It is proposed to examine in the following chapter, what is the form of government established in America on the principle of the sovereignty of the people; what are its resources, its hindrances2, its advantages, and its dangers. The first difficulty which presents itself arises from the complex nature of the constitution of the United States, which consists of two distinct social structures, connected, and, as it were, encased, one within the other; two governments, completely separate, and almost independent, the one fulfilling the ordinary duties, and responding to the daily and indefinite calls of a community, the other circumscribed4 within certain limits, and only exercising an exceptional authority over the general interests of the country. In short, there are twenty-four small sovereign nations, whose agglomeration5 constitutes the body of the union. To examine the union before we have studied the states, would be to adopt a method filled with obstacles. The Federal government of the United States was the last which was adopted; and it is in fact nothing more than a modification6 or a summary of these republican principles which were current in the whole community before it existed, and independently of its existence. Moreover, the federal government is, as I have just observed, the exception; the government of the states is the rule. The author who should attempt to exhibit the picture as a whole, before he had explained its details, would necessarily fall into obscurity and repetition.
The great political principles which govern American society at this day, undoubtedly8 took their origin and their growth in the state. It is therefore necessary to become acquainted with the state in order to possess a clew to the remainder. The states which at present compose the American union, all present the same features as far as regards the external aspect of their institutions. Their political or administrative9 existence is centred in three foci of action, which may not inaptly be compared to the different nervous centres which convey motion to the human body. The township is in the lowest order, then the county, and lastly the state; and I propose to devote the following chapter to the examination of these three divisions.
THE AMERICAN SYSTEM OF TOWNSHIPS AND MUNICIPAL BODIES.{63}
Why the Author begins the Examination of the Political Institutions with the Township.—Its Existence in all Nations.—Difficulty of Establishing and Preserving Independence.—Its Importance.—Why the Author has selected the Township System of New England as the main Object of his Inquiry11.
It is not undesignedly that I begin this subject with the township. The village or township is the only association which is so perfectly12 natural, that wherever a number of men are collected, it seems to constitute itself.
The town, or tithing, as the smallest division of a community, must necessarily exist in all nations, whatever their laws and customs may be: if man makes monarchies13, and establishes republics, the first association of mankind seems constituted by the hand of God. But although the existence of the township is coeval14 with that of man, its liberties are not the less rarely respected and easily destroyed. A nation is always able to establish great political assemblies, because it habitually15 contains a certain number of individuals fitted by their talents, if not by their habits, for the direction of affairs. The township is, on the contrary, composed of coarser materials, which are less easily fashioned by the legislator. The difficulties which attend the consolidation16 of its independence rather augment17 than diminish with the increasing enlightenment of the people. A highly-civilized community spurns18 the attempts of a local independence, is disgusted at its numerous blunders, and is apt to despair of success before the experiment is completed. Again, no immunities19 are so ill-protected from the encroachments of the supreme20 power as those of municipal bodies in general: they are unable to struggle, single-handed, against a strong or an enterprising government, and they cannot defend their cause with success unless it be identified with the customs of the nation and supported by public opinion. Thus, until the independence of townships is amalgamated21 with the manners of a people, it is easily destroyed; and it is only after a long existence in the laws that it can be thus amalgamated. Municipal freedom eludes22 the exertions24 of man; it is rarely created; but it is, as it were, secretly and spontaneously engendered26 in the midst of a semi-barbarous state of society. The constant action of the laws and the national habits, peculiar27 circumstances, and above all, time, may consolidate28 it; but there is certainly no nation on the continent of Europe which has experienced its advantages. Nevertheless, local assemblies of citizens constitute the strength of free nations. Municipal institutions are to liberty what primary schools are to science; they bring it within the people's reach, they teach men how to use and how to enjoy it. A nation may establish a system of free government, but without the spirit of municipal institutions it cannot have the spirit of liberty. The transient passions, and the interests of an hour, or the chance of circumstances, may have created the external forms of independence; but the despotic tendency which has been repelled29 will, sooner or later, inevitably30 reappear on the surface.
In order to explain to the reader the general principles on which the political organisations of the counties and townships of the United States rest, I have thought it expedient31 to choose one of the states of New England as an example, to examine the mechanism32 of its constitution, and then to cast a general glance over the country.
The township and the county are not organized in the same manner in every part of the union; it is, however, easy to perceive that the same principles have guided the formation of both of them throughout the union. I am inclined to believe that these principles have been carried farther in New England than elsewhere, and consequently that they offer greater facilities to the observations of a stranger.
The institutions of New England form a complete and regular whole; they have received the sanction of time, they have the support of the laws, and the still stronger support of the manners of the community, over which they exercise the most prodigious33 influence; they consequently deserve our attention on every account.
LIMITS OF THE TOWNSHIP.
The township of New England is a division which stands between the commune and the canton of France, and which corresponds in general to the English tithing, or town. Its average population is from two to three thousand;{64} so that, on the one hand, the interests of the inhabitants are not likely to conflict, and, on the other, men capable of conducting its affairs are always to be found among its citizens.
AUTHORITIES OF THE TOWNSHIP IN NEW ENGLAND.
The People the Source of all Power here as Elsewhere.—Manages its own Affairs. No Corporation.—The greater part of the Authority vested in the Hands of the Selectmen.—How the Selectmen act.—Town-meeting.—Enumeration of the public Officers of the Township Obligatory34 and remunerated Functions.
In the township, as well as everywhere else, the people is the only source of power; but in no stage of government does the body of citizens exercise a more immediate35 influence. In America, the people is a master whose exigences demand obedience36 to the utmost limits of possibility.
In New England the majority acts by representatives in the conduct of the public business of the state; but if such an arrangement be necessary in general affairs, in the township, where the legislative37 and administrative action of the government is in more immediate contact with the subject, the system of representation is not adopted. There is no corporation; but the body of electors, after having designated its magistrates39, directs them in anything that exceeds the simple and ordinary executive business of the state.{65}
This state of things is so contrary to our ideas, and so different from our customs, that it is necessary for me to adduce some examples to explain it thoroughly40.
The public duties in the township are extremely numerous and minutely divided, as we shall see farther on; but the large proportion of administrative power is vested in the hands of a small number of individuals called "the selectmen."{66}
The general laws of the state impose a certain number of obligations on the selectmen, which may they fulfil without the authorization41 of the body they govern, but which they can only neglect on their own responsibility. The law of the state obliges them, for instance, to draw up the list of electors in the townships; and if they omit this part of their functions, they are guilty of a misdemeanor. In all the affairs, however, which are determined42 by the town-meeting, the selectmen are the organs of the popular mandate43, as in France the maire executes the decree of the municipal council. They usually act upon their own responsibility, and merely put in practice principles which have been previously44 recognised by the majority. But if any change is to be introduced in the existing state of things, or if they wish to undertake any new enterprise, they are obliged to refer to the source of their power. If, for instance, a school is to be established, the selectmen convoke45 the whole body of electors on a certain day at an appointed place; they explain the urgency of the case; they give their opinion on the means of satisfying it, on the probable expense, and the site which seems to be most favorable. The meeting is consulted on these several points; it adopts the principle, marks out the site, votes the rate, and confides46 the execution of its resolution to the selectmen.
The selectmen alone have the right of calling a town-meeting; but they may be requested to do so: if the citizens are desirous of submitting a new project to the assent47 of the township, they may demand a general convocation of the inhabitants; the selectmen are obliged to comply, but they have only the right of presiding at the meeting.{67}
The selectmen are elected every year in the month of April or of May. The town-meeting chooses at the same time a number of municipal magistrates, who are intrusted with important administrative functions. The assessors rate the township; the collectors receive the rate. A constable48 is appointed to keep the peace, to watch the streets, and to forward the execution of the laws; the town-clerk records all the town votes, orders, grants, births, deaths, and marriages; the treasurer49 keeps the funds; the overseer of the poor performs the difficult task of superintending the action of the poor laws; committee-men are appointed to attend to the schools and to public instruction; and the road-surveyors, who take care of the greater and lesser50 thoroughfares of the township, complete the list of the principal functionaries51. They are, however, still farther subdivided52; and among the municipal officers are to be found parish commissioners53, who audit54 the expenses of public worship; different classes of inspectors55, some of whom are to direct the citizens in case of fire; tithing-men, listers, haywards, chimney-viewers, fence-viewers to maintain the bounds of property, timber-measurers, and sealers of weights and measures.{68}
There are nineteen principal offices in a township. Every inhabitant is constrained56, on pain of being fined, to undertake these different functions; which, however, are almost all paid, in order that the poor citizens may be able to give up their time without loss. In general the American system is not to grant a fixed58 salary to its functionaries. Every service has its price, and they are remunerated in proportion to what they have done.
EXISTENCE OF THE TOWNSHIP.
Every one the best Judge of his own Interest.—Corollary of the Principle of the Sovereignty of the People.—Application of these Doctrines60 in the Townships of America.—The Township of New England is Sovereign in that which concerns itself alone; subject to the State in all other matters.—Bond of Township and the State.—In France the Government lends its Agents to the Commune.—In America the Reverse occurs.
I have already observed, that the principle of the sovereignty of the people governs the whole political system of the Anglo-Americans. Every page of this book will afford new instances of the same doctrine59. In the nations by which the sovereignty of the people is recognised, every individual possesses an equal share of power, and participates alike in the government of the state. Every individual is therefore supposed to be as well informed, as virtuous61, and as strong, as any of his fellow-citizens. He obeys the government, not because he is inferior to the authorities which conduct it, or that he is less capable than his neighbor of governing himself, but because he acknowledges the utility of an association with his fellow-men, and because he knows that no such association can exist without a regulating force. If he be a subject in all that concerns the mutual62 relations of citizens, he is free and responsible to God alone for all that concerns himself. Hence arises the maxim63 that every one is the best and the sole judge of his own private interest, and that society has no right to control a man's actions, unless they are prejudicial to the common weal, or unless the common weal demands his co-operation. This doctrine is universally admitted in the United States. I shall hereafter examine the general influence which it exercises on the ordinary actions of life: I am now speaking of the nature of municipal bodies.
The township, taken as a whole, and in relation to the government of the country, may be looked upon as an individual to whom the theory I have just alluded65 to is applied67. Municipal independence is therefore a natural consequence of the principle of the sovereignty of the people in the United States, all the American republics recognise it more or less; but circumstances have peculiarly favored its growth in New England.
In this part of the union the impulsion of political activity was given in the townships; and it may almost be said that each of them originally formed an independent nation. When the kings of England asserted their supremacy68, they were contented69 to assume the central power of the state. The townships of New England remained as they were before; and although they are now subject to the state, they were at first scarcely dependent upon it. It is important to remember that they have not been invested with privileges, but that they seem, on the contrary, to have surrendered a portion of their independence to the state. The townships are only subordinate to the state in those interests which I shall term social, as they are common to all the citizens. They are independent in all that concerns themselves; and among the inhabitants of New England I believe that not a man is to be found who would acknowledge that the state has any right to interfere70 in their local interests. The towns of New England buy and sell, prosecute71 or are indicted72, augment or diminish their rates, without the slightest opposition73 on the part of the administrative authority of the state.
They are bound, however, to comply with the demands of the community. If the state is in need of money, a town can neither give nor withhold74 the supplies. If the state projects a road, the township cannot refuse to let it cross its territory; if a police regulation is made by the state, it must be enforced by the town. A uniform system of instruction is organised all over the country, and every town is bound to establish the schools which the law ordains75. In speaking of the administration of the United States, I shall have occasion to point out the means by which the townships are compelled to obey in these different cases: I here merely show the existence of the obligation. Strict as this obligation is, the government of the state imposes it in principle only, and in its performance the township resumes all its independent rights. Thus, taxes are voted by the state, but they are assessed and collected by the township; the existence of a school is obligatory, but the township builds, pays, and superintends it. In France the state collector receives the local imposts; in America the town collector receives the taxes of the state. Thus the French government lends its agents to the commune; in America, the township is the agent of the government. This fact alone shows the extent of the differences which exist between the two nations.
PUBLIC SPIRIT OF THE TOWNSHIPS OF NEW ENGLAND.
How the Township of New England wins the Affections of its Inhabitants.—Difficulty of creating local public Spirit in Europe.—The Rights and Duties of the American Township favorable to it.—Characteristics of Home in the United States.—Manifestations of public Spirit in New England.—Its happy Effects.
In America, not only do municipal bodies exist, but they are kept alive and supported by public spirit. The township of New England possesses two advantages which infallibly secure the attentive76 interest of mankind, namely, independence and authority. Its sphere is indeed small and limited, but within that sphere its action is unrestrained; and its independence would give to it a real importance, even if its extent and population did not ensure it.
It is to be remembered that the affections of men are generally turned only where there is strength. Patriotism77 is not durable78 in a conquered nation. The New Englander is attached to his township, not only because he was born in it, but because it constitutes a strong and free social body of which he is a member, and whose government claims and deserves the exercise of his sagacity. In Europe, the absence of local public spirit is a frequent subject of regret to those who are in power; every one agrees that there is no surer guarantee of order and tranquillity80, and yet nothing is more difficult to create. If the municipal bodies were made powerful and independent, the authorities of the nation might be disunited, and the peace of the country endangered. Yet, without power and independence, a town may contain good subjects, but it can have no active citizens. Another important fact is, that the township of New England is so constituted as to excite the warmest of human affections, without arousing the ambitious passions of the heart of man. The officers of the county are not elected, and their authority is very limited. Even the state is only a second-rate community, whose tranquil79 and obscure administration offers no inducement sufficient to draw men away from the circle of their interests into the turmoil81 of public affairs. The federal government confers power and honor on the men who conduct it; but these individuals can never be very numerous. The high station of the presidency82 can only be reached at an advanced period of life; and the other federal functionaries are generally men who have been favored by fortune, or distinguished83 in some other career. Such cannot be the permanent aim of the ambitious. But the township serves as a centre for the desire of public esteem84, the want of exciting interests, and the taste for authority and popularity, in the midst of the ordinary relations of life: and the passions which commonly embroil85 society, change their character when they find a vent86 so near the domestic hearth87 and the family circle.
In the American states power has been disseminated88 with admirable skill, for the purpose of interesting the greatest possible number of persons in the common weal. Independently of the electors who are from time to time called into action, the body politic7 is divided into innumerable functionaries and officers, who all, in their several spheres, represent the same powerful corporation in whose name they act. The local administration thus affords an unfailing source of profit and interest to a vast number of individuals.
The American system, which divides the local authority among so many citizens, does not scruple89 to multiply the functions of the town officers. For in the United States, it is believed, and with truth, that patriotism is a kind of devotion, which is strengthened by ritual observance. In this manner the activity of the township is continually perceptible; it is daily manifested in the fulfilment of a duty, or the exercise of a right; and a constant though gentle motion is thus kept up in society which animates90 without disturbing it.
The American attaches himself to his home, as the mountaineer clings to his hills, because the characteristic features of his country are there more distinctly marked than elsewhere. The existence of the townships of New England is in general a happy one. Their government is suited to their tastes, and chosen by themselves. In the midst of the profound peace and general comfort which reign1 in America, the commotions91 of municipal discord92 are infrequent. The conduct of local business is easy. The political education of the people has long been complete; say rather that it was complete when the people first set foot upon the soil. In New England no tradition exists of a distinction of ranks; no portion of the community is tempted93 to oppress the remainder; and the abuses which may injure isolated94 individuals are forgotten in the general contentment which prevails. If the government is defective95 (and it would no doubt be easy to point out its deficiencies), the fact that it really emanates96 from those it governs, and that it acts, either ill or well, casts the protecting spell of a parental97 pride over its faults. No term of comparison disturbs the satisfaction of the citizen: England formerly98 governed the mass of the colonies, but the people was always sovereign in the township, where its rule is not only an ancient, but a primitive99 state.
The native of New England is attached to his township because it is independent and free; his co-operation in its affairs ensures his attachment100 to its interest; the well-being101 it affords him secures his affection; and its welfare is the aim of his ambition and of his future exertions; he takes a part in every occurrence in the place; he practises the art of government in the small sphere within his reach; he accustoms102 himself to those forms which can alone ensure the steady progress of liberty; he imbibes103 their spirit; he acquires a taste for order, comprehends the union of the balance of powers, and collects clear practical notions on the nature of his duties and the extent of his rights.
THE COUNTIES OF NEW ENGLAND.
The division of the counties in America has considerable analogy with that of the arrondissements of France. The limits of the counties are arbitrarily laid down, and the various districts which they contain have no necessary connexion, no common traditional or natural sympathy; their object is simply to facilitate the administration of public affairs.
The extent of the township was too small to contain a system of judicial64 institutions; each county has, however, a court of justice,{69} a sheriff to execute its decrees, and a prison for criminals. There are certain wants which are felt alike by all the townships of a county; it is therefore natural that they should be satisfied by a central authority. In the state of Massachusetts this authority is vested in the hands of several magistrates who are appointed by the governor of the state, with the advice{70} of his council.{71} The officers of the county have only a limited and occasional authority, which is applicable to certain predetermined cases. The state and the townships possess all the power requisite104 to conduct public business. The budget of the county is only drawn105 up by its officers, and is voted by the legislature.{72} There is no assembly which directly or indirectly106 represents the county; it has, therefore, properly speaking, no political existence.
A twofold tendency may be discerned in the American constitutions, which impels107 the legislator to centralize the legislative, and to disperse108 the executive power. The township of New England has in itself an indestructible element of independence; but this distinct existence could only be fictitiously109 introduced into the county, where its utility had not been felt. All the townships united have but one representation, which is the state, the centre of the national authority: beyond the action of the township and that of the nation, nothing can be said to exist but the influence of individual exertion25.
ADMINISTRATION IN NEW ENGLAND.
Administration not perceived in America.—Why?—The Europeans believe that Liberty is promoted by depriving the social Authority of some of its Rights; the Americans, by dividing its Exercise.—Almost all the Administration confined to the Township, and divided among the town Officers.—No trace of an administrative Hierarchy110 to be perceived either in the Township, or above it.—The Reason of this.—How it happens that the Administration of the State is uniform.—Who is empowered to enforce the Obedience of the Township and the County to the Law.—The introduction of judicial Power into the Administration.—Consequence of the Extension of the elective Principle to all Functionaries.—The Justice of the Peace in New England.—By whom Appointed.—County Officer.—Ensures the Administration of the Townships.—Court of Sessions.—Its Action.—Right of Inspection111 and Indictment112 disseminated like the other administrative Functions.—Informers encouraged by the division of Fines.
Nothing is more striking to a European traveller in the United States than the absence of what we term government, or the administration. Written laws exist in America, and one sees that they are daily executed; but although everything is in motion, the hand which gives the impulse to the social machine can nowhere be discovered. Nevertheless, as all people are obliged to have recourse to certain grammatical forms, which are the foundation of human language, in order to express their thoughts; so all communities are obliged to secure their existence by submitting to a certain portion of authority, without which they fall a prey113 to anarchy114. This authority may be distributed in several ways, but it must always exist somewhere.
There are two methods of diminishing the force of authority in a nation.
The first is to weaken the supreme power in its very principle, by forbidding or preventing society from acting115 in its own defence under certain circumstances. To weaken authority in this manner is what is generally termed in Europe to lay the foundations of freedom.
The second manner of diminishing the influence of authority does not consist in stripping society of any of its rights, nor in paralysing its efforts, but in distributing the exercise of its privileges among various hands, and in multiplying functionaries, to each of whom the degree of power necessary for him to perform his duty is intrusted. There may be nations whom this distribution of social powers might lead to anarchy; but in itself it is not anarchical. The action of authority is indeed thus rendered less irresistible116, and less perilous118, but it is not totally suppressed.
The revolution of the United States was the result of a mature and deliberate taste for freedom, not of a vague or ill-defined craving119 for independence. It contracted no alliance with the turbulent passions of anarchy; but its course was marked, on the contrary, by an attachment to whatever was lawful120 and orderly.
It was never assumed in the United States that the citizen of a free country has a right to do whatever he pleases: on the contrary, social obligations were there imposed upon him more various than anywhere else; no idea was ever entertained of attacking the principles, or of contesting the rights of society; but the exercise of its authority was divided, to the end that the office might be powerful and the officer insignificant121, and that the community should be at once regulated and free. In no country in the world does the law hold so absolute a language as in America; and in no country is the right of applying it vested in so many hands. The administrative power in the United States presents nothing either central or hierarchical in its constitution, which accounts for its passing unperceived. The power exists, but its representative is not to be discerned.
We have already seen that the independent townships of New England protect their own private interests; and the municipal magistrates are the persons to whom the execution of the laws of the state is most frequently intrusted.{73} Beside the general laws, the state sometimes passes general police regulations; but more commonly the townships and town officers, conjointly with the justices of the peace, regulate the minor122 details of social life, according to the necessities of the different localities, and promulgate123 such enactments125 as concern the health of the community, and the peace as well as morality of the citizens.{74} Lastly, these municipal magistrates provide of their own accord and without any delegated powers, for those unforeseen emergencies which frequently occur in society.{75}
It results, from what we have said, that in the state of Massachusetts the administrative authority is almost entirely126 restricted to the township,{76} but that it is distributed among a great number of individuals. In the French commune there is properly but one official functionary127, namely, the maire; and in New England we have seen that there are nineteen. These nineteen functionaries do not in general depend upon one another. The law carefully prescribes a circle of action to each of these magistrates; and within that circle they have an entire right to perform their functions independently of any other authority. Above the township scarcely any trace of a series of official dignities is to be found. It sometimes happens that the county officers alter a decision of the townships, or town magistrates,{77} but in general the authorities of the county have no right to interfere with the authorities of the township,{78} except in such matters as concern the county.
The magistrates of the township, as well as those of the county, are bound to communicate their acts to the central government in a very small number of predetermined cases.{79} But the central government is not represented by an individual whose business it is to publish police regulations and ordinances128 enforcing the execution of the laws; to keep up a regular communication with the officers of the township and the county; to inspect their conduct, to direct their actions, or reprimand their faults. There is no point which serves as a centre to the radii129 of the administration.
What, then, is the uniform plan on which the government is conducted, and how is the compliance130 of the counties and their magistrates, or the townships and their officers, enforced? In the states of New England the legislative authority embraces more subjects than it does in France; the legislator penetrates131 to the very core of the administration; the law descends133 to the most minute details; the same enactment124 prescribes the principle and the method of its application, and thus imposes a multitude of strict and rigorously defined obligations on the secondary functionaries of the state. The consequence of this is, that if all the secondary functionaries of the administration conform to the law, society in all its branches proceeds with the greatest uniformity; the difficulty remains134 of compelling the secondary functionaries of the administration to conform to the law. It may be affirmed that, in general, society has only two methods of enforcing the execution of the laws at its disposal; a discretionary power may be intrusted to a superior functionary of directing all the others, and of cashiering them in case of disobedience; or the courts of justice may be authorized135 to inflict136 judicial penalties on the offender137: but these two methods are not always available.
The right of directing a civil officer pre-supposes that of cashiering him if he does not obey orders, and of rewarding him by promotion138 if he fulfils his duties with propriety139. But an elected magistrate38 can neither be cashiered nor promoted. All elective functions are inalienable until their term is expired. In fact, the elected magistrate has nothing either to expect or to fear from his constituents140; and when all public offices are filled by ballot141, there can be no series of official dignities, because the double right of commanding and of enforcing obedience can never be vested in the same individual, and because the power of issuing an order can never be joined to that of inflicting142 a punishment or bestowing143 a reward.
The communities therefore in which the secondary functionaries of the government are elected, are perforce obliged to make great use of judicial penalties as a means of administration. This is not evident at first sight; for those in power are apt to look upon the institution of elective functionaries as one concession144, and the subjection of the elective magistrate to the judges of the land as another. They are equally averse145 to both these innovations; and as they are more pressingly solicited146 to grant the former than the latter, they accede147 to the election of the magistrate, and leave him independent of the judicial power. Nevertheless, the second of these measures is the only thing that can possibly counter-balance the first; and it will be found that an elective authority which is not subject to judicial power will, sooner or later, either elude23 all control or be destroyed. The courts of justice are the only possible medium between the central power and the administrative bodies; they alone can compel the elected functionary to obey, without violating the rights of the elector. The extension of judicial power in the political world ought therefore to be in the exact ratio of the extension of elective offices; if these two institutions do not go hand in hand, the state must fall into anarchy or into subjection.
It has always been remarked that habits of legal business do not render men apt to the exercise of administrative authority. The Americans have borrowed from the English, their fathers, the idea of an institution which is unknown upon the continent of Europe: I allude66 to that of justices of the peace.
The justice of the peace is a sort of mezzo termine between the magistrate and the man of the world, between the civil officer and the judge. A justice of the peace is a well-informed citizen, though he is not necessarily versed148 in the knowledge of the laws. His office simply obliges him to execute the police regulations of society; a task in which good sense and integrity are of more avail than legal science. The justice introduces into the administration a certain taste for established forms and publicity149, which renders him a most unserviceable instrument of despotism; and, on the other hand, he is not blinded by those superstitions150 which render legal officers unfit members of a government. The Americans have adopted the system of English justices of the peace, but they have deprived it of that aristocratic character which is discernible in the mother-country. The governor of Massachusetts{80} appoints a certain number of justices of the peace in every county, whose functions last seven years.{81} He farther designates three individuals from among the whole body of justices, who form in each county what is called the court of sessions. The justices take a personal share in public business; they are sometimes intrusted with administrative functions in conjunction with elected officers;{82} they sometimes constitute a tribunal, before which the magistrates summarily prosecute a refractory151 citizen or the citizens inform against the abuses of the magistrate. But it is in the court of sessions that they exercise their most important functions. This court meets twice a year in the county town; in Massachusetts it is empowered to enforce the obedience of the greater number{83} of public officers.{84} It must be observed that in the state of Massachusetts the court of sessions is at the same time an administrative body, properly so called, and a political tribunal. It has been asserted that the county is a purely152 administrative division. The court of sessions presides over that small number of affairs which, as they concern several townships, or all the townships of the county in common, cannot be intrusted to any of them in particular.{85}
In all that concerns county business, the duties of the court of sessions are therefore purely administrative; and if in its investigations154 it occasionally borrows the forms of judicial procedure, it is only with a view to its own information,{86} or as a guarantee to the community over which it presides. But when the administration of the township is brought before it, it almost always acts as a judicial body, and in some few cases as an administrative assembly.
The first difficulty is to procure155 the obedience of an authority so entirely independent of the general laws of the state as the township is. We have stated that assessors are annually156 named by the town meetings, to levy157 the taxes. If a township attempts to evade158 the payment of the taxes by neglecting to name its assessors, the court of sessions condemns159 it to a heavy penalty.{87} The fine is levied160 on each of the inhabitants; and the sheriff of the county, who is an officer of justice, executes the mandate. Thus it is that in the United States the authority of the government is mysteriously concealed161 under the forms of a judicial sentence; and the influence is at the same time fortified162 by that irresistible power with which men have invested the formalities of law.
These proceedings164 are easy to follow, and to understand. The demands made upon a township are in general plain and accurately165 defined; they consist in a simple fact without any complication, or in a principle without its application in detail.{88} But the difficulty increases when it is not the obedience of the township, but that of the town officers, which is to be enforced. All the reprehensible166 actions of which a public functionary may be guilty are reducible to the following heads:
He may neglect to execute the law;
The last two violations169 of duty can alone come under the cognizance of a tribunal; a positive and appreciable170 fact is the indispensable foundation of an action at law. Thus, if the selectmen omit to fulfil the legal formalities usual to town elections, they may be condemned171 to pay a fine;{89} but when the public officer performs his duty without ability, and when he obeys the letter of the law without zeal or energy, he is at least beyond the reach of judicial interference. The court of sessions, even when it is invested with its administrative powers, is in this case unable to compel him to a more satisfactory obedience. The fear of removal is the only check to these quasi offences; and as the court of sessions does not originate the town authorities, it cannot remove functionaries whom it does not appoint. Moreover, a perpetual investigation153 would be necessary to convict the subordinate officer of negligence172 or lukewarmness; and the court of sessions sits but twice a year, and then only judges such offences as are brought before its notice. The only security for that active and enlightened obedience, which a court of justice cannot impose upon public officers, lies in the possibility of their arbitrary removal. In France this security is sought for in powers exercised by the heads of the administration; in America it is sought for in the principle of election.
Thus, to recapitulate173 in a few words what I have been showing:—
If a public officer in New England commits a crime in the exercise of his functions, the ordinary courts of justice are always called upon to pass sentence upon him.
If he commits a fault in his official capacity, a purely administrative tribunal is empowered to punish him; and, if the affair is important or urgent, the judge supplies the omission174 of the functionary.{90}
Lastly, if the same individual is guilty of one of those intangible offences, of which human justice has no cognizance, he annually appears before a tribunal from which there is no appeal, which can at once reduce him to insignificance175, and deprive him of his charge. This system undoubtedly possesses great advantages, but its execution is attended with a practical difficulty which it is important to point out.
I have already observed, that the administrative tribunal, which is called the court of sessions, has no right of inspection over the town officers. It can only interfere when the conduct of a magistrate is specially176 brought under its notice; and this is the delicate part of the system. The Americans of New England are unacquainted with the office of public prosecutor177 in the court of sessions,{91} and it may readily be perceived that it could not have been established without difficulty. If an accusing magistrate had merely been appointed in the chief town of each county, and if he had been unassisted by agents in the townships, he would not have been better acquainted with what was going on in the county than the members of the court of sessions. But to appoint agents in each township, would have been to centre in his person the most formidable of powers, that of a judicial administration. Moreover, laws are the children of habit, and nothing of the kind exists in the legislation of England. The Americans have therefore divided the officers of inspection and of prosecution178 as well as all the other functions of the administration. Grand-jurors are bound by the law to apprize the court to which they belong of all the misdemeanors which may have been committed in their county.{92} There are certain great offences which are officially prosecuted179 by the state;{93} but more frequently the task of punishing delinquents180 devolves upon the fiscal182 officer, whose province it is to receive the fine; thus the treasurer of the township is charged with the prosecution of such administrative offences as fall under his notice. But a more especial appeal is made by American legislation to the private interest of the citizen,{94} and this great principle is constantly to be met with in studying the laws of the United States. American legislators are more apt to give men credit for intelligence than for honesty; and they rely not a little on personal cupidity183 for the execution of the laws. When an individual is really and sensibly injured by an administrative abuse, it is natural that his personal interest should induce him to prosecute. But if a legal formality be required which, however advantageous184 to the community, is of small importance to individuals, plaintiffs may be less easily found; and thus, by a tacit agreement, the laws might fall into disuse. Reduced by their system to this extremity185, the Americans are obliged to encourage informers by bestowing on them a portion of the penalty in certain cases;{95} and to ensure the execution of the laws by the dangerous expedient of degrading the morals of the people.
The only administrative authority above the county magistrates is, properly speaking, that of the government.
GENERAL REMARKS ON THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE UNITED STATES.
Difference of the States of the union in their Systems of Administration.—Activity and Perfection of the local Authorities decreases towards the South.—Power of the Magistrates increases; that of the Elector diminishes.—Administration passes from the Township to the County.—States of New York, Ohio, Pennsylvania.—Principles of Administration applicable to the whole union.—Election of public Officers, and Inalienability of their Functions.—Absence of Gradation of Ranks.—Introduction of judicial Resources into the Administration.
I have already promised that after having examined the constitution of the township and the county of New England in detail, I should take a general view of the remainder of the union. Townships and a local activity exist in every state; but in no part of the confederation is a township to be met with precisely186 similar to those in New England. The more we descend132 toward the south, the less active does the business of the township or parish become; the number of magistrates, of functions, and of rights, decreases; the population exercises a less immediate influence on affairs; town-meetings are less frequent, and the subjects of debates less numerous. The power of the elected magistrate is augmented187, and that of the elector diminished, while the public spirit of the local communities is less awakened188 and less influential189.{96}
These differences may be perceived to a certain extent in the state of New York; they are very sensible in Pennsylvania; but they become less striking as we advance to the northwest. The majority of the emigrants190 who settle in the northwestern states are natives of New England, and they carry the habits of their mother-country with them into that which they adopt. A township in Ohio is by no means dissimilar from a township in Massachusetts.
We have seen that in Massachusetts the principal part of the public administration lies in the township. It forms the common centre of the interests and affections of the citizens. But this ceases to be the case as we descend to states in which knowledge is less generally diffused191, and where the township consequently offers fewer guarantees of a wise and active administration. As we leave New England, therefore, we find that the importance of the town is gradually transferred to the county, which becomes the centre of administration, and the intermediate power between the government and the citizen. In Massachusetts the business of the town is conducted by the court of sessions, which is composed of a quorum192 named by the governor and his council; but the county has no representative assembly, and its expenditure193 is voted by the national{97} legislature. In the great state of New York, on the contrary, and in those of Ohio and Pennsylvania, the inhabitants of each county choose a certain number of representatives, who constitute the assembly of the county.{98} The county assembly has the right of taxing the inhabitants to a certain extent; and in this respect it enjoys the privileges of a real legislative body: at the same time it exercises an executive power in the county, frequently directs the administration of the townships, and restricts their authority within much narrower bounds than in Massachusetts.
Such are the principal differences which the systems of county and town administration present in the federal states. Were it my intention to examine the provisions of American law minutely, I should have to point out still farther differences in the executive details of the several communities. But what I have already said may suffice to show the general principles on which the administration of the United States rests. These principles are differently applied; their consequences are more or less numerous in various localities; but they are always substantially the same. The laws differ, and their outward features change, but their character does not vary. If the township and the county are not everywhere constituted in the same manner, it is at least true that in the United States the county and the township are always based upon the same principle, namely, that every one is the best judge of what concerns himself alone, and the person most able to supply his private wants. The township and the county are therefore bound to take care of their special interests: the state governs, but it does not interfere with their administration. Exceptions to this rule may be met with, but not a contrary principle.
The first consequence of this doctrine has been to cause all the magistrates to be chosen either by, or at least from among the citizens. As the officers are everywhere elected or appointed for a certain period, it has been impossible to establish the rules of a dependent series of authorities; there are almost as many independent functionaries as there are functions, and the executive power is disseminated in a multitude of hands. Hence arose the indispensable necessity of introducing the control of the courts of justice over the administration, and the system of pecuniary194 penalties, by which the secondary bodies and their representatives are constrained to obey the laws. The system obtains from one end of the union to the other. The power of punishing the misconduct of public officers, or of performing the part of the executive, in urgent cases, has not, however, been bestowed195 on the same judges in all the states. The Anglo-Americans derived197 the institution of justices of the peace from a common source; but although it exists in all the states, it is not always turned to the same use. The justices of the peace everywhere participate in the administration of the townships and the counties,{99} either as public officers or as the judges of public misdemeanors, but in most of the states the more important classes of public offences come under the cognisance of the ordinary tribunals.
The election of public officers, or the inalienability of their functions, the absence of a gradation of powers, and the introduction of a judicial control over the secondary branches of the administration, are the universal characteristics of the American system from Maine to the Floridas. In some states (and that of New York has advanced most in this direction) traces of a centralised administration begin to be discernible. In the state of New York the officers of the central government exercise, in certain cases, a sort of inspection of control over the secondary bodies.{100} At other times they constitute a court of appeal for the decision of affairs.{101} In the state of New York judicial penalties are less used than in other parts as a means of administration; and the right of prosecuting198 the offences of public officers is vested in fewer hands.{102} The same tendency is faintly observable in some other states;{103} but in general the prominent feature of the administration in the United States is its excessive local independence.
OF THE STATE.
I have described the townships and the administration: it now remains for me to speak of the state and government. This is ground I may pass over rapidly, without fear of being misunderstood; for all I have to say is to be found in written forms of the various constitutions, which are easily to be procured199.{104} These constitutions rest upon a simple and rational theory; their forms have been adopted by all constitutional nations, and are become familiar to us.
In this place, therefore, it is only necessary for me to give a short analysis; I shall endeavor afterward200 to pass judgment201 upon what I now describe.
LEGISLATIVE POWER OF THE STATE.
Division of the Legislative Body into two Houses.—Senate.—House of Representatives.—Different functions of these two Bodies.
The legislative power of the state is vested in two assemblies, the first of which generally bears the name of the senate.
The senate is commonly a legislative body; but it sometimes becomes an executive and judicial one. It takes a part in the government in several ways, according to the constitution of the different states;{105} but it is in the nomination202 of public functionaries that it most commonly assumes an executive power. It partakes of judicial power in the trial of certain political offences, and sometimes also in the decision of certain civil cases.{106} The number of its members is always small. The other branch of the legislature, which is usually called the house of representatives, has no share whatever in the administration, and only takes a part in the judicial power inasmuch as it impeaches203 public functionaries before the senate.
The members of the two houses are nearly everywhere subject to the same conditions of election. They are chosen in the same manner, and by the same citizens.
The only difference which exists between them is, that the term for which the senate is chosen, is in general longer than that of the house of representatives. The latter seldom remain in office longer than a year; the former usually sit two or three years.
By granting to the senators the privilege of being chosen for several years, and being renewed seriatim, the law takes care to preserve in the legislative body a nucleus204 of men already accustomed to public business, and capable of exercising a salutary influence upon the junior members.
The Americans, plainly, did not desire, by this separation of the legislative body into two branches, to make one house hereditary205 and the other elective; one aristocratic and the other democratic. It was not their object to create in the one a bulwark206 to power, while the other represented the interests and passions of the people. The only advantages which result from the present constitution of the United States, are, the division of the legislative power, and the consequent check upon political assemblies; with the creation of a tribunal of appeal for the revision of the laws.
Time and experience, however, have convinced the Americans that if these are its only advantages, the division of the legislative power is still a principle of the greatest necessity. Pennsylvania was the only one of the United States which at first attempted to establish a single house of assembly; and Franklin himself was so far carried away by the necessary consequences of the principle of the sovereignty of the people, as to have concurred207 in the measure; but the Pennsylvanians were soon obliged to change the law, and to create two houses. Thus the principle of the division of the legislative power was finally established, and its necessity may henceforward be regarded as a demonstrated truth.
This theory, which was nearly unknown to the republics of antiquity—which was introduced into the world almost by accident, like so many other great truths—and misunderstood by several modern nations, is at length become an axiom in the political science of the present age.
THE EXECUTIVE POWER OF THE STATE.
Office of Governor in an American State.—The Place he occupies in relation to the Legislature.—His Rights and his Duties.—His Dependence10 on the People.
The executive power of the state may with truth be said to be represented by the governor, although he enjoys but a portion of its rights. The supreme magistrate, under the title of governor, is the official moderator and counsellor of the legislature. He is armed with a suspensive veto, which allows him to stop, or at least to retard208, its movements at pleasure. He lays the wants of the country before the legislative body, and points out the means which he thinks may be usefully employed in providing for them; he is the natural executor of its decrees in all the undertakings209 which interest the nation at large.{107} In the absence of the legislature, the governor is bound to take all necessary steps to guard the state against violent shocks and unforeseen dangers.
The whole military power of the state is at the disposal of the governor. He is commander of the militia211 and head of the armed force. When the authority, which is by general consent awarded to the laws, is disregarded, the governor puts himself at the head of the armed force of the state, to quell212 resistance and to restore order.
Lastly, the governor takes no share in the administration of townships and counties, except it be indirectly in the nomination of justices of the peace, which nomination he has not the power to revoke213.{108}
The governor is an elected magistrate, and is generally chosen for one or two years only; so that he always continues to be strictly214 dependent on the majority who returned him.
POLITICAL EFFECTS OF THE SYSTEM OF LOCAL ADMINISTRATION IN THE UNITED STATES.
Necessary Distinction between the general Centralisation of Government and the Centralisation of the local Administration.—Local Administration not centralized in the United States; great general Centralisation of the Government.—Some bad Consequences resulting to the United States from the local Administration.—Administrative Advantages attending the Order of things.—The Power which conducts the Government is less regular, less enlightened, less learned, but much greater than in Europe.—Political Advantages of this Order of things.—In the United States the Interests of the Country are everywhere kept in View.—Support given to the Government by the Community.—Provincial215 Institutions more necessary in Proportion as the social Condition becomes more democratic.—Reason of this.
Centralisation is become a word of general and daily use, without any precise meaning being attached to it. Nevertheless, there exist two distinct kinds of centralisation, which it is necessary to discriminate216 with accuracy.
Certain interests are common to all parts of a nation, such as the enactment of its general laws, and the maintenance of its foreign relations. Other interests are peculiar to certain parts of the nation; such, for instance, as the business of different townships. When the power which directs the general interests is centred in one place, or in the same persons, it constitutes a central government. The power of directing partial or local interests, when brought together, in like manner constitutes what may be termed a central administration.
Upon some points these two kinds of centralisation coalesce217; but by classifying the objects which fall more particularly within the province of each of them, they may easily be distinguished.
It is evident that a central government acquires immense power when united to administrative centralisation. Thus combined, it accustoms men to set their own will habitually and completely aside; to submit, not only for once or upon one point, but in every respect, and at all times. Not only, therefore, does the union of power subdue218 them by force, but it affects them in the ordinary habits of life, and influences each individual, first separately, and then collectively.
These two kinds of centralisation mutually assist and attract each other: but they must not be supposed to be inseparable. It is impossible to imagine a more completely central government than that which existed in France under Louis XIV.; when the same individual was the author and the interpreter of the laws, and being the representative of France at home and abroad, he was justified219 in asserting that the state was identified with his person. Nevertheless, the administration was much less centralized under Louis XIV., than it is at the present day.
In England the centralisation of the government is carried to great perfection; the state has the compact vigor220 of a man, and by the sole act of its will it puts immense engines in motion, and wields221 or collects the efforts of its authority. Indeed, I cannot conceive that a nation can enjoy a secure or prosperous existence without a powerful centralisation of government. But I am of opinion that a central administration enervates222 the nations in which it exists by incessantly223 diminishing their public spirit. If such an administration succeeds in condensing at a given moment on a given point all the disposable resources of a people, it impairs224 at least the renewal225 of those resources. It may ensure a victory in the hour of strife226, but it gradually relaxes the sinews of strength. It may contribute admirably to the transient greatness of a man, but it cannot ensure the durable prosperity of a people.
If we pay proper attention, we shall find that whenever it is said that a state cannot act because it has no central point, it is the centralisation of the government in which it is deficient227. It is frequently asserted, and we are prepared to assent to the proposition, that the German empire was never able to bring all its powers into action. But the reason was, that the state has never been able to enforce obedience to its general laws, because the several members of that great body always claimed the right, or found the means, of refusing their co-operation to the representatives of the common authority, even in the affairs which concerned the mass of the people; in other words, because there was no centralisation of government. The same remark is applicable to the middle ages; the cause of all the confusion of feudal228 society was that the control, not only of local but of general interests, was divided among a thousand hands, and broken up in a thousand different ways; the absence of a central government prevented the nations of Europe from advancing with energy in any straightforward229 course.
We have shown that in the United States no central administration, and no dependent series of public functionaries, exist. Local authority has been carried to lengths which no European nation could endure without great inconvenience, and which have even produced some disadvantageous consequences in America. But in the United States the centralisation of the government is complete; and it would be easy to prove that the national power is more compact than it has ever been in the old monarchies of Europe. Not only is there but one legislative body in each state; not only does there exist but one source of political authority; but numerous district assemblies and county courts have in general been avoided, lest they should be tempted to exceed their administrative duties and interfere with the government. In America the legislature of each state is supreme; nothing can impede230 its authority; neither privileges, nor local immunities, nor personal influence, nor even the empire of reason, since it represents that majority which claims to be the sole organ of reason. Its own determination is, therefore, the only limit to its action. In juxtaposition231 to it, and under its immediate control, is the representative of the executive power, whose duty it is to constrain57 the refractory to submit by superior force. The only symptom of weakness lies in certain details of the action of the government. The American republics have no standing232 armies to intimidate233 a discontented minority; but as no minority has as yet been reduced to declare open war, the necessity of an army has not been felt. The state usually employs the officers of the township or the county, to deal with the citizens. Thus, for instance, in New England the assessor fixes the rate of taxes; the collector receives them; the town treasurer transmits the amount to the public treasury234; and the disputes which may arise are brought before the ordinary courts of justice. This method of collecting taxes is slow as well as inconvenient235, and it would prove a perpetual hindrance3 to a government whose pecuniary demands were large. In general it is desirable that in what ever materially affects its existence, the government should be served by officers of its own, appointed by itself, removable at pleasure, and accustomed to rapid methods of proceeding163. But it will always be easy for the central government, organized as it is in America, to introduce new and more efficacious modes of action proportioned to its wants.
The absence of a central government will not, then, as has often been asserted, prove the destruction of the republics of the New World; far from supposing that the American governments are not sufficiently236 centralized, I shall prove hereafter that they are too much so. The legislative bodies daily encroach upon the authority of the government, and their tendency, like that of the French convention, is to appropriate it entirely to themselves. Under these circumstances the social power is constantly changing hands, because it is subordinate to the power of the people, which is too apt to forget the maxims237 of wisdom and of foresight238 in the consciousness of its strength: hence arises its danger; and thus its vigor, and not its impotence, will probably be the cause of its ultimate destruction.
The system of local administration produces several different effects in America. The Americans seem to me to have outstepped the limits of sound policy, in isolating239 the administration of the government; for order, even in second-rate affairs, is a matter of national importance.{109} As the state has no administrative functionaries of its own, stationed on different parts of its territory, to whom it can give a common impulse, the consequence is that it rarely attempts to issue any general police regulations. The want of these regulations is severely240 felt, and is frequently observed by Europeans. The appearance of disorder241 which prevails on the surface, leads them at first to imagine that society is in a state of anarchy; nor do they perceive their mistake till they have gone deeper into the subject. Certain undertakings are of importance to the whole state; but they cannot be put in execution, because there is no national administration to direct them. Abandoned to the exertions of the towns or counties, under the care of elected or temporary agents, they lead to no result, or at least to no durable benefit.
The partisans242 of centralisation in Europe maintain that the government directs the affairs of each locality better than the citizens could do it for themselves: this may be true when the central power is enlightened, and when the local districts are ignorant; when it is as alert as they are slow; when it is accustomed to act, and they to obey. Indeed, it is evident that this double tendency must augment with the increase of centralisation, and that the readiness of the one, and the incapacity of the others, must become more and more prominent. But I deny that such is the case when the people is as enlightened, as awake to its interests, and as accustomed to reflect on them, as the Americans are. I am persuaded, on the contrary, that in this case the collective strength of the citizens will always conduce more efficaciously to the public welfare than the authority of the government. It is difficult to point out with certainty the means of arousing a sleeping population, and of giving it passions and knowledge which it does not possess; it is, I am well aware, an arduous243 task to persuade men to busy themselves about their own affairs; and it would frequently be easier to interest them in the punctilios of court etiquette244 than in the repairs of their common dwelling245. But whenever a central administration affects to supersede246 the persons most interested, I am inclined to suppose that it is either misled, or desirous to mislead. However enlightened and however skilful247 a central power may be, it cannot of itself embrace all the details of the existence of a great nation. Such vigilance exceeds the powers of man. And when it attempts to create and set in motion so many complicated springs, it must submit to a very imperfect result, or consume itself in bootless efforts.
Centralisation succeeds more easily, indeed, in subjecting the external actions of men to a certain uniformity, which at last commands our regard, independently of the objects to which it is applied, like those devotees who worship the statue and forget the deity248 it represents. Centralisation imparts without difficulty an admirable regularity249 to the routine of business; rules the details of the social police with sagacity; represses the smallest disorder and the most petty misdemeanors; maintains society in a status quo, alike secure from improvement and decline; and perpetuates250 a drowsy251 precision in the conduct of affairs, which is hailed by the heads of the administration as a sign of perfect order and public tranquillity;{110} in short, it excels more in prevention than in action. Its force deserts it when society is to be disturbed or accelerated in its course; and if once the co-operation of private citizens is necessary to the furtherance of its measures, the secret of its impotence is disclosed. Even while it invokes252 their assistance, it is on the condition that they shall act exactly as much as the government chooses, and exactly in the manner it appoints. They are to take charge of the details, without aspiring253 to guide the system; they are to work in a dark and subordinate sphere, and only to judge the acts in which they have themselves co-operated, by their results. These, however, are not conditions on which the alliance of the human will is to be obtained; its carriage must be free, and its actions responsible, or (such is the constitution of man) the citizen had rather remain a passive spectator than a dependent actor in schemes with which he is unacquainted.
It is undeniable, that the want of those uniform regulations which control the conduct of every inhabitant of France is not unfrequently felt in the United States. Gross instances of social indifference254 and neglect are to be met with; and from time to time disgraceful blemishes255 are seen, in complete contrast with the surrounding civilisation256. Useful undertakings, which cannot succeed without perpetual attention and rigorous exactitude, are very frequently abandoned in the end; for in America, as well as in other countries, the people is subject to sudden impulses and momentary257 exertions. The European who is accustomed to find a functionary always at hand to interfere with all he undertakes, has some difficulty in accustoming258 himself to the complex mechanism of the administration of the townships. In general it may be affirmed that the lesser details of the police, which render life easy and comfortable, are neglected in America; but that the essential guarantees of man in society are as strong there as elsewhere. In America the power which conducts the government is far less regular, less enlightened, and less learned, but a hundredfold more authoritative259, than in Europe. In no country in the world do the citizens make such exertions for the common weal; and I am acquainted with no people which has established schools as numerous and as efficacious, places of public worship better suited to the wants of the inhabitants, or roads kept in better repair. Uniformity or permanence of design, the minute arrangement of details,{111} and the perfection of an ingenious administration, must not be sought for in the United States; but it will be easy to find, on the other hand, the symptoms of a power, which, if it is somewhat barbarous, is at least robust260; and of an existence, which is checkered261 with accidents indeed, but cheered at the same time by animation262 and effort.
Granting for an instant that the villages and counties of the United States would be more usefully governed by a remote authority, which they had never seen, than by functionaries taken from the midst of them—admitting, for the sake of argument, that the country would be more secure, and the resources of society better employed, if the whole administration centred in a single arm, still the political advantages which the Americans derive196 from their system would induce me to prefer it to the contrary plan. It profits me but little, after all, that a vigilant263 authority protects the tranquillity of my pleasures, and constantly averts265 all danger from my path, without my care or my concern, if the same authority is the absolute mistress of my liberty and of my life, and if it so monopolises all the energy of existence, that when it languishes266 everything languishes around it, that when it sleeps everything must sleep, that when it dies the state itself must perish.
In certain countries of Europe the natives consider themselves as a kind of settlers, indifferent to the fate of the spot upon which they live. The greatest changes are effected without their concurrence267 and (unless chance may have apprised268 them of the event) without their knowledge; nay269 more, the citizen is unconcerned as to the condition of his village, the police of his street, the repairs of the church or the parsonage; for he looks upon all these things as unconnected with himself, and as the property of a powerful stranger whom he calls the government. He has only a life-interest in these possessions, and he entertains no notions of ownership or of improvement. This want of interest in his own affairs goes so far, that if his own safety or that of his children is endangered, instead of trying to avert264 the peril117, he will fold his arms, and wait till the nation comes to his assistance. This same individual, who has so completely sacrificed his own free will, has no natural propensity270 to obedience; he cowers271, it is true, before the pettiest officer; but he braves the law with the spirit of a conquered foe272 as soon as its superior force is removed: his oscillations between servitude and license273 are perpetual. When a nation has arrived at this state, it must either change its customs and its laws, or perish: the source of public virtue274 is dry; and though it may contain subjects, the race of citizens is extinct. Such communities are a natural prey to foreign conquest; and if they do not disappear from the scene of life, it is because they are surrounded by other nations similar or inferior to themselves; it is because the instinctive275 feeling of their country's claims still exists in their hearts; and because an involuntary pride in the name it bears, or the vague reminiscence of its by-gone fame, suffices to give them the impulse of self-preservation.
Nor can the prodigious exertions made by certain people in the defence of a country, in which they may almost be said to have lived as aliens, be adduced in favor of such a system; for it will be found that in these cases their main incitement276 was religion. The permanence, the glory, and the prosperity of the nation, were become parts of their faith; and in defending the country they inhabited, they defended that holy city of which they were all citizens. The Turkish tribes have never taken an active share in the conduct of the affairs of society, but they accomplished277 stupendous enterprises as long as the victories of the sultans were the triumphs of the Mohammedan faith. In the present age they are in rapid decay, because their religion is departing, and despotism only remains. Montesquieu, who attributed to absolute power an authority peculiar to itself, did it, as I conceive, undeserved honor; for despotism, taken by itself, can produce no durable results. On close inspection we shall find that religion, and not fear, has ever been the cause of the long-lived prosperity of absolute governments. Whatever exertions may be made, no true power can be founded among men which does not depend upon the free union of their inclinations278; and patriotism and religion are the only two motives279 in the world which can permanently280 direct the whole of a body politic to one end.
Laws cannot succeed in rekindling281 the ardor282 of an extinguished faith; but men may be interested in the fate of their country by the laws. By this influence, the vague impulse of patriotism, which never abandons the human heart, may be directed and revived: and if it be connected with the thoughts, the passions and daily habits of life, it may be consolidated283 into a durable and rational sentiment. Let it not be said that the time for the experiment is already past; for the old age of nations is not like the old age of men, and every fresh generation is a new people ready for the care of the legislator.
It is not the administrative, but the political effects of the local system that I most admire in America. In the United States the interests of the country are everywhere kept in view; they are an object of solicitude284 to the people of the whole union, and every citizen is as warmly attached to them as if they were his own. He takes pride in the glory of his nation; he boasts of his success, to which he conceives himself to have contributed; and he rejoices in the general prosperity by which he profits. The feeling he entertains toward the state is analogous285 to that which unites him to his family, and it is by a kind of egotism that he interests himself in the welfare of his country.
The European generally submits to a public officer because he represents a superior force; but to an American he represents a right. In America it may be said that no one renders obedience to man, but to justice and to law. If the opinion which the citizen entertains of himself is exaggerated, it is at least salutary; he unhesitatingly confides in his own powers, which appear to him to be all-sufficient. When a private individual meditates286 an undertaking210, however directly connected it may be with the welfare of society, he never thinks of soliciting287 the co-operation of the government: but he publishes his plan, offers to execute it himself, courts the assistance of other individuals, and struggles manfully against all obstacles. Undoubtedly he is less successful than the state might have been in his position; but in the end, the sum of these private undertakings far exceeds all that the government could effect.
As the administrative authority is within the reach of the citizens, whom it in some degree represents, it excites neither their jealousy288 nor their hatred289: as its resources are limited, every one feels that he must not rely solely290 on its assistance. Thus when the administration thinks fit to interfere, it is not abandoned to itself as in Europe; the duties of the private citizens are not supposed to have lapsed291 because the state assists in their fulfilment; but every one is ready, on the contrary, to guide and to support it. This action of individual exertions, joined to that of the public authorities, frequently performs what the most energetic central administration would be unable to execute. It would be easy to adduce several facts in proof of what I advance, but I had rather give only one, with which I am more thoroughly acquainted.{112} In America, the means which the authorities have at their disposal for the discovery of crimes and the arrest of criminals are few. A state police does not exist, and passports are unknown. The criminal police of the United States cannot be compared with that of France; the magistrates and public prosecutors292 are not numerous, and the examinations of prisoners are rapid and oral. Nevertheless in no country does crime more rarely elude punishment. The reason is that every one conceives himself to be interested in furnishing evidence of the act committed, and in stopping the delinquent181. During my stay in the United States, I saw the spontaneous formation of committees for the pursuit and prosecution of a man who had committed a great crime in a certain county. In Europe a criminal is an unhappy being, who is struggling for his life against the ministers of justice, while the population is merely a spectator of the conflict: in America he is looked upon as an enemy of the human race, and the whole of mankind is against him.
I believe that provincial institutions are useful to all nations, but nowhere do they appear to me to be more indispensable than among a democratic people. In an aristocracy, order can always be maintained in the midst of liberty; and as the rulers have a great deal to lose, order is to them a first-rate consideration. In like manner an aristocracy protects the people from the excesses of despotism, because it always possesses an organized power ready to resist a despot. But a democracy without provincial institutions has no security against these evils. How can a populace, unaccustomed to freedom in small concerns, learn to use it temperately293 in great affairs? What resistance can be offered to tyranny in a country where every private individual is impotent, and where the citizens are united by no common tie? Those who dread294 the license of the mob, and those who fear the rule of absolute power, ought alike to desire the progressive growth of provincial liberties.
On the other hand, I am convinced that democratic nations are most exposed to fall beneath the yoke295 of a central administration, for several reasons, among which is the following:—
The constant tendency of these nations is to concentrate all the strength of the government in the hands of the only power which directly represents the people: because, beyond the people nothing is to be perceived but a mass of equal individuals confounded together. But when the same power is already in possession of all the attributes of the government, it can scarcely refrain from penetrating296 into the details of the administration; and an opportunity of doing so is sure to present itself in the end, as was the case in France. In the French revolution there were two impulses in opposite directions, which must never be confounded; the one was favorable to liberty, the other to despotism. Under the ancient monarchy297 the king was the sole author of the laws; and below the power of the sovereign, certain vestiges298 of provincial institutions half-destroyed, were still distinguishable. These provincial institutions were incoherent, ill-compacted, and frequently absurd; in the hands of the aristocracy they had sometimes been converted into instruments of oppression. The revolution declared itself the enemy of royalty299 and of provincial institutions at the same time; it confounded all that had preceded it—despotic power and the checks to its abuses—in an indiscriminate hatred; and its tendency was at once to republicanism and to centralisation. This double character of the French revolution is a fact which has been adroitly300 handled by the friends of absolute power. Can they be accused of laboring301 in the cause of despotism, when they are defending of the revolution?{113} In this manner popularity may be conciliated with hostility302 to the rights of the people, and the secret slave of tyranny may be the professed303 admirer of freedom.
I have visited the two nations in which the system of provincial liberty has been most perfectly established, and I have listened to the opinions of different parties in those countries. In America I met with men who secretly aspired304 to destroy the democratic institutions of the union; in England, I found others who attacked aristocracy openly; but I know of no one who does not regard provincial independence as a great benefit. In both countries I have heard a thousand different causes assigned for the evils of the state; but the local system was never mentioned among them. I have heard citizens attribute the power and prosperity of their country to a multitude of reasons: but they all placed the advantages of local institutions in the foremost rank.
Am I to suppose that when men who are naturally so divided on religious opinions, and on political theories, agree on one point (and that, one of which they have daily experience), they are all in error? The only nations which deny the utility of provincial liberties are those which have fewest of them; in other words, those who are unacquainted with the institution are the only persons who pass a censure305 upon it.
点击收听单词发音
1 reign | |
n.统治时期,统治,支配,盛行;v.占优势 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 hindrances | |
阻碍者( hindrance的名词复数 ); 障碍物; 受到妨碍的状态 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 hindrance | |
n.妨碍,障碍 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 circumscribed | |
adj.[医]局限的:受限制或限于有限空间的v.在…周围划线( circumscribe的过去式和过去分词 );划定…范围;限制;限定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 agglomeration | |
n.结聚,一堆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 modification | |
n.修改,改进,缓和,减轻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 politic | |
adj.有智虑的;精明的;v.从政 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 undoubtedly | |
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 administrative | |
adj.行政的,管理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 dependence | |
n.依靠,依赖;信任,信赖;隶属 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 monarchies | |
n. 君主政体, 君主国, 君主政治 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 coeval | |
adj.同时代的;n.同时代的人或事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 habitually | |
ad.习惯地,通常地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 consolidation | |
n.合并,巩固 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 augment | |
vt.(使)增大,增加,增长,扩张 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 spurns | |
v.一脚踢开,拒绝接受( spurn的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 immunities | |
免除,豁免( immunity的名词复数 ); 免疫力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 amalgamated | |
v.(使)(金属)汞齐化( amalgamate的过去式和过去分词 );(使)合并;联合;结合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 eludes | |
v.(尤指机敏地)避开( elude的第三人称单数 );逃避;躲避;使达不到 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 elude | |
v.躲避,困惑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 exertions | |
n.努力( exertion的名词复数 );费力;(能力、权力等的)运用;行使 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 exertion | |
n.尽力,努力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 engendered | |
v.产生(某形势或状况),造成,引起( engender的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 consolidate | |
v.使加固,使加强;(把...)联为一体,合并 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 repelled | |
v.击退( repel的过去式和过去分词 );使厌恶;排斥;推开 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 inevitably | |
adv.不可避免地;必然发生地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 expedient | |
adj.有用的,有利的;n.紧急的办法,权宜之计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 mechanism | |
n.机械装置;机构,结构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 prodigious | |
adj.惊人的,奇妙的;异常的;巨大的;庞大的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 obligatory | |
adj.强制性的,义务的,必须的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 obedience | |
n.服从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 legislative | |
n.立法机构,立法权;adj.立法的,有立法权的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 magistrate | |
n.地方行政官,地方法官,治安官 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 magistrates | |
地方法官,治安官( magistrate的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 thoroughly | |
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 authorization | |
n.授权,委任状 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 mandate | |
n.托管地;命令,指示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 convoke | |
v.召集会议 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 confides | |
v.吐露(秘密,心事等)( confide的第三人称单数 );(向某人)吐露(隐私、秘密等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 assent | |
v.批准,认可;n.批准,认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 constable | |
n.(英国)警察,警官 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 treasurer | |
n.司库,财务主管 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 lesser | |
adj.次要的,较小的;adv.较小地,较少地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 functionaries | |
n.公职人员,官员( functionary的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 subdivided | |
再分,细分( subdivide的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 commissioners | |
n.专员( commissioner的名词复数 );长官;委员;政府部门的长官 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 audit | |
v.审计;查帐;核对;旁听 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 inspectors | |
n.检查员( inspector的名词复数 );(英国公共汽车或火车上的)查票员;(警察)巡官;检阅官 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 constrained | |
adj.束缚的,节制的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 constrain | |
vt.限制,约束;克制,抑制 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 doctrines | |
n.教条( doctrine的名词复数 );教义;学说;(政府政策的)正式声明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 virtuous | |
adj.有品德的,善良的,贞洁的,有效力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 mutual | |
adj.相互的,彼此的;共同的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 maxim | |
n.格言,箴言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 judicial | |
adj.司法的,法庭的,审判的,明断的,公正的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 alluded | |
提及,暗指( allude的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 allude | |
v.提及,暗指 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 supremacy | |
n.至上;至高权力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 contented | |
adj.满意的,安心的,知足的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 interfere | |
v.(in)干涉,干预;(with)妨碍,打扰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 prosecute | |
vt.告发;进行;vi.告发,起诉,作检察官 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 indicted | |
控告,起诉( indict的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 withhold | |
v.拒绝,不给;使停止,阻挡 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 ordains | |
v.任命(某人)为牧师( ordain的第三人称单数 );授予(某人)圣职;(上帝、法律等)命令;判定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 attentive | |
adj.注意的,专心的;关心(别人)的,殷勤的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 patriotism | |
n.爱国精神,爱国心,爱国主义 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 durable | |
adj.持久的,耐久的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 tranquil | |
adj. 安静的, 宁静的, 稳定的, 不变的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 tranquillity | |
n. 平静, 安静 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 turmoil | |
n.骚乱,混乱,动乱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 presidency | |
n.总统(校长,总经理)的职位(任期) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 esteem | |
n.尊敬,尊重;vt.尊重,敬重;把…看作 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 embroil | |
vt.拖累;牵连;使复杂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 vent | |
n.通风口,排放口;开衩;vt.表达,发泄 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 hearth | |
n.壁炉炉床,壁炉地面 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 disseminated | |
散布,传播( disseminate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 scruple | |
n./v.顾忌,迟疑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 animates | |
v.使有生气( animate的第三人称单数 );驱动;使栩栩如生地动作;赋予…以生命 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 commotions | |
n.混乱,喧闹,骚动( commotion的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 discord | |
n.不和,意见不合,争论,(音乐)不和谐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 tempted | |
v.怂恿(某人)干不正当的事;冒…的险(tempt的过去分词) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 isolated | |
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 defective | |
adj.有毛病的,有问题的,有瑕疵的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 emanates | |
v.从…处传出,传出( emanate的第三人称单数 );产生,表现,显示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 parental | |
adj.父母的;父的;母的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 formerly | |
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 attachment | |
n.附属物,附件;依恋;依附 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 well-being | |
n.安康,安乐,幸福 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 accustoms | |
v.(使)习惯于( accustom的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 imbibes | |
v.吸收( imbibe的第三人称单数 );喝;吸取;吸气 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 requisite | |
adj.需要的,必不可少的;n.必需品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 indirectly | |
adv.间接地,不直接了当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 impels | |
v.推动、推进或敦促某人做某事( impel的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 disperse | |
vi.使分散;使消失;vt.分散;驱散 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 fictitiously | |
adv.虚构地;假地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 hierarchy | |
n.等级制度;统治集团,领导层 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 inspection | |
n.检查,审查,检阅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 indictment | |
n.起诉;诉状 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 prey | |
n.被掠食者,牺牲者,掠食;v.捕食,掠夺,折磨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 anarchy | |
n.无政府状态;社会秩序混乱,无秩序 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 acting | |
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 irresistible | |
adj.非常诱人的,无法拒绝的,无法抗拒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 peril | |
n.(严重的)危险;危险的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 perilous | |
adj.危险的,冒险的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 craving | |
n.渴望,热望 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 lawful | |
adj.法律许可的,守法的,合法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 insignificant | |
adj.无关紧要的,可忽略的,无意义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 minor | |
adj.较小(少)的,较次要的;n.辅修学科;vi.辅修 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 promulgate | |
v.宣布;传播;颁布(法令、新法律等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 enactment | |
n.演出,担任…角色;制订,通过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 enactments | |
n.演出( enactment的名词复数 );展现;规定;通过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 functionary | |
n.官员;公职人员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 ordinances | |
n.条例,法令( ordinance的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 radii | |
n.半径;半径(距离)( radius的名词复数 );用半径度量的圆形面积;半径范围;桡骨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 compliance | |
n.顺从;服从;附和;屈从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 penetrates | |
v.穿过( penetrate的第三人称单数 );刺入;了解;渗透 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 descend | |
vt./vi.传下来,下来,下降 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 descends | |
v.下来( descend的第三人称单数 );下去;下降;下斜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 authorized | |
a.委任的,许可的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 inflict | |
vt.(on)把…强加给,使遭受,使承担 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 offender | |
n.冒犯者,违反者,犯罪者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 promotion | |
n.提升,晋级;促销,宣传 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 propriety | |
n.正当行为;正当;适当 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 constituents | |
n.选民( constituent的名词复数 );成分;构成部分;要素 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141 ballot | |
n.(不记名)投票,投票总数,投票权;vi.投票 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142 inflicting | |
把…强加给,使承受,遭受( inflict的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143 bestowing | |
砖窑中砖堆上层已烧透的砖 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144 concession | |
n.让步,妥协;特许(权) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145 averse | |
adj.厌恶的;反对的,不乐意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146 solicited | |
v.恳求( solicit的过去式和过去分词 );(指娼妇)拉客;索求;征求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147 accede | |
v.应允,同意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148 versed | |
adj. 精通,熟练 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149 publicity | |
n.众所周知,闻名;宣传,广告 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150 superstitions | |
迷信,迷信行为( superstition的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151 refractory | |
adj.倔强的,难驾驭的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
152 purely | |
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
153 investigation | |
n.调查,调查研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
154 investigations | |
(正式的)调查( investigation的名词复数 ); 侦查; 科学研究; 学术研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
155 procure | |
vt.获得,取得,促成;vi.拉皮条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
156 annually | |
adv.一年一次,每年 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
157 levy | |
n.征收税或其他款项,征收额 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
158 evade | |
vt.逃避,回避;避开,躲避 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
159 condemns | |
v.(通常因道义上的原因而)谴责( condemn的第三人称单数 );宣判;宣布…不能使用;迫使…陷于不幸的境地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
160 levied | |
征(兵)( levy的过去式和过去分词 ); 索取; 发动(战争); 征税 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
161 concealed | |
a.隐藏的,隐蔽的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
162 fortified | |
adj. 加强的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
163 proceeding | |
n.行动,进行,(pl.)会议录,学报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
164 proceedings | |
n.进程,过程,议程;诉讼(程序);公报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
165 accurately | |
adv.准确地,精确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
166 reprehensible | |
adj.该受责备的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
167 zeal | |
n.热心,热情,热忱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
168 enjoins | |
v.命令( enjoin的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
169 violations | |
违反( violation的名词复数 ); 冒犯; 违反(行为、事例); 强奸 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
170 appreciable | |
adj.明显的,可见的,可估量的,可觉察的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
171 condemned | |
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
172 negligence | |
n.疏忽,玩忽,粗心大意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
173 recapitulate | |
v.节述要旨,择要说明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
174 omission | |
n.省略,删节;遗漏或省略的事物,冗长 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
175 insignificance | |
n.不重要;无价值;无意义 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
176 specially | |
adv.特定地;特殊地;明确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
177 prosecutor | |
n.起诉人;检察官,公诉人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
178 prosecution | |
n.起诉,告发,检举,执行,经营 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
179 prosecuted | |
a.被起诉的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
180 delinquents | |
n.(尤指青少年)有过失的人,违法的人( delinquent的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
181 delinquent | |
adj.犯法的,有过失的;n.违法者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
182 fiscal | |
adj.财政的,会计的,国库的,国库岁入的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
183 cupidity | |
n.贪心,贪财 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
184 advantageous | |
adj.有利的;有帮助的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
185 extremity | |
n.末端,尽头;尽力;终极;极度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
186 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
187 Augmented | |
adj.增音的 动词augment的过去式和过去分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
188 awakened | |
v.(使)醒( awaken的过去式和过去分词 );(使)觉醒;弄醒;(使)意识到 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
189 influential | |
adj.有影响的,有权势的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
190 emigrants | |
n.(从本国移往他国的)移民( emigrant的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
191 diffused | |
散布的,普及的,扩散的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
192 quorum | |
n.法定人数 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
193 expenditure | |
n.(时间、劳力、金钱等)支出;使用,消耗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
194 pecuniary | |
adj.金钱的;金钱上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
195 bestowed | |
赠给,授予( bestow的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
196 derive | |
v.取得;导出;引申;来自;源自;出自 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
197 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
198 prosecuting | |
检举、告发某人( prosecute的现在分词 ); 对某人提起公诉; 继续从事(某事物); 担任控方律师 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
199 procured | |
v.(努力)取得, (设法)获得( procure的过去式和过去分词 );拉皮条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
200 afterward | |
adv.后来;以后 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
201 judgment | |
n.审判;判断力,识别力,看法,意见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
202 nomination | |
n.提名,任命,提名权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
203 impeaches | |
v.控告(某人)犯罪( impeach的第三人称单数 );弹劾;对(某事物)怀疑;提出异议 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
204 nucleus | |
n.核,核心,原子核 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
205 hereditary | |
adj.遗传的,遗传性的,可继承的,世袭的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
206 bulwark | |
n.堡垒,保障,防御 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
207 concurred | |
同意(concur的过去式与过去分词形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
208 retard | |
n.阻止,延迟;vt.妨碍,延迟,使减速 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
209 undertakings | |
企业( undertaking的名词复数 ); 保证; 殡仪业; 任务 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
210 undertaking | |
n.保证,许诺,事业 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
211 militia | |
n.民兵,民兵组织 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
212 quell | |
v.压制,平息,减轻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
213 revoke | |
v.废除,取消,撤回 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
214 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
215 provincial | |
adj.省的,地方的;n.外省人,乡下人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
216 discriminate | |
v.区别,辨别,区分;有区别地对待 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
217 coalesce | |
v.联合,结合,合并 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
218 subdue | |
vt.制服,使顺从,征服;抑制,克制 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
219 justified | |
a.正当的,有理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
220 vigor | |
n.活力,精力,元气 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
221 wields | |
手持着使用(武器、工具等)( wield的第三人称单数 ); 具有; 运用(权力); 施加(影响) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
222 enervates | |
v.使衰弱,使失去活力( enervate的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
223 incessantly | |
ad.不停地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
224 impairs | |
v.损害,削弱( impair的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
225 renewal | |
adj.(契约)延期,续订,更新,复活,重来 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
226 strife | |
n.争吵,冲突,倾轧,竞争 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
227 deficient | |
adj.不足的,不充份的,有缺陷的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
228 feudal | |
adj.封建的,封地的,领地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
229 straightforward | |
adj.正直的,坦率的;易懂的,简单的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
230 impede | |
v.妨碍,阻碍,阻止 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
231 juxtaposition | |
n.毗邻,并置,并列 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
232 standing | |
n.持续,地位;adj.永久的,不动的,直立的,不流动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
233 intimidate | |
vt.恐吓,威胁 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
234 treasury | |
n.宝库;国库,金库;文库 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
235 inconvenient | |
adj.不方便的,令人感到麻烦的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
236 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
237 maxims | |
n.格言,座右铭( maxim的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
238 foresight | |
n.先见之明,深谋远虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
239 isolating | |
adj.孤立的,绝缘的v.使隔离( isolate的现在分词 );将…剔出(以便看清和单独处理);使(某物质、细胞等)分离;使离析 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
240 severely | |
adv.严格地;严厉地;非常恶劣地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
241 disorder | |
n.紊乱,混乱;骚动,骚乱;疾病,失调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
242 partisans | |
游击队员( partisan的名词复数 ); 党人; 党羽; 帮伙 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
243 arduous | |
adj.艰苦的,费力的,陡峭的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
244 etiquette | |
n.礼仪,礼节;规矩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
245 dwelling | |
n.住宅,住所,寓所 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
246 supersede | |
v.替代;充任 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
247 skilful | |
(=skillful)adj.灵巧的,熟练的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
248 deity | |
n.神,神性;被奉若神明的人(或物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
249 regularity | |
n.规律性,规则性;匀称,整齐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
250 perpetuates | |
n.使永存,使人记住不忘( perpetuate的名词复数 );使永久化,使持久化,使持续 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
251 drowsy | |
adj.昏昏欲睡的,令人发困的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
252 invokes | |
v.援引( invoke的第三人称单数 );行使(权利等);祈求救助;恳求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
253 aspiring | |
adj.有志气的;有抱负的;高耸的v.渴望;追求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
254 indifference | |
n.不感兴趣,不关心,冷淡,不在乎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
255 blemishes | |
n.(身体的)瘢点( blemish的名词复数 );伤疤;瑕疵;污点 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
256 civilisation | |
n.文明,文化,开化,教化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
257 momentary | |
adj.片刻的,瞬息的;短暂的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
258 accustoming | |
v.(使)习惯于( accustom的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
259 authoritative | |
adj.有权威的,可相信的;命令式的;官方的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
260 robust | |
adj.强壮的,强健的,粗野的,需要体力的,浓的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
261 checkered | |
adj.有方格图案的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
262 animation | |
n.活泼,兴奋,卡通片/动画片的制作 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
263 vigilant | |
adj.警觉的,警戒的,警惕的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
264 avert | |
v.防止,避免;转移(目光、注意力等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
265 averts | |
防止,避免( avert的第三人称单数 ); 转移 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
266 languishes | |
长期受苦( languish的第三人称单数 ); 受折磨; 变得(越来越)衰弱; 因渴望而变得憔悴或闷闷不乐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
267 concurrence | |
n.同意;并发 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
268 apprised | |
v.告知,通知( apprise的过去式和过去分词 );评价 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
269 nay | |
adv.不;n.反对票,投反对票者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
270 propensity | |
n.倾向;习性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
271 cowers | |
v.畏缩,抖缩( cower的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
272 foe | |
n.敌人,仇敌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
273 license | |
n.执照,许可证,特许;v.许可,特许 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
274 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
275 instinctive | |
adj.(出于)本能的;直觉的;(出于)天性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
276 incitement | |
激励; 刺激; 煽动; 激励物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
277 accomplished | |
adj.有才艺的;有造诣的;达到了的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
278 inclinations | |
倾向( inclination的名词复数 ); 倾斜; 爱好; 斜坡 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
279 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
280 permanently | |
adv.永恒地,永久地,固定不变地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
281 rekindling | |
v.使再燃( rekindle的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
282 ardor | |
n.热情,狂热 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
283 consolidated | |
a.联合的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
284 solicitude | |
n.焦虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
285 analogous | |
adj.相似的;类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
286 meditates | |
深思,沉思,冥想( meditate的第三人称单数 ); 内心策划,考虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
287 soliciting | |
v.恳求( solicit的现在分词 );(指娼妇)拉客;索求;征求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
288 jealousy | |
n.妒忌,嫉妒,猜忌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
289 hatred | |
n.憎恶,憎恨,仇恨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
290 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
291 lapsed | |
adj.流失的,堕落的v.退步( lapse的过去式和过去分词 );陷入;倒退;丧失 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
292 prosecutors | |
检举人( prosecutor的名词复数 ); 告发人; 起诉人; 公诉人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
293 temperately | |
adv.节制地,适度地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
294 dread | |
vt.担忧,忧虑;惧怕,不敢;n.担忧,畏惧 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
295 yoke | |
n.轭;支配;v.给...上轭,连接,使成配偶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
296 penetrating | |
adj.(声音)响亮的,尖锐的adj.(气味)刺激的adj.(思想)敏锐的,有洞察力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
297 monarchy | |
n.君主,最高统治者;君主政体,君主国 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
298 vestiges | |
残余部分( vestige的名词复数 ); 遗迹; 痕迹; 毫不 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
299 royalty | |
n.皇家,皇族 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
300 adroitly | |
adv.熟练地,敏捷地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
301 laboring | |
n.劳动,操劳v.努力争取(for)( labor的现在分词 );苦干;详细分析;(指引擎)缓慢而困难地运转 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
302 hostility | |
n.敌对,敌意;抵制[pl.]交战,战争 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
303 professed | |
公开声称的,伪称的,已立誓信教的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
304 aspired | |
v.渴望,追求( aspire的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
305 censure | |
v./n.责备;非难;责难 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |