknowledge that the term retrospective emotion denotes a real group of mental phenomena, including revenge, regret, remorse25, and kindred forms, which are marked as feeling for the past merely as past. However, pure retrospection is rare and late. The past does not for primitive mind stand by itself as something to be dwelt upon, to be thought about, to be moved by, and stirred to action. The immediate present absorbs the mind, and the past interests and excites only so far as bearing directly on the present. And so it is that the child lives in the present, the youth and man in the future, 179the old man in the past; and this denotes the relatively26 late appearance of pure retrospection and of emotion founded thereon. Emotion is first merely spectant, then prospective, then retrospective. However, when we say an emotion is concerned solely27 with the present in the very young, we mean, of course, the immediately prospective—that which has relation to but one sense and by association rouses emotion, as an apple, seen or handled by a child, awakens28 emotion, desire to taste. Where sense consciousness is not multiform, but single and uniform, as, doubtless, in very low organisms, there is no opportunity for any emotion, for there is no interpretation power. But the intensification29 of some one sense connection already attained may be a basis for emotion which we may loosely call emotion spectant, as when the greedy child eagerly eating an apple desires a larger bite, sweeter portion, etc. However,—though it has little classification value,—emotion can be only prospective or retrospective; and this is, of course, implied in its basis—representation. Emotion by its very nature must be a looking forward, or a looking backward, or both. As a feeling about, and not a direct feeling, this is obviously its unvariable cognitive30 content. The immediate and actual realization31 may be direct feeling or sensation, but it is never in itself emotion. Emotion is always over something, an experience of experience, and cannot thus be simple content. It is thus a consciously idealizing mode as distinguished32 from direct realization which is wholly self-contained.
One of the most important and interesting retrospective emotions is revenge. The cardinal idea in revenge is returning evil for evil. Not only must there be a paying back for past injury, but there must be an equivalence, eye for an eye, and tooth for a tooth; and the revengeful emotion is the meting33 out such purely retributive action. Exact return becomes the basis of a general usage in animal and human societies. Justice, law, and punishment 180rest upon the idea of inflicting35 duplicate or equivalent injury for injury received. Administrative36 justice is the specialization of revenge in the hands of a few members of a community, a social differentiation37 by which individuals in general secure their revenges at great economy by proxy38. Further, the revengeful emotion is a smouldering hate which vents39 itself only some time after the immediate occasion. This is not the flush of anger which prompts to vigorous offensive action upon the injurer at the very moment of harm perceived, and it does not appear as stimulant40 to immediate self-conservative activities, but is simply the spirit of getting even for relatively long past injury.
What, now, is the function of revenge as a life factor? It surely does not mend my injury that I do another harm solely because he has some time harmed me, and the whole impulse might seem a pure waste of energy. But under natural selection revenge must arise in serviceability of some sort; and it is obvious that while revenge is of no use in mending the past, it yet has a large value with reference to future possible injury. Yet revenge is undeniably without conscious meaning for present or future; it is merely the spirit and determination to get even, and so its deterrent41 function is unconsciously attained. A dwelling42 in thought on the past per se, a feeling about it and acting43 on it, while it cannot help life directly, has a large value in its ultimate effect upon enemies. He who never forgets injury, and for whom by-gones are never by-gones, who never fails to return injury for injury, is feared and is less likely to be injured. Junker, the African traveller, remarks of the pygmies, “They are much feared for their revengeful spirit.” Thus, other things being equal, the most revengeful are the most successful in the struggle for self-conservation and self-furtherance. Though by itself considered irrational44 and foolish to inflict34 return injuries upon an injurer long after the immediate occasion, yet its 181deterrent effect is very great with reference to other assailants. Thus, pure retrospection may have unconsciously prospective value, or sometimes revenge may be really retrospective-prospective, as when one says, “I will fix him so he will not do that again.” Here function is consciously known, but in instinctive45 revenge there is no such foresight46, and, in general, utility is no consideration with the revenger, whose mind is bent47 rather on doing great harm for its own sake to his enemy rather than benefiting himself. It is always the conscious or unconscious significance for the future that justifies48 revenge in the natural course of events; while it is no remedy for my hurt, if some one has put out my eye, to put out his in return, yet this revenge act, and so the feeling which prompts it, is of highest prospective value with reference to future possible enemies. Every one will know that I cannot be harmed with impunity49. Despoil50 or injure the revengeful in any way and you inevitably51 suffer for it sooner or later, and so revenge acts as a protective psychical52 variation of high value. On the whole the revengeful is less likely than others to be molested54 and injured, and thus has a manifest advantage in the struggle for existence. Revenge has, then, also rightfully its own subjective sanction, a pleasure reaction, for revenge is, indeed, “sweet.”
Revenge is apparently55 found in a considerable range in the animal kingdom, and seems universal in the genus homo. However, we cannot infallibly conclude from certain actions that revengeful emotion is present, and especially is this so in the case of animals. Thus, in the well-known instance of the elephant, who, observing a man passing by who had greatly annoyed him years before, suddenly drenched56 him with dirty water, we are not necessarily to suppose that this elephant was prompted by the emotion of revenge; although this may have been the case, we are not perfectly sure how far the elephant did the act merely as recompense for what the man had done, or how far the 182sight of the injurer, and so one likely to injure, roused to simple anger and defence against the threatening harmful. Many acts which seem like revenge are quite likely to be common defence or offence, are done with reference to what the object is and will be as injurious, based upon knowledge of the past, and not as merely retrospective retributive acts. Memory for injuries received is strong in many animals; that which has harmed is often recognised after many years as the harmful, and appropriate simple emotion, not revenge, is manifested. Rage, rather than revenge, is the usual emotion among lower animals in special instances where revenge might seem called for; and thus it is more likely that the elephant should rage and hate rather than have pure revenge as in the case considered.
However, somewhere rather late in sub-human psychism57 revengeful emotion certainly arose as an advantageous58 variation, and it grew in strength and prominence59 for many ages of psychic53 progress. At length it culminated60, and began its decline with the marked increase of co-operative sociality, with which it must greatly interfere61. Reprisal62 and counter-reprisal, vendetta63, feud64, is opposed to that social union which is strength; and so we see that tribes and nations in which the spirit of personal revenge has been a dominant65 trait have been left behind in the march of progress. Revengefulness, at least in the form of retributive personal violence for injuries done, is, in a highly civilized66 community, entirely67 superseded68 by the machinery69 of law. Instead of slaying70 a brother’s murderer I call upon the law to execute justice and retribution, and I bring certain designated ones among my fellows to secure my revenge. Where a man takes the law in his own hands, and kills or injures the violator of his home or the slayer71 of his nearest kin16, he recedes72 to the lower unsocial plane from which civilization has arisen. Thus revengefulness, in certain forms at least, has become in the highest human 183communities a disadvantageous variation, and is gradually being eliminated. This negative elimination73 of revenge is also greatly hastened by the progress of certain ethical74 and Christian75 conceptions by which a new and opposite law of conduct is enforced, namely, the returning good for evil.
One of the most interesting and most retrospective of emotions is sorrow. Sorrow, grief and regret are wholly regardful of the past, are pains at the past. They are purely subjective or “mental” pains at the past, and in no wise pains from the past; they are not pains recurrent from past pains, but purely a painful emotion at the representation of past pain. Thus, a man says, “I did it to my own harm and hurt, and I have always been sorry I did it.” Here the sorrow-pain is evidently quite distinct from the direct pain of the injury; pain for the harm done is one thing, and pain from the harm done is another. I hurt myself, and I not only have this pain, but, being sorry that I did it, I have this new emotional pain added. Sorrow as painful emotion for the past is thus plainly unique and peculiar76. To feel sorry over what has happened is a mode of feeling altogether different from feeling proud of it, angry at it, etc., and we may reasonably regard sorrow as a distinct genus of retrospective emotion. What, now, is the nature and function of this special emotion reaction?
We have to consider here only that simple primitive sorrow which is a painful emotion at regarding personal loss or failure. Such simple sorrow we see in the child who cries over spilled milk, in the man who expresses deep regret at the careless misstep by which he broke his leg. In this emotional reaction at the injurious the harmful is neither escaped nor repelled77, as through fear and anger; the feeling disturbance78 is comparatively passive and purely reflective, and is not a spur to some immediate advantageous defensive79 or offensive activity. In sorrow we are pained emotionally at the trouble which has come upon 184us through our own agency or otherwise, but we do not struggle from it or against it, but there is purely helpless retrospection. Harm and loss which might provoke in one nature to fear or anger, in another lead only to inactive sorrow.
The cognition form in sorrow means always sense of personal loss. I may fear a thing, or I may be angry at a thing, but I can be sorry only for a person. I do not feel sorry for a broken chair, though I may feel sorry for having broken it. This view of one’s own personal agency in causing harm to one’s self and harm to others is very prominent in a large range of sorrow. In viewing any action which determined some evil, I say, “I am sorry I did it.” This is, however, a later mode of the emotion, which at the first cannot take account of any agency, but is simply an acute feeling of distress80 at the injury received. Thus the one who grieves over the spilled milk regards, not his own agency, but only his loss; he is sorry, not that he spilled the milk, but that his milk was spilled. Yet the sense of personal agency certainly forms a great part in much sorrow, and tends to intensify81 it. I may grieve over any harm that has come upon me, but my grief is intensified82 as I remember my own agency in bringing it about. I may feel sorry over the loss of my goods by fire, but if I lose them by my own careless act, my sorrow is redoubled. Strictly speaking, perhaps, the sorrows are distinct, I feel sorry for having done it and I am sorry at it done; yet they may be said to constitute a single psychic state. Sense of our own agency, however, in having produced harm to self is as likely to produce anger at self or even fear of self. Hence our intensest and purest sorrows are apt to be those occasioned by considering injuries occasioned by elemental forces. That harm which we did not help because we could not, the inevitable83 injury, this excites a keen regret and deep mourning.
185The pain in sorrow is as peculiar, searching, unanalyzable and undescribable as other simple emotion pains, and only conceivable through realization. This sinking, helpless pain over what has happened is clearly distinct from the sensation order of pains, and is in no wise a reflection from them. The pain I have at remembrance of some great loss which has befallen me is certainly very distinct from that which came from the loss itself.
What part now does sorrow play as a psychic life-function, and how explain it on the general principle of natural selection? At first sight, sorrow or grief over the past seems utterly84 valueless, seems to be mental energy thrown away. The past is irretrievable, of what use then is any grief? Is not all regret vain? To deplore85 its loss does not tend to restore a lost arm, and it is of no use crying over spilled milk. Indeed, he who bewails spilled milk has not only the actual loss but the ideal pain about the loss. He who grieves suffers doubly. But while it is true that sorrow for what has happened cannot alter the occurrence, yet it has a permanent salutary effect on the one who sorrows to give more caution for the future. The child will carry the pitcher86 of milk the more carefully next time by the more he has grieved over the past occurrence. By increasing sensitiveness and capacity for sorrow experience is strengthened, deepened, and completely adjusted to environment. Shallow and volatile87 natures, who take all loss and harm easily, and even gaily88, have little strength, and attain18 no great and permanent growth. But with most, when the object of strong desire is suddenly lost, not only will there be a disappearance89 of the positive feeling about it, but an actual minus or negative state will be generated, a reaction mode we term grief. By this grief the chief lessons of all higher experience are made possible. Grief is not a pathological phenomenon in mind, but in its place thoroughly90 normal and useful. Indeed, if under certain circumstances grief did not appear, mind 186would be proved very crude, obtuse91, or diseased. He who never feels sad about what has happened, is not of a progressive or highly advanced type. If one does not feel sorry for his past errors and hurtful actions, he plainly has so much the less motive92 force to higher action for the future. If sorrow had never entered the world of mind, if the whole corrective for injurious actions or want of action lay wholly in the immediate pain resulting or in the direct simple emotions like fear and anger, a most potent93 factor in psychic progress would be lacking. The possibility of going wrong, i.e., literally94 aside, and contrariwise to one’s own interests, is implied in the struggle for existence. The next best thing to the impossible status of being unable to do wrong, is to have the capacity of feeling for the wrong, that is, of experiencing grief. Sorrow is thus a corrective of the highest importance in the history of experience. The slips, willed and unwilled, from the narrow path of upward evolution are of necessity many; but a man is, on the whole, best doing the largest part in the evolution scheme in which he finds himself, who both knows the wrong as such, and is sorry for it, whether in the primitive selfish mode, or better still, on the higher ethical and religious grounds. The greatest and most efficient minds are those who have felt most keenly for their errors, faults, and sins.
As to the origin of grief, we may say with confidence that it is tolerably late, and certainly subsequent to anger and hate and like reactions. Under certain circumstances sorrow must be accounted a more favourable95 reaction than these. Rage is certainly impotent and useless on many occasions of recalled injury, and rage is besides a very intense emotion and expensive of energy. The general law in the development of emotion is toward milder, more economical, and more permanent forms, and then it is that sorrow must at some time have originated under the demands of life, and been preserved and developed under 187natural selection. Sorrow most probably originated as supplanting96 rage at the view or remembrance of injury done. In young children we often see rage mingled97 with the first manifestation98 of grief, and but slowly is the rage eliminated and pure grief attained. Sorrow exercises its function where rage is useless. The child cries over spilled milk partly from rage, partly from grief, but such mishaps99 will tend more and more to be attended by grief only, as the better and more economical reaction. Further, in a certain range of cases, sorrow in its manifestations100 serves to appease101 revenger, and sincere regret, unmistakably expressed, often saves the wrong-doer an equivalent harm. This form of sorrow function is distinctly cultivated in the education of children where they are taught to feel sorry for faults if they would be forgiven and escape punishment.
Grief in its origin and its earlier occurrence is not the spontaneous and almost irresistible102 impulse of our adult human experience, but, like all emotion and all progressive psychism, is by effort of will. That is, we must suppose that grief has its origin in some such nisus as a child exhibits when he is taught to be sorry for something he has done. Hence it is only gradually and with the lapse103 of many generations after its origin that sorrow becomes hereditary104 and spontaneous. At first sorrow was a distinct attainment105, rarely and but occasionally reached by any individual, and it is comparatively late in psychic history that it becomes a permanent and innate106 power. Sorrow also very gradually widens its sphere. At first purely selfish, a retrospective reaction at one’s own hurt, it becomes at length, through sociality and its concurrent107 advantages, altruistic108; sorrow is felt for others and the springs of sympathy and pity are developed. That this altruism109 is very late development is obvious, in that it has still to be taught even among the most advanced of the human race to their children. The child is taught to 188feel sorry for the cat he has hurt, for the blind man, for the cripple. And we must conclude that at one time in psychic history egoistic sorrow was likewise at the stage of development at which we now see altruistic, and we may suppose that in the far future the altruistic may come to the present status of the egoistic sorrow. However, for both there is an indefinite field for expansion, for refinement110 of sensibility, and for readiness and appropriateness of manifestation. Sorrow also will develop more and more on ethical and religious grounds. Remorse arises and develops; and also the “godly sorrow for sin.” We learn to feel, not merely sorry over the past as affecting our disadvantage, but to feel sorry conscientiously111 as our deeds or those of others conflict with the law of right or with the law of God. Those who have no God-consciousness, and so no feeling about their action in the sight of God, no sense of sinfulness, have yet often acute moral sense and feelings. However, the origin and function of the moral and religious sense in the light of natural selection is a wide subject which can only be alluded112 to here; suffice it to say that sorrow is thereby113 lifted to a peculiar and new plane of self-contained spirituality. That is, the bearing of it is often without relation to physical life-function, and even adverse114 thereto, and throughout has its value and sanction in itself alone.
One of the deepest and most significant of late forms of sorrow is that for the dead, and its importance is obvious from the fact that a word is especially coined to denote its expression, namely, mourning. Nothing can be more useless than mourning for the dead as far as the individual object is concerned; the most poignant115 sorrow cannot in anywise tend to reanimate the corpse116. However, it plainly serves as an index to the value put upon life, and so in general has a most powerful effect on conservation and upbuilding of life. Other things being equal, sensitiveness to this form of sorrow measures accurately117 possibly self-conservative 189effort or effort for others’ conservation, which in a state of sociality, is equivalent in value to one’s self. The lives for which there is the most mourning and real sorrow when death comes are the most valuable to the community, and for the conserving118 of which the utmost combined effort would be extended. Where life has little value attached to it, sorrow is slight and mourning short. As compared with the savage119 state, loss and injury to life is infinitely120 more respected in the great centres of modern civilization—the nuclei121 of progress. It is because we feel strongly for the safety of friends and relatives that we employ the best devices to insure their protection from injury and death. One who has sorrowed most deeply over the death of a friend caused by his own careless handling of a gun, will for the future be much more careful for himself and others. To be sure we sorrow deeply because we place a high estimate upon the life rather than place high estimate because we sorrow greatly; but if there were no sorrow reaction, there would be no emotion basis for the future caution and care, and it affects our general estimate of life. Thus there is ever a cumulative122 emotional development.
Perhaps the latest developed form of sorrow is the feeling of sadness which comes over one in reflecting upon pain as a universal fact of existence. The pessimistic mood, with its converse123, the optimistic, as based on philosophic124 generalization125, is certainly extremely late. Pain at pain in general, pleasure at pleasure as a purely general fact, are equally remote from primitive modes, and mark culminating phases. While, perhaps, there is a certain justification126 and value in being saddened by the spectacle of universal pain, yet a gravity rather than a despondency is its proper measure. Pain, punitive127 and premonitory, plays, as we have already noted128 more than once in our discussions, a most beneficent and essential part in the struggle for existence and in all the higher struggle. It 190is a necessary and salutary phenomenon, involved in the very nature of evolution by struggle; hence he who impugns129 pain and is offended at it, really impugns the psychic nature of things and desires with Schopenhauer the annihilation of will. As a matter of fact the extreme pessimistic spirit is more destructive to progress than even the most buoyant optimism, in that it nips all earnest and forceful activity in the bud. A foolishly happy-go-lucky activity is better than a paralysis130 of effort through conviction of its inherent painfulness and ultimate inutility. The scientific evidence, so far as we can now read it, points decisively to the belief that pain-will activity, an intense struggle, is the earliest mind, and the condition of its birth has been the law of its development, and for aught that we can see, ever will be. Into this we are born, and it is as foolish to run counter to it as to the law of gravitation. A philosophy which runs counter to reality must either build a new reality or subside131; but it is most certainly to be doubted whether the philosophic spirit ever has or ever will determine a general innovation in psychic evolution. But we cannot do more than merely advert132 to these large questions here.
With reference to the development of sorrow it is an obvious remark that much which causes grief in the earlier stages of mental growth ceases to have that effect with maturer experience. Thus the man may not notice, or may laugh at, or may feel irritation133 at occasions which in his early life would have wakened grief. On the contrary, much that seems grievous to the old is not so regarded by the young. In general, grief tends to become less frequent and paroxysmal, but more profound and lasting134 with the growth of mind.
As to the kinds of retrospective emotion the largest division is, of course, into the painful and pleasurable. We have touched only on some of the painful, but each painful emotion has its analogous135 pleasurable emotion. 191We have used the terms sorrow and grief as synonyms136. If we should make a distinction, it would be to put sadness or sorrow in antithesis137 to happiness, and grief to joy; that is, sorrow proceeds from outward circumstances, grief from subjective conditions. However, popular usage is not firm on this point. Regret is a mild sorrow. Remorse is the ethical side of sorrow. Resignation is a very late phase of emotion related to sorrow. A person says, My child was crushed in the accident, yet I do not grieve, but am quite resigned. Here certainly is a new mode of feeling about past harm, and it is a mode as far above sorrow proper as sorrow is above anger in the evolutionary138 scale. We do not lament139 or weep over the past, but there is self-conscious, self-constrained sinking of the will, and a composure which is not apathy140, but a gentle emotion wave. Nor is there a callousness141; one is not hardened, but softened142, and made the more sensitive. The emotion of resignation is thus cultivated and to be cultivated, and is yet in the volition143 stage which marks the early form of all emotions. Even in the highest human types resignation does not come, it must be brought; the instinctive impulse upon contemplating144 past personal evil is toward sorrow or anger and revenge, which must be checked, and resignation directly willed and assumed as the proper emotion. Resignation, then, as a growing point in psychic evolution, a distinct attainment as frame of mind, is generally and rightly accounted a virtue145. At present, then, it seems the culmination146 of retrospective emotion with regard to past personal injuries, and it exercises and will more and more exercise a most important function in human psychic development.

点击
收听单词发音

1
retrospect
![]() |
|
n.回顾,追溯;v.回顾,回想,追溯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2
prospect
![]() |
|
n.前景,前途;景色,视野 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3
prospective
![]() |
|
adj.预期的,未来的,前瞻性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4
phenomena
![]() |
|
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5
benefactor
![]() |
|
n. 恩人,行善的人,捐助人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6
differentiate
![]() |
|
vi.(between)区分;vt.区别;使不同 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7
repulse
![]() |
|
n.击退,拒绝;vt.逐退,击退,拒绝 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8
choleric
![]() |
|
adj.易怒的,性情暴躁的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9
purely
![]() |
|
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10
strictly
![]() |
|
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11
essentially
![]() |
|
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12
determined
![]() |
|
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13
potency
![]() |
|
n. 效力,潜能 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14
radical
![]() |
|
n.激进份子,原子团,根号;adj.根本的,激进的,彻底的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15
intensity
![]() |
|
n.强烈,剧烈;强度;烈度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16
kin
![]() |
|
n.家族,亲属,血缘关系;adj.亲属关系的,同类的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17
subjective
![]() |
|
a.主观(上)的,个人的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18
attain
![]() |
|
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19
attained
![]() |
|
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20
perfectly
![]() |
|
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21
immediate
![]() |
|
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22
interpretation
![]() |
|
n.解释,说明,描述;艺术处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23
primitive
![]() |
|
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24
cardinal
![]() |
|
n.(天主教的)红衣主教;adj.首要的,基本的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25
remorse
![]() |
|
n.痛恨,悔恨,自责 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26
relatively
![]() |
|
adv.比较...地,相对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27
solely
![]() |
|
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28
awakens
![]() |
|
v.(使)醒( awaken的第三人称单数 );(使)觉醒;弄醒;(使)意识到 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29
intensification
![]() |
|
n.激烈化,增强明暗度;加厚 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30
cognitive
![]() |
|
adj.认知的,认识的,有感知的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31
realization
![]() |
|
n.实现;认识到,深刻了解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32
distinguished
![]() |
|
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33
meting
![]() |
|
v.(对某人)施以,给予(处罚等)( mete的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34
inflict
![]() |
|
vt.(on)把…强加给,使遭受,使承担 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35
inflicting
![]() |
|
把…强加给,使承受,遭受( inflict的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36
administrative
![]() |
|
adj.行政的,管理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37
differentiation
![]() |
|
n.区别,区分 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38
proxy
![]() |
|
n.代理权,代表权;(对代理人的)委托书;代理人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39
vents
![]() |
|
(气体、液体等进出的)孔、口( vent的名词复数 ); (鸟、鱼、爬行动物或小哺乳动物的)肛门; 大衣等的)衩口; 开衩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40
stimulant
![]() |
|
n.刺激物,兴奋剂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41
deterrent
![]() |
|
n.阻碍物,制止物;adj.威慑的,遏制的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42
dwelling
![]() |
|
n.住宅,住所,寓所 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43
acting
![]() |
|
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44
irrational
![]() |
|
adj.无理性的,失去理性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45
instinctive
![]() |
|
adj.(出于)本能的;直觉的;(出于)天性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46
foresight
![]() |
|
n.先见之明,深谋远虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47
bent
![]() |
|
n.爱好,癖好;adj.弯的;决心的,一心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48
justifies
![]() |
|
证明…有理( justify的第三人称单数 ); 为…辩护; 对…作出解释; 为…辩解(或辩护) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49
impunity
![]() |
|
n.(惩罚、损失、伤害等的)免除 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50
despoil
![]() |
|
v.夺取,抢夺 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51
inevitably
![]() |
|
adv.不可避免地;必然发生地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52
psychical
![]() |
|
adj.有关特异功能现象的;有关特异功能官能的;灵魂的;心灵的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53
psychic
![]() |
|
n.对超自然力敏感的人;adj.有超自然力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54
molested
![]() |
|
v.骚扰( molest的过去式和过去分词 );干扰;调戏;猥亵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55
apparently
![]() |
|
adv.显然地;表面上,似乎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56
drenched
![]() |
|
adj.湿透的;充满的v.使湿透( drench的过去式和过去分词 );在某人(某物)上大量使用(某液体) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57
psychism
![]() |
|
心灵论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58
advantageous
![]() |
|
adj.有利的;有帮助的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59
prominence
![]() |
|
n.突出;显著;杰出;重要 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60
culminated
![]() |
|
v.达到极点( culminate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61
interfere
![]() |
|
v.(in)干涉,干预;(with)妨碍,打扰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62
reprisal
![]() |
|
n.报复,报仇,报复性劫掠 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63
vendetta
![]() |
|
n.世仇,宿怨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64
feud
![]() |
|
n.长期不和;世仇;v.长期争斗;世代结仇 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65
dominant
![]() |
|
adj.支配的,统治的;占优势的;显性的;n.主因,要素,主要的人(或物);显性基因 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66
civilized
![]() |
|
a.有教养的,文雅的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67
entirely
![]() |
|
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68
superseded
![]() |
|
[医]被代替的,废弃的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69
machinery
![]() |
|
n.(总称)机械,机器;机构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70
slaying
![]() |
|
杀戮。 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71
slayer
![]() |
|
n. 杀人者,凶手 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72
recedes
![]() |
|
v.逐渐远离( recede的第三人称单数 );向后倾斜;自原处后退或避开别人的注视;尤指问题 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73
elimination
![]() |
|
n.排除,消除,消灭 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74
ethical
![]() |
|
adj.伦理的,道德的,合乎道德的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75
Christian
![]() |
|
adj.基督教徒的;n.基督教徒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76
peculiar
![]() |
|
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77
repelled
![]() |
|
v.击退( repel的过去式和过去分词 );使厌恶;排斥;推开 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78
disturbance
![]() |
|
n.动乱,骚动;打扰,干扰;(身心)失调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79
defensive
![]() |
|
adj.防御的;防卫的;防守的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80
distress
![]() |
|
n.苦恼,痛苦,不舒适;不幸;vt.使悲痛 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81
intensify
![]() |
|
vt.加强;变强;加剧 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82
intensified
![]() |
|
v.(使)增强, (使)加剧( intensify的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83
inevitable
![]() |
|
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84
utterly
![]() |
|
adv.完全地,绝对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85
deplore
![]() |
|
vt.哀叹,对...深感遗憾 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86
pitcher
![]() |
|
n.(有嘴和柄的)大水罐;(棒球)投手 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87
volatile
![]() |
|
adj.反复无常的,挥发性的,稍纵即逝的,脾气火爆的;n.挥发性物质 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88
gaily
![]() |
|
adv.欢乐地,高兴地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89
disappearance
![]() |
|
n.消失,消散,失踪 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90
thoroughly
![]() |
|
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91
obtuse
![]() |
|
adj.钝的;愚钝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92
motive
![]() |
|
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93
potent
![]() |
|
adj.强有力的,有权势的;有效力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94
literally
![]() |
|
adv.照字面意义,逐字地;确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95
favourable
![]() |
|
adj.赞成的,称赞的,有利的,良好的,顺利的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96
supplanting
![]() |
|
把…排挤掉,取代( supplant的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97
mingled
![]() |
|
混合,混入( mingle的过去式和过去分词 ); 混进,与…交往[联系] | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98
manifestation
![]() |
|
n.表现形式;表明;现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99
mishaps
![]() |
|
n.轻微的事故,小的意外( mishap的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100
manifestations
![]() |
|
n.表示,显示(manifestation的复数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101
appease
![]() |
|
v.安抚,缓和,平息,满足 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102
irresistible
![]() |
|
adj.非常诱人的,无法拒绝的,无法抗拒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103
lapse
![]() |
|
n.过失,流逝,失效,抛弃信仰,间隔;vi.堕落,停止,失效,流逝;vt.使失效 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104
hereditary
![]() |
|
adj.遗传的,遗传性的,可继承的,世袭的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105
attainment
![]() |
|
n.达到,到达;[常pl.]成就,造诣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106
innate
![]() |
|
adj.天生的,固有的,天赋的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107
concurrent
![]() |
|
adj.同时发生的,一致的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108
altruistic
![]() |
|
adj.无私的,为他人着想的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109
altruism
![]() |
|
n.利他主义,不自私 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110
refinement
![]() |
|
n.文雅;高尚;精美;精制;精炼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111
conscientiously
![]() |
|
adv.凭良心地;认真地,负责尽职地;老老实实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112
alluded
![]() |
|
提及,暗指( allude的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113
thereby
![]() |
|
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114
adverse
![]() |
|
adj.不利的;有害的;敌对的,不友好的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115
poignant
![]() |
|
adj.令人痛苦的,辛酸的,惨痛的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116
corpse
![]() |
|
n.尸体,死尸 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117
accurately
![]() |
|
adv.准确地,精确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118
conserving
![]() |
|
v.保护,保藏,保存( conserve的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119
savage
![]() |
|
adj.野蛮的;凶恶的,残暴的;n.未开化的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120
infinitely
![]() |
|
adv.无限地,无穷地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121
nuclei
![]() |
|
n.核 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122
cumulative
![]() |
|
adj.累积的,渐增的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123
converse
![]() |
|
vi.谈话,谈天,闲聊;adv.相反的,相反 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124
philosophic
![]() |
|
adj.哲学的,贤明的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125
generalization
![]() |
|
n.普遍性,一般性,概括 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126
justification
![]() |
|
n.正当的理由;辩解的理由 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127
punitive
![]() |
|
adj.惩罚的,刑罚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128
noted
![]() |
|
adj.著名的,知名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129
impugns
![]() |
|
v.非难,指谪( impugn的第三人称单数 );对…有怀疑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130
paralysis
![]() |
|
n.麻痹(症);瘫痪(症) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131
subside
![]() |
|
vi.平静,平息;下沉,塌陷,沉降 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132
advert
![]() |
|
vi.注意,留意,言及;n.广告 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133
irritation
![]() |
|
n.激怒,恼怒,生气 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134
lasting
![]() |
|
adj.永久的,永恒的;vbl.持续,维持 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135
analogous
![]() |
|
adj.相似的;类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136
synonyms
![]() |
|
同义词( synonym的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137
antithesis
![]() |
|
n.对立;相对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138
evolutionary
![]() |
|
adj.进化的;演化的,演变的;[生]进化论的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139
lament
![]() |
|
n.悲叹,悔恨,恸哭;v.哀悼,悔恨,悲叹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140
apathy
![]() |
|
n.漠不关心,无动于衷;冷淡 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141
callousness
![]() |
|
参考例句: |
|
|
142
softened
![]() |
|
(使)变软( soften的过去式和过去分词 ); 缓解打击; 缓和; 安慰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143
volition
![]() |
|
n.意志;决意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144
contemplating
![]() |
|
深思,细想,仔细考虑( contemplate的现在分词 ); 注视,凝视; 考虑接受(发生某事的可能性); 深思熟虑,沉思,苦思冥想 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145
virtue
![]() |
|
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146
culmination
![]() |
|
n.顶点;最高潮 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |