But, say the experimental psychologists, subjective verification is impossible; psychology, if it is to become a science, must, like the other sciences, resort to the laboratory, and by definite and exact experiments produce the facts to order, study them by the most approved instruments, and obtain with certainty a knowledge of their laws. Now it is sufficiently28 easy to experiment on light, sound, and on plant growth in a laboratory, but how can we make consciousness to order with the same certainty? how can we know when we have got a consciousness, what kind it is, etc., except by subjective verification? You certainly cannot see the consciousness or touch it; but you must wholly rely on the subjective report of the individual experimented on as verified by your own consciousness. We have no impassive agent entirely under our control, except in hypnosis, and we cannot secure conditions with the same exactness in testing the intensity29 of some form of consciousness, as anger, as in testing the tensile strength of iron.
In the physical laboratory we produce certain conditions and we get invariably certain observable and measurable results, but in a psychological laboratory how shall I get with certainty a definite consciousness in a large number of cases and formulate24 its law? How shall I know at a given moment that the mental act of the agent is what my experiment requires? Moreover, does not experimental psychology by beginning with human consciousness enter rashly upon a very complex field? If it would get results, let it start with the simpler mental life, just as biology has 374founded itself in a study of simplest elements. But how shall psychology get at the consciousness of a clam30 with the same exactness as biology investigates the circulation of blood in the clam? It is plain, in short, that if we are to have a fruitful experimental psychology, some very important questions of method must first be settled. A method of getting psychoses to order, to obtain the exact reaction required, and knowing and realizing what it is when got, this is a desideratum not yet attained31. Further, we must remark that experimentation33 is itself a psychic act, and sense of experimentation is a disturbing factor in results; that is, a consciousness which is conscious of being experimented on is thereby34 complicated over mere35 observation method. This is markedly the case in self-experimentation. Consciousness is not, like an electric current or a sound wave, an objective fact, readily reproducible in the laboratory. And again ethics36 may interfere37 with psychical38 experiment. How far have we a right to incite39 psychosis for experiment’s sake? How far may psychical vivisection be carried in the name of science? A scientist who should for his own study make an animal or person angry, would be reprobated as would the artist who should incite anger in his model in order to catch artistic40 effect. However, that there is a vast scope for experimental psychology cannot be denied, and we may expect an indefinite multiplication41 of artificial psychoses and combinations comparable to the artificial syntheses and new compounds of the chemical laboratory. Mind may develop and act merely on the scientific motive42, and accomplish by tour de force a complex field of artificial consciousness quite distinct in origin and nature from natural consciousness. But for the present, at least, we regard not experiment but observation as the main method. Not laboratory, but field work, is most needed. The psychical scientist must go psychologizing, as the botanist43 goes botanizing. But there is no simple objective 375method as in botany. In order to have insight and interpretative power, there must be constant self-observation. He can know the real nature, conditions, and laws of other minds only so far as he realizes them in himself. If he has never feared, he will never know fear, and if he has never analyzed45 his own fear, he will not know its factors as occurring in others. All external consciousness is but a projection46 from the observer’s own consciousness.
But it may be said that mind is but a kind of neural47 function, and that physiological48 psychology will give us the true key to consciousness. But if one has never known any psychosis, as fear, directly in himself and indirectly49 in others, how will he find it in any nerve activities? Nervous activities are significant of psychosis only so far as psychosis is already known. In fact, the sciences of neurosis and psychosis are radically50 distinct. I stick a pin in my finger, the facts of pain, volition51, anger, etc., are of one order knowable only by introspection, the nerve excitation, current and reaction are of another order, constitute a complete circle, and are known only by inspection. Neurology in its own field can afford to ignore psychosis, for it does not find it: it finds only neural changes, and psychology likewise can afford to ignore physiology. These sciences stand self-sufficient, and may develop indefinitely each in its own way without meeting. Divide and conquer. The present mingling52 of the two is greatly to be deplored53. Thus in current books we often find such sentences as this: “The prevalent view hitherto has probably been that the same nervous apparatus54 which on moderate excitement produces sensations of pressure or temperature, produces feelings of pain when irritated with increased intensity.” (Ladd, Outlines Physiological Psychology, p. 387.)
This confusing of objective and subjective terms, sensation and irritation55, is but too frequent in recent treatises56. There is no way yet found of discovering psychic facts in 376neural, or neural in psychic, whatever may be their connection and interdependence. If we must have a cross-interpretation57, the psychologist has the vantage-ground on the basis of evolution by struggle. Nisus has developed all sense and motor organs and all nervous organs. It is the effort at seeing that has produced the optic nerve and the physiological function of sight. The vision and visual organ of the eagle came by incessant58 looking for prey59 during thousands of years. Hence mind is not reflex or concomitant of nerve, but nerve is outgrowth of mind in the struggle of existence, and a psychological physiology is better than a physiological psychology.
The psychological field is then first, self; second, other selves or individuals. In this latter phase of human psychology we have the psychology of adults, then adolescent, senile, infantile, sexual, and racial psychology. In sub-human or comparative psychology we include animals, wild and tame, also all discussion on plant psychism, mind stuff (e.g. Clifford’s), etc. In superhuman psychology we include all doctrine61 of cosmic intelligence, teleology62 (vide Mind, x. 420).
We have limited ourselves to evolutionary63 psychology and that of the feelings, and our data are mostly from adult human consciousness. Evolutionary psychology bases itself on the idea that mental development originates and is continued through struggle or will effort. Such evidence as we can gather points to feeling, impelled64 exertion65 as the essence of psychic evolution, and it proves fruitful when assumed as a guiding principle. And the principle of struggle is final. We cannot admit with Bain a principle of spontaneity. The activities of a new-born lamb are seemingly spontaneous only because they are the results of energies stored in ages of psychic effort. This doctrine of struggle does away with all impressionism and all passivity theories. Mind is not a receptivity, an association of impressions, a reflex or concomitant of 377physiological activities, but it is dynamic determining vital fact, an active response to the conditions of self-existence. This impetus66 of struggle and striving seems to feed all life and make life, and has its place, perhaps the highest in the dynamic whole we term the universe. While the significance of struggle is a question for philosophy, yet, as matter of fact, it is the only method of realization we know; and the office of humanity is the providing a wider and higher scope for struggle, the making new and independent life regions. Science and art, ethics and religion, which are at bottom only phases of emotionalism, are with utmost toil67 developed for themselves, and new emotions now arising and yet to arise will be cherished for their own sakes. Mind begins and continues long as the servant of the body, it ends by making the body its servant, the instrument of the spiritual life, the temple of the Holy Ghost; but all its evolution is through supreme68 effort. In the spiritual evolution he who loveth his life shall lose it, he whose struggle is in the primitive69 stage, namely, for material existence, loses thereby the real life, the life of the spirit.
It is possible, indeed, that we may over-estimate this salient fact of struggle, and certainly, in the present state of psychology, modesty70 is most commendable71. We would be far from assuming that the horizon of our mind is the limit of the universe. However, assuming mind as a biological function continually evolving in the service of self-conservation and self-furtherance, our endeavour has been to point out the general trend of the evolution of feeling, and to analyze44 some of its more important features. The little exploration we have made suggests the greatness of the unexplored field of mind, the vast number of psychoses unknown, and perhaps unknowable. The difficulties of the subjective method make it seem almost impossible to trace a complete history of mind. For mind to return over and realize its whole growth in all its ramifications73 378seems quite as hard as to develop new forms, or a whole region of artificial psychosis. In the filling up of missing links, psychology presents vastly greater difficulties than biology because of its subjectivity74 of method and the evanescent nature of the facts. Further, the more I analyze consciousness, the more I am convinced of the great and often unexpected complexity75 of apparently76 simple forms, and I am satisfied then the simplicity77 and completeness of the system-making psychologists, physiological or idealistic, is factitious and delusive78. An inductive science of mind is yet in its infancy79. My conclusion that mind was at first, and is always as progressive, feeling-impelled will, and that sensing arose as secondary, as useful cognitive80 effort, is simply the best reading I can make from present data when assuming the current doctrine of evolution.
A very important point, which needs to be worked out more fully81 than we have been able to do, is as to the nature of revival82 as involving emotion. Sense of re-experience and of the experienceable is one of the most important acquisitions of mind. The self-consolidation and organization of experience certainly does not come in the first place by any mechanical association, but we must assume that all mental progress is the result of the most intense, though often blind and fortuitous striving. But just how the return of an experience is cognized as return and as experience, and so becoming basis for emotion, this is a most difficult inquiry83 on which we have made but a few remarks in the chapter on the nature of emotion. Just when and how sense of experience is generated, and what is a full analysis of its nature, must be postponed84 to some future study, but I am convinced that a very fruitful field for investigation85 lies in this direction. Experience certainly does at a very early stage become compound, become self-appreciative in some form, as sense of the potentiality of things, but the elucidation86 of progress in 379this line is confronted by many difficulties. The history of ideation or representation as a power for self-conservation has yet to be traced with definiteness and completeness.
Another point, which needs a far fuller discussion than we can now give, is as to the nature of organic interaction in consciousness, as to the real quality of psychic cause and effect. We have all along assumed feeling as stimulant87 of will, both the will to know and the will to act, but just how does feeling develop will as struggling effort? What is the exact mode of connection? We conceive readily of physical impact as determining effects in the material world, and we conceive a transference and transmutation of energy, but in the psychic realm we have no entities88 as permanent existences susceptible89 of entering into relation with other entities. How then does a pain incite a will activity? A peculiar form of consciousness we term will activity does directly follow upon feeling pain, and, within limits, the greater the pain, the greater the willing, but we have no theory to express the mode of connection of these consciousnesses. All that we can say is that one does follow upon the other as somehow caused by it. Yet it is certain that the limitation of conscious capacity must in every individual determine a definite range of interaction, and, beyond some particular point, the more I feel, the less I will, and vice72 versa. But the phenomenon of interference is likewise as obscure as that of excitation. The development of distinct organic forms of consciousness is slowly carried forward, and they exercise a definite dynamic relation to each other, though the mode is as yet wholly obscure. Thus the largest subdivisions of consciousness, knowing, feeling, and willing, become determined90 as distinct organically related modes, like the nervous, nutritive-circulatory and motor systems forming one organic whole body. These psychic modes attain32 gradually an intricate and definite development, whose 380constant interdependent connection with an individual body we term a “mind.” And we must remark that this vital relation of one consciousness and one form of consciousness to another is in no wise effected through apperception, through a third distinct consciousness, a cognitive one, which unites them in idea. A feeling excited a will act long before there was consciousness of either, or of their relation. In general we must say that consciousness does not consciously forge for itself its own relations, but that in by far the larger part of psychic development new modes of consciousness and their inter-relations come in a totally unforeseen way, by a blind striving in the struggle for existence. It may be doubted, indeed, if even the most advanced human mind can really invent a new consciousness or a new relation in consciousness, but by intense effort it attains91 them. One of the obscurest points in biology is as to the nature and cause of morphological variation, and the subject of mental variation is for psychological science far more obscure. We presuppose that mental variations somehow arise in response to sudden and great emergencies, and in connection with the severest effort. Mental progress is, in all the earlier life at least, only achieved under pressure of intense pain actually experienced or ideally so,—emotion—and in some way an appropriate and saving psychosis as response of organism to environment originates. This new form may be indistinct, and proceed as a gradual differentiation92 from previous types, still the method of action of the motive force seems mysterious. We can see, indeed, the advantage which accrues93, for example, to the animal which is first able to detect danger or nutriment by scent60, but just the method of the rise and progress of scenting94 as a conscious process seems difficult to trace. We cannot say that power of smell arose because organs of smell were developed; this puts the cart before the horse. It is the struggle to sense that is the prime motive force in developing the sense 381organs and not vice versa. We do not smell because we have noses, but we have noses because we smell. That the sense of smell is a differentiated95 general sensation is likely enough, but we are unable to follow the steps. We know that the higher development of our present senses is attained only through great exertion, which determines a physical basis and organic progress—as in microscopy, telescopy, and so-called mind-reading—and if humanity is to develop in the future an electric sense or a telepathic sense, it must be reached by the intense struggle of a very few. We must believe that every mode of mind is at bottom but some modification96 of pre-existing forms, and it may be that as all modes of the material are interpretable in motion, so the manifold mental may be equally resolvable into some one type. Yet so far as we can now see, feeling, will, and cognition seem radically and primitively97 distinct. The missing links in mental evolution are most difficult to determine, for, as we have often remarked, while we can with comparative ease both determine fossil organic forms a priori and discover as realities, the intermediate mental forms can only be known through a subjective realization.
It does not help us to ascribe the advantageous98 variation to chance, a word, indeed, which does not belong to the dictionary of science, for it is but a cover to ignorance. Chance means that the determinate line of causes is hidden from the observer, who only knows that one of several results will take place. Chance is thus wholly relative; the gambling99 of savages101 is often calculable to the European, and so every affair of chance, as dice102 throwing, might be calculable to a superior intelligence who could compute103 or watch every turn of the dice. Chance, then, does not reside in the outward thing, is not a property of phenomena, but is wholly a subjective limitation of the investigating mind, hence to ascribe variation, physical or psychical, to chance is simply to objectivise our own imperfect cognition. The pre-supposition of all science is that every event or 382change has its definite determining antecedents, and that these are cognizable; hence the doctrine of chance has no place in any complete and real science of phenomena. That organism is, indeed, fortunate, which first achieves some notable and valuable psychic mode, but this good fortune does not in any wise come by chance, or by the passive enjoyment104 of concurrent105 favourable106 circumstances, but it is a well-earned superiority attained only by the severest and most patient responsive struggle, and there in every case a determinate series of steps in mental process which may ultimately be traceable.
Mental forms also arise through perversion107, competitors perverting108 originally advantageous variations, as has been already pointed109 out for paralysing-fear, sense-destroying anger, etc. Atavistic tendency gives pseudo-variations. Certain mental forms may be negative in origin, that is, merely reactionary110 from previous states. Given a high degree of any joyous111 emotion, say hope, and suddenly remove its conditions, and the swing is back beyond the zero point of emotion to actual negative emotion, as despair. Still the whole gamut112 from positive to negative, as from highest hope to deepest despair, is but a single generic113 emotion form of polar correlate elements, which have equally developed through struggle.
The subject of psychic intensity in general, and feeling intensity in particular, is likewise obscure and difficult. Physical intensity is comparatively easy to investigate in its nature and laws. For instance, in the case of light we clearly conceive its nature in terms of molecular114 motion, we measure it exactly by photometers, and we know it to proceed by the law of inverse115 squares. We have no similar certainty and clearness with regard to mental intensity. We speak of suffering very slight or very intense pains, but there is no scientific theory or valuation of psychic intensity. Mere physical intensity does not explain psychic, and we know that variations in rapidity 383of ether waves, for example, give, not quantitative116, but qualitative117 psychic variations. 640 billion vibrations118 are felt subjectively119 as the comparatively feeble colour blue, while 450 billion gives the striking and intense colour, red. It is only within a certain range and with certain forms of forces that Weber’s law of geometric and arithmetic increase applies.
Strictly120 speaking, we cannot apply quantitative conceptions to consciousness, inasmuch as mind has no spatiality121 which is the basis of idea of quantity and size. Hence the use of quantitative terms, like great, large, small, little, etc., is an indirect reference to intensity. I was in very great pain equals I was in very intense pain. No consciousness is literally122 either larger or smaller than another, because consciousnesses cannot, by reason of their non-spatial nature, enter into quantitative relations. So-called massive pains are really manifold. (See on this and kindred points my remarks in Nature, vol. 40, p. 642.)
A popular test of mental intensity, and one which has a relative value, is by the power needed to displace a given psychosis. Thus, if a man in a brown study walks into a pond of cold water without noticing it, we rightly conclude that he is thinking very intensely. This, of course establishes a scale relative to the individual, beginning with a psychosis which resists all displacing agencies, and ending with those of such very slight intensity that they give way to any and all diversions. A consciousness which supplants123 another must per se be more intense than the other. All that which rouses and diverts patients suffering from monomania and fixed124 ideas is practically equal in intensity. While we may thus pronounce one state as being equal in intensity to another or as being more or less intense than it, we yet have no ground for any numerical estimate. When a person says, “I feel twice as bad as I did yesterday, or I feel a hundred 384times as happy now as I was a year ago,” it is plainly a general and indefinite expression. Emotions have not yet been brought within the range of mathematical comparisons.
The intensity of feelings, as also of sensations, sustains undoubtedly125 certain mathematical relations to intensity of objective stimulus126, but owing to their complex nature, emotions, at least, must always be very difficult of interpretation by any such law as Weber’s, though simple pain may be brought more easily under some law. A pain, other things being equal, increases in some ratio to increment127 of physical stimulus. But we must believe that the reason for the diversity between proportion of actual increments128 of stimulus and actual increments of sensation and feeling is largely physiological. It certainly is not a true psycho-physical law, a law of relation of mind and matter, as is often claimed; for we cannot obtain an absolutely objective standard to test subjectivity. Hence any such law is merely a law of relation of different kinds of sensations, of different methods of interpreting the objective. Intensity of stimulus itself is always determinable only through some sensation, which is itself subject to Weber’s law. There is no objective standard for sense stimuli129; the measure of increasing stimulus to increasing sensation must be by some sense which has its own law with reference to physical increment as interpreted by another sense equally under law, and so on. Take pressure, for instance; we note by sense of sight the arm of a balance reacting regularly and constantly to definite small additions to load, while upon our own arm we do not notice the same additions in any such series of feeling of pressure increments. The arm and balance as disparate weighers must, of course, be in certain ratios related, and for a certain range we must have a geometrical series, but other ratios at other points.
That the degree of sensitivity is proportioned to the 385intensity of sensation already present, that the knock at the door must be the louder the more noise is going on within, is a defect in organic measurement, but it is not entirely absent in mechanical; scales which weigh by the ton do not respond easily or at all to minute weights. But, abstractly speaking, mechanic methods are in general far superior to organic; a fine balance weighs better than any arm, and a good camera pictures better than the best eye; that is, their ratio of discriminating130 sensibility is far greater than natural organs, and it may be as geometric series to arithmetic series. Practically, however, organic weighing and seeing are well adjusted to the demands of life. An appreciation131 of gravity, so far as it is of use to the organism, is secured, and if a finer sensibility were demanded it would be attained. That is, I am inclined to believe that the Weber-Fechner law of definite mathematical proportions is purely132 empirical, and does not mark a real limit or a fundamental psycho-physical law. If a man’s life and living depended on it, he could become a good weighing machine, and in time a race of organic weighers might be raised up which should vie in accuracy and range with the best scales now constructed. The quotient of sensitiveness is really indefinitely variable. It is probable, indeed, that deep sea organisms have a discriminative133 sensibility for both gravity and light far more delicate than the acutest human sense.
The whole subject of measurement of mental intensities134 must evidently be approached with the greatest care, and the diversities of researches in results and in their interpretation, is evidence that we have not completely isolated135 the facts we are in search of. Conscious experimentation must be allowed as tending to disturb sense. When attention is strained to marking sense increments it may very easily be deluded136, and wrongly suppose as to feeling or not feeling. Consciousness is by no means infallible as to its own acts, and especially when artificial. Feelings 386may, and often do, originate subjectively by suggestion, and hence may have no direct reference to the external cause which is under experimental manipulation.
And not only have we thus to guard against a strong tendency to introspective and apperceptive error as to what we actually experience, or how we experience, but we have also to constantly bear in mind that every experience, every sensing, as of pressure, light, etc., is not an isolated phenomenon, but as resting upon and involving the past, it can never be a simple direct measure of the objective present, as a given weight or light. Every conscious experience, like all other vital organic phenomena, has thus an individuality and differs from every other as every leaf differs from every other, and so the laws of experience are capable only of general expression. Since all consciousness is self-integrating and brings up the past into itself, it is always more than any occasional reflection of a present phenomenon; in the finest analysis every consciousness must have an equation of its own.
However, there is a quotient of relation of physical stimulus, mechanically measured, with increase and decrease of both sense and of pleasure-pain. The pack-carrier feels in a certain proportion to his present load pressure of weight-increments, and pressure pains also augment137, though probably not in strict corresponding ratio. It is a popular saying that the last straw breaks the camel’s back, and it is certain that pains rapidly culminate138. It is probable that increments which may not be sensed may yet be felt as pain. In fact, it is but very gradually that sense of pressure is evolved as practically free of pain; as a mere cognitive process it is always secondary to pleasure-pain states which are felt directly from weights or but slightly objectified. Pleasure-pain which proceeds from weights gradually is driven to sensing them—the evolution of the pressure sense—and to noting variations, sense increments, and if, like marine139 organisms, we ranged 387through pressure zones, the significance of discriminative sensibility might be very great.
However, it is obvious that in its rise and in its whole evolution, pleasure-pain is bound up with the pressure sense, but not with the arm of the balance as a record. Hence it is possible that Weber’s law, so far as applicable, is in some measure a result of feeling interference. The simplicity of direct reaction is being destroyed by the hedonalgic law disturbing the direct ratio; we may thus feel an increasing pain from increasing weights, and have decreasing pressure sense. Beyond a certain point the law of increments, with reference to external standard for sensing and for pleasure and pain are in inverse ratio. On a very hot day we notice more and more strongly each additional degree of heat by the temperature sense, but beyond a certain degree, peculiar to the individual at the time, sense of heat will rapidly diminish as heat increases, and with increase of pain.
As to the number of feelings, of qualitatively140 distinct states, we must on a general doctrine of evolution pronounce this to be innumerable and indefinite. The present forms of feeling in human consciousness of course represent but a small fraction of the total number which have arisen in the course of psychic evolution. Every distinct form implies a long evolution of intermediate types which are now for the most part beyond our realization and so beyond cognition. The process of naming affords some slight clue to the importance and multiformity of feeling, though this denotes only a few of the most obvious points which have impressed themselves on the popular mind. Certainly the most striking fact to ordinary introspection, human and sub-human, is feeling, and the manifold variety of simple pleasure-pains and of emotions has always, and will always, attract most strongly the general attention. It would be a most interesting and profitable study to follow the course of language in its denotation141 388of feeling. Varied142 expression for varied feelings is gradually achieved in vocal143 forms, which expressions become a language sense to denote the feeling expressed. Thus the hoarse144 bellow145 of rage will both express and denote rage. The vocal expression form as imitated is the earliest language form, and only very gradually does language assume the mechanical and arbitrary forms of its highest development. It is by imitating being mad vocally146 and otherwise, and pointing to the angered one, that the savage100 conveys the idea of anger. Gradually all but the vocal expression is dropped, and this conventionalized, becomes the origin of the word to denote the emotion in question. Feeling and emotion names are doubtless in their origin debased vocal expression forms, though in the later evolution of language this is generally not detectable147, and various other more indirect associations control language. Only states of consciousness which have attained a considerable force and prominence148 receive notice in the vocabulary of common speech. For many variances149 of feeling there is no word denotation, but it may be given by intonation150. The number of names of feeling is thus in any language, or in all languages, but a very rough index to the actual number of kinds of feeling, and we may expect that a thorough scientific analysis will develop as extended scientific nomenclature of feeling, as chemistry has of kinds of matter. At the present crude stage of psychology we must affirm that the number of cognizable, but unnamed feelings, far exceeds the number of the named, and that the number of the undiscriminated or the undiscovered feelings far exceeds the number of both forms.
On the whole, it has been the object of our present studies to point out with some definiteness the extent and mode of the early differentiation of feeling. Owing to the peculiar difficulties which beset151 this form of study and to which we have often adverted152, our conclusions may seem 389rather meagre and uncertain, but it is sufficient if they emphasize a region of introspective study, which, though of the utmost practical importance, is yet the most neglected of all in psychic science; and we hope to have set forth153 the most probable general order of mental evolution with some distinctness as based on the struggle of existence. Mind, beginning in pure pain, and culminating on the feeling side in the higher emotions, contains an intermediate, continuous, indefinite number of forms, determined by the demands of life and preserved by natural selection, many of which are so entirely outgrown154 that they may be for ever beyond human conception, and many occurring only occasionally in human consciousness as survivals, and a large, yet comparatively small number constituting the present evolution phase of feeling in human consciousness. We have dwelt specially9 on the lower developments, the rise of objectification and its nature, the rise and value of emotion, with some characterization of the simpler and earlier emotions. Emotion is superior to and supplants sensation, though based thereon. The poison I fear, I abstain155 from without tasting; but with lower psychisms there must be a direct sensing of the thing before its experience quality is apprehended156.
Must we not suppose that feeling and emotion is destined157 to be an evanescent form in the evolution of mind? Is not the emotional type gradually disappearing, and will not the men of the future be pure indifferentists? Or are we rather to judge that emotion will always continue to strengthen and deepen? In an intellectual and introspective age like our own the na?ve mental life, which is primitive and merely natural, vanishes, and we find that men everywhere, like Kenyon, in Howell’s novel, The Undiscovered Country are constantly destroying their feelings by pulling them up by the roots to see what they are and why they are. Such are only occasionally surprised into a genuine emotion, but they greet it with joy, 390and forthwith pull it to pieces in a morbid158 self-analysis. An indifferentism, born of intellectual curiosity, of scepticism or of pessimism159, is, in fact, a pathological state, a certain mono-emotionalism, for humanity cannot escape emotionalism if it would. This blasé way of looking at things and feeling about them, is a decadent160 symptom in an artificial age. The struggle of life in a natural state always demands a varied, prompt, and frank emotionalism. If mind lose its love of things and men, it may yet be moved to highest attainment161 by sentiments like the love of science and truth. An intense intellectual life must be driven to its strugglings and achievements by some strong motive power, some powerful emotion, though this may be purely impersonal162, like the conviction of duty, or the love of truth. Feeling as the fundamental element in mind, as the very core of mentality, as the force which actuates both will and cognition, can never be destroyed, and for the future progress of mind, as for the past, we are assured that feeling and emotion will not cease to become ever stronger, deeper, and nobler.
The End
点击收听单词发音
1 psychology | |
n.心理,心理学,心理状态 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 cognate | |
adj.同类的,同源的,同族的;n.同家族的人,同源词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 premature | |
adj.比预期时间早的;不成熟的,仓促的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 insufficient | |
adj.(for,of)不足的,不够的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 inspection | |
n.检查,审查,检阅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 expressive | |
adj.表现的,表达…的,富于表情的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 realization | |
n.实现;认识到,深刻了解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 specially | |
adv.特定地;特殊地;明确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 mentality | |
n.心理,思想,脑力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 fins | |
[医]散热片;鱼鳍;飞边;鸭掌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 ductility | |
n.展延性,柔软性,顺从;韧性;塑性;展性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 psychic | |
n.对超自然力敏感的人;adj.有超自然力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 psychism | |
心灵论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 subjective | |
a.主观(上)的,个人的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 hindrance | |
n.妨碍,障碍 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 embryo | |
n.胚胎,萌芽的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 disclaim | |
v.放弃权利,拒绝承认 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 consensus | |
n.(意见等的)一致,一致同意,共识 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 standing | |
n.持续,地位;adj.永久的,不动的,直立的,不流动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 formulated | |
v.构想出( formulate的过去式和过去分词 );规划;确切地阐述;用公式表示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 formulate | |
v.用公式表示;规划;设计;系统地阐述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 rigidly | |
adv.刻板地,僵化地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 uncertainty | |
n.易变,靠不住,不确知,不确定的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 physiology | |
n.生理学,生理机能 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 intensity | |
n.强烈,剧烈;强度;烈度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 clam | |
n.蛤,蛤肉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 experimentation | |
n.实验,试验,实验法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 ethics | |
n.伦理学;伦理观,道德标准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 interfere | |
v.(in)干涉,干预;(with)妨碍,打扰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 psychical | |
adj.有关特异功能现象的;有关特异功能官能的;灵魂的;心灵的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 incite | |
v.引起,激动,煽动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 artistic | |
adj.艺术(家)的,美术(家)的;善于艺术创作的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 multiplication | |
n.增加,增多,倍增;增殖,繁殖;乘法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 botanist | |
n.植物学家 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 analyze | |
vt.分析,解析 (=analyse) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 analyzed | |
v.分析( analyze的过去式和过去分词 );分解;解释;对…进行心理分析 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 projection | |
n.发射,计划,突出部分 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 neural | |
adj.神经的,神经系统的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 physiological | |
adj.生理学的,生理学上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 indirectly | |
adv.间接地,不直接了当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 radically | |
ad.根本地,本质地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 volition | |
n.意志;决意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 mingling | |
adj.混合的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 deplored | |
v.悲叹,痛惜,强烈反对( deplore的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 apparatus | |
n.装置,器械;器具,设备 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 irritation | |
n.激怒,恼怒,生气 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 treatises | |
n.专题著作,专题论文,专著( treatise的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 interpretation | |
n.解释,说明,描述;艺术处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 incessant | |
adj.不停的,连续的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 prey | |
n.被掠食者,牺牲者,掠食;v.捕食,掠夺,折磨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 scent | |
n.气味,香味,香水,线索,嗅觉;v.嗅,发觉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 teleology | |
n.目的论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 evolutionary | |
adj.进化的;演化的,演变的;[生]进化论的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 impelled | |
v.推动、推进或敦促某人做某事( impel的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 exertion | |
n.尽力,努力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 impetus | |
n.推动,促进,刺激;推动力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 toil | |
vi.辛劳工作,艰难地行动;n.苦工,难事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 modesty | |
n.谦逊,虚心,端庄,稳重,羞怯,朴素 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 commendable | |
adj.值得称赞的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 ramifications | |
n.结果,后果( ramification的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 subjectivity | |
n.主观性(主观主义) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 complexity | |
n.复杂(性),复杂的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 apparently | |
adv.显然地;表面上,似乎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 simplicity | |
n.简单,简易;朴素;直率,单纯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 delusive | |
adj.欺骗的,妄想的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 infancy | |
n.婴儿期;幼年期;初期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 cognitive | |
adj.认知的,认识的,有感知的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 revival | |
n.复兴,复苏,(精力、活力等的)重振 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 postponed | |
vt.& vi.延期,缓办,(使)延迟vt.把…放在次要地位;[语]把…放在后面(或句尾)vi.(疟疾等)延缓发作(或复发) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 investigation | |
n.调查,调查研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 elucidation | |
n.说明,阐明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 stimulant | |
n.刺激物,兴奋剂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 entities | |
实体对像; 实体,独立存在体,实际存在物( entity的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 susceptible | |
adj.过敏的,敏感的;易动感情的,易受感动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 attains | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的第三人称单数 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 differentiation | |
n.区别,区分 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 accrues | |
v.增加( accrue的第三人称单数 );(通过自然增长)产生;获得;(使钱款、债务)积累 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 scenting | |
vt.闻到(scent的现在分词形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 differentiated | |
区分,区别,辨别( differentiate的过去式和过去分词 ); 区别对待; 表明…间的差别,构成…间差别的特征 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 modification | |
n.修改,改进,缓和,减轻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 primitively | |
最初地,自学而成地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 advantageous | |
adj.有利的;有帮助的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 gambling | |
n.赌博;投机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 savage | |
adj.野蛮的;凶恶的,残暴的;n.未开化的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 savages | |
未开化的人,野蛮人( savage的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 dice | |
n.骰子;vt.把(食物)切成小方块,冒险 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 compute | |
v./n.计算,估计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 enjoyment | |
n.乐趣;享有;享用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 concurrent | |
adj.同时发生的,一致的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 favourable | |
adj.赞成的,称赞的,有利的,良好的,顺利的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 perversion | |
n.曲解;堕落;反常 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 perverting | |
v.滥用( pervert的现在分词 );腐蚀;败坏;使堕落 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 pointed | |
adj.尖的,直截了当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 reactionary | |
n.反动者,反动主义者;adj.反动的,反动主义的,反对改革的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 joyous | |
adj.充满快乐的;令人高兴的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 gamut | |
n.全音阶,(一领域的)全部知识 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 generic | |
adj.一般的,普通的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 molecular | |
adj.分子的;克分子的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 inverse | |
adj.相反的,倒转的,反转的;n.相反之物;v.倒转 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 quantitative | |
adj.数量的,定量的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 qualitative | |
adj.性质上的,质的,定性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 vibrations | |
n.摆动( vibration的名词复数 );震动;感受;(偏离平衡位置的)一次性往复振动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 subjectively | |
主观地; 臆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 spatiality | |
空间性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 literally | |
adv.照字面意义,逐字地;确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 supplants | |
把…排挤掉,取代( supplant的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 undoubtedly | |
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 stimulus | |
n.刺激,刺激物,促进因素,引起兴奋的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 increment | |
n.增值,增价;提薪,增加工资 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 increments | |
n.增长( increment的名词复数 );增量;增额;定期的加薪 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 stimuli | |
n.刺激(物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 discriminating | |
a.有辨别能力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 appreciation | |
n.评价;欣赏;感谢;领会,理解;价格上涨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 purely | |
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 discriminative | |
有判别力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 intensities | |
n.强烈( intensity的名词复数 );(感情的)强烈程度;强度;烈度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 isolated | |
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 deluded | |
v.欺骗,哄骗( delude的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 augment | |
vt.(使)增大,增加,增长,扩张 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 culminate | |
v.到绝顶,达于极点,达到高潮 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 marine | |
adj.海的;海生的;航海的;海事的;n.水兵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 qualitatively | |
质量上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141 denotation | |
n.(明示的)意义;指示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142 varied | |
adj.多样的,多变化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143 vocal | |
adj.直言不讳的;嗓音的;n.[pl.]声乐节目 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144 hoarse | |
adj.嘶哑的,沙哑的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145 bellow | |
v.吼叫,怒吼;大声发出,大声喝道 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146 vocally | |
adv. 用声音, 用口头, 藉著声音 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147 detectable | |
adj.可发觉的;可查明的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148 prominence | |
n.突出;显著;杰出;重要 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149 variances | |
n.变化( variance的名词复数 );不和;差异;方差 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150 intonation | |
n.语调,声调;发声 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151 beset | |
v.镶嵌;困扰,包围 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
152 adverted | |
引起注意(advert的过去式与过去分词形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
153 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
154 outgrown | |
长[发展] 得超过(某物)的范围( outgrow的过去分词 ); 长[发展]得不能再要(某物); 长得比…快; 生长速度超过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
155 abstain | |
v.自制,戒绝,弃权,避免 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
156 apprehended | |
逮捕,拘押( apprehend的过去式和过去分词 ); 理解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
157 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
158 morbid | |
adj.病的;致病的;病态的;可怕的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
159 pessimism | |
n.悲观者,悲观主义者,厌世者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
160 decadent | |
adj.颓废的,衰落的,堕落的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
161 attainment | |
n.达到,到达;[常pl.]成就,造诣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
162 impersonal | |
adj.无个人感情的,与个人无关的,非人称的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |