The meaning of representative government is, that the whole people, or some numerous portion of them, exercise through deputies periodically elected by themselves the ultimate controlling power, which, in every constitution, must reside somewhere. This ultimate power they must possess in all its completeness. They must be masters, whenever they please, of all the operations of government. There is no need that the constitutional law should itself give them this mastery. It does not in the British Constitution. But what it does give practically amounts to this: the power of final control is as essentially1 single, in a mixed and balanced government, as in a pure monarchy2 or democracy. This is the portion of truth in the opinion of the ancients, revived by great authorities in our own time, that a balanced constitution is impossible. There is almost always a balance, but the scales never hang exactly even. Which of them preponderates3 is not always apparent on the face of the political institutions. In the British Constitution, each of the three co-ordinate members of the sovereignty is invested with powers which, if fully4 exercised, would enable it to stop all the machinery5 of government. Nominally6, therefore, each is invested with equal power of thwarting7 and obstructing8 the others; and if, by exerting that power, any of the three could hope to better its position, the ordinary course of human affairs forbids us to doubt that the power would be exercised. There can be no question that the full powers of each would be employed defensively if it found itself assailed9 by one or both of the others. What, then, prevents the same powers from being exerted aggressively? The unwritten maxims11 of the Constitution—in other words, the positive political morality of the country; and this positive political morality is what we must look to if we would know in whom the really supreme12 power in the Constitution resides.
By constitutional law, the crown can refuse its assent13 to any act of Parliament, and can appoint to office and maintain in it any minister, in opposition14 to the remonstrances15 of Parliament. But the constitutional morality of the country nullifies these powers, preventing them from being ever used; and, by requiring that the head of the administration should always be virtually appointed by the House of Commons, makes that body the real sovereign of the state.
These unwritten rules, which limit the use of lawful16 powers, are, however, only effectual, and maintain themselves in existence on condition of harmonising with the actual distribution of real political strength. There is in every constitution a strongest power—one which would gain the victory if the compromises by which the Constitution habitually17 works were suspended, and there came a trial of strength. Constitutional maxims are adhered to, and are practically operative, so long as they give the predominance in the Constitution to that one of the powers which has the preponderance of active power out of doors. This, in England, is the popular power. If, therefore, the legal provisions of the British Constitution, together with the unwritten maxims by which the conduct of the different political authorities is in fact regulated, did not give to the popular element in the Constitution that substantial supremacy18 over every department of the government which corresponds to its real power in the country, the Constitution would not possess the stability which characterizes it; either the laws or the unwritten maxims would soon have to be changed. The British government is thus a representative government in the correct sense of the term; and the powers which it leaves in hands not directly accountable to the people can only be considered as precautions which the ruling power is willing should be taken against its own errors. Such precautions have existed in all well-constructed democracies. The Athenian Constitution had many such provisions, and so has that of the United States.
But while it is essential to representative government that the practical supremacy in the state should reside in the representatives of the people, it is an open question what actual functions, what precise part in the machinery of government, shall be directly and personally discharged by the representative body. Great varieties in this respect are compatible with the essence of representative government, provided the functions are such as secure to the representative body the control of every thing in the last resort.
There is a radical19 distinction between controlling the business of government and actually doing it. The same person or body may be able to control every thing, but can not possibly do every thing; and in many cases its control over every thing will be more perfect the less it personally attempts to do. The commander of an army could not direct its movements effectually if he himself fought in the ranks or led an assault. It is the same with bodies of men. Some things can not be done except by bodies; other things can not be well done by them. It is one question, therefore, what a popular assembly should control, another what it should itself do. It should, as we have already seen, control all the operations of government. But, in order to determine through what channel this general control may most expediently20 be exercised, and what portion of the business of government the representative assembly should hold in its own hands, it is necessary to consider what kinds of business a numerous body is competent to perform properly. That alone which it can do well it ought to take personally upon itself. With regard to the rest, its proper province is not to do it, but to take means for having it well done by others.
For example, the duty which is considered as belonging more peculiarly than any other to an assembly representative of the people is that of voting the taxes. Nevertheless, in no country does the representative body undertake, by itself or its delegated officers, to prepare the estimates. Though the supplies can only be voted by the House of Commons, and though the sanction of the House is also required for the appropriation22 of the revenues to the different items of the public expenditure23, it is the maxim10 and the uniform practice of the Constitution that money can be granted only on the proposition of the crown. It has, no doubt, been felt that moderation as to the amount, and care and judgment24 in the detail of its application, can only be expected when the executive government, through whose hands it is to pass, is made responsible for the plans and calculations on which the disbursements are grounded. Parliament, accordingly, is not expected, nor even permitted, to originate directly either taxation25 or expenditure. All it is asked for is its consent, and the sole power it possesses is that of refusal.
The principles which are involved and recognized in this constitutional doctrine26, if followed as far as they will go, are a guide to the limitation and definition of the general functions of representative assemblies. In the first place, it is admitted in all countries in which the representative system is practically understood, that numerous representative bodies ought not to administer. The maxim is grounded not only on the most essential principles of good government, but on those of the successful conduct of business of any description. No body of men, unless organized and under command, is fit for action, in the proper sense. Even a select board, composed of few members, and these specially27 conversant28 with the business to be done, is always an inferior instrument to some one individual who could be found among them, and would be improved in character if that one person were made the chief, and all the others reduced to subordinates. What can be done better by a body than by any individual is deliberation. When it is necessary or important to secure hearing and consideration to many conflicting opinions, a deliberative body is indispensable. Those bodies, therefore, are frequently useful, even for administrative29 business, but in general only as advisers30; such business being, as a rule, better conducted under the responsibility of one. Even a joint-stock company has always in practice, if not in theory, a managing director; its good or bad management depends essentially on some one person's qualifications, and the remaining directors, when of any use, are so by their suggestions to him, or by the power they possess of watching him, and restraining or removing him in case of misconduct. That they are ostensibly equal shares with him in the management is no advantage, but a considerable set-off against any good which they are capable of doing: it weakens greatly the sense in his own mind, and in those of other people, of that individual responsibility in which he should stand forth31 personally and undividedly.
But a popular assembly is still less fitted to administer, or to dictate32 in detail to those who have the charge of administration. Even when honestly meant, the interference is almost always injurious. Every branch of public administration is a skilled business, which has its own peculiar21 principles and traditional rules, many of them not even known in any effectual way, except to those who have at some time had a hand in carrying on the business, and none of them likely to be duly appreciated by persons not practically acquainted with the department. I do not mean that the transaction of public business has esoteric mysteries, only to be understood by the initiated34. Its principles are all intelligible35 to any person of good sense, who has in his mind a true picture of the circumstances and conditions to be dealt with; but to have this he must know those circumstances and conditions; and the knowledge does not come by intuition. There are many rules of the greatest importance in every branch of public business (as there are in every private occupation), of which a person fresh to the subject neither knows the reason or even suspects the existence, because they are intended to meet dangers or provide against inconveniences which never entered into his thoughts. I have known public men, ministers of more than ordinary natural capacity, who, on their first introduction to a department of business new to them, have excited the mirth of their inferiors by the air with which they announced as a truth hitherto set at nought36, and brought to light by themselves, something which was probably the first thought of every body who ever looked at the subject, given up as soon as he had got on to a second. It is true that a great statesman is he who knows when to depart from traditions, as well as when to adhere to them; but it is a great mistake to suppose that he will do this better for being ignorant of the traditions. No one who does not thoroughly37 know the modes of action which common experience has sanctioned is capable of judging of the circumstances which require a departure from those ordinary modes of action. The interests dependent on the acts done by a public department, the consequences liable to follow from any particular mode of conducting it, require for weighing and estimating them a kind of knowledge, and of specially exercised judgment, almost as rarely found in those not bred to it, as the capacity to reform the law in those who have not professionally studied it. All these difficulties are sure to be ignored by a representative assembly which attempts to decide on special acts of administration. At its best, it is inexperience sitting in judgment on experience, ignorance on knowledge; ignorance which, never suspecting the existence of what it does not know, is equally careless and supercilious38, making light of, if not resenting, all pretensions39 to have a judgment better worth attending to than its own. Thus it is when no interested motives40 intervene; but when they do, the result is jobbery more unblushing and audacious than the worst corruption41 which can well take place in a public office under a government of publicity42. It is not necessary that the interested bias43 should extend to the majority of the assembly. In any particular case it is of ten enough that it affects two or three of their number. Those two or three will have a greater interest in misleading the body than any other of its members are likely to have in putting it right. The bulk of the assembly may keep their hands clean, but they can not keep their minds vigilant44 or their judgments45 discerning in matters they know nothing about; and an indolent majority, like an indolent individual, belongs to the person who takes most pains with it. The bad measures or bad appointments of a minister may be checked by Parliament; and the interest of ministers in defending, and of rival partisans46 in attacking, secures a tolerably equal discussion; but quis custodiet custodes? who shall check the Parliament? A minister, a head of an office, feels himself under some responsibility. An assembly in such cases feels under no responsibility at all; for when did any member of Parliament lose his seat for the vote he gave on any detail of administration? To a minister, or the head of an office, it is of more importance what will be thought of his proceedings47 some time hence, than what is thought of them at the instant; but an assembly, if the cry of the moment goes with it, however hastily raised or artificially stirred up, thinks itself and is thought by every body, to be completely exculpated48, however disastrous49 may be the consequences. Besides, an assembly never personally experiences the inconveniences of its bad measures until they have reached the dimensions of national evils. Ministers and administrators50 see them approaching, and have to bear all the annoyance51 and trouble of attempting to ward52 them off.
The proper duty of a representative assembly in regard to matters of administration is not to decide them by its own vote, but to take care that the persons who have to decide them shall be the proper persons. Even this they can not advantageously do by nominating the individuals. There is no act which more imperatively53 requires to be performed under a strong sense of individual responsibility than the nomination55 to employments. The experience of every person conversant with public affairs bears out the assertion that there is scarcely any act respecting which the conscience of an average man is less sensitive; scarcely any case in which less consideration is paid to qualifications, partly because men do not know, and partly because they do not care for, the difference in qualifications between one person and another. When a minister makes what is meant to be an honest appointment, that is, when he does not actually job it for his personal connections or his party, an ignorant person might suppose that he would try to give it to the person best qualified56. No such thing. An ordinary minister thinks himself a miracle of virtue57 if he gives it to a person of merit, or who has a claim on the public on any account, though the claim or the merit may be of the most opposite description to that required. Il fallait un calculateur, ce fut un danseur qui l'obtint, is hardly more of a caricature than in the days of Figaro; and the minister doubtless thinks himself not only blameless, but meritorious58, if the man dances well. Besides, the qualifications which fit special individuals for special duties can only be recognized by those who know the individuals, or who make it their business to examine and judge of persons from what they have done, or from the evidence of those who are in a position to judge. When these conscientious59 obligations are so little regarded by great public officers who can be made responsible for their appointments, how must it be with assemblies who can not? Even now, the worst appointments are those which are made for the sake of gaining support or disarming60 opposition in the representative body; what might we expect if they were made by the body itself? Numerous bodies never regard special qualifications at all. Unless a man is fit for the gallows61, he is thought to be about as fit as other people for almost any thing for which he can offer himself as a candidate. When appointments made by a public body are not decided62, as they almost always are, by party connection or private jobbing, a man is appointed either because he has a reputation, often quite undeserved, for general ability, or oftener for no better reason than that he is personally popular.
It has never been thought desirable that Parliament should itself nominate even the members of a cabinet. It is enough that it virtually decides who shall be prime minister, or who shall be the two or three individuals from whom the prime minister shall be chosen. In doing this, it merely recognizes the fact that a certain person is the candidate of the party whose general policy commands its support. In reality, the only thing which Parliament decides is, which of two, or at most three, parties or bodies of men shall furnish the executive government: the opinion of the party itself decides which of its members is fittest to be placed at the head. According to the existing practice of the British Constitution, these things seem to be on as good a footing as they can be. Parliament does not nominate any minister, but the crown appoints the head of the administration in conformity64 to the general wishes and inclinations65 manifested by Parliament, and the other ministers on the recommendation of the chief; while every minister has the undivided moral responsibility of appointing fit persons to the other offices of administration which are not permanent. In a republic, some other arrangement would be necessary; but the nearer it approached in practice to that which has long existed in England, the more likely it would be to work well. Either, as in the American republic, the head of the executive must be elected by some agency entirely66 independent of the representative body; or the body must content itself with naming the prime minister, and making him responsible for the choice of his associates and subordinates. In all these considerations, at least theoretically, I fully anticipate a general assent; though, practically, the tendency is strong in representative bodies to interfere33 more and more in the details of administration, by virtue of the general law, that whoever has the strongest power is more and more tempted67 to make an excessive use of it; and this is one of the practical dangers to which the futurity of representative governments will be exposed.
But it is equally true, though only of late and slowly beginning to be acknowledged, that a numerous assembly is as little fitted for the direct business of legislation as for that of administration. There is hardly any kind of intellectual work which so much needs to be done not only by experienced and exercised minds, but by minds trained to the task through long and laborious68 study, as the business of making laws. This is a sufficient reason, were there no other, why they can never be well made but by a committee of very few persons. A reason no less conclusive70 is, that every provision of a law requires to be framed with the most accurate and long-sighted perception of its effect on all the other provisions; and the law when made should be capable of fitting into a consistent whole with the previously71 existing laws. It is impossible that these conditions should be in any degree fulfilled when laws are voted clause by clause in a miscellaneous assembly. The incongruity73 of such a mode of legislating74 would strike all minds, were it not that our laws are already, as to form and construction, such a chaos75, that the confusion and contradiction seem incapable76 of being made greater by any addition to the mass. Yet even now, the utter unfitness of our legislative77 machinery for its purpose is making itself practically felt every year more and more. The mere63 time necessarily occupied in getting through bills, renders Parliament more and more incapable of passing any, except on detached and narrow points. If a bill is prepared which even attempts to deal with the whole of any subject (and it is impossible to legislate78 properly on any part without having the whole present to the mind), it hangs over from session to session through sheer impossibility of finding time to dispose of it. It matters not though the bill may have been deliberately79 drawn80 up by the authority deemed the best qualified, with all appliances and means to boot; or by a select commission, chosen for their conversancy81 with the subject, and having employed years in considering and digesting the particular measure: it can not be passed, because the House of Commons will not forego the precious privilege of tinkering it with their clumsy hands. The custom has of late been to some extent introduced, when the principle of a bill has been affirmed on the second reading, of referring it for consideration in detail to a select committee; but it has not been found that this practice causes much less time to be lost afterwards in carrying it through the committee of the whole House: the opinions or private crotchets which have been overruled by knowledge always insist on giving themselves a second chance before the tribunal of ignorance. Indeed, the practice itself has been adopted principally by the House of Lords, the members of which are less busy and fond of meddling82, and less jealous of the importance of their individual voices, than those of the elective House. And when a bill of many clauses does succeed in getting itself discussed in detail, what can depict83 the state in which it comes out of committee! Clauses omitted which are essential to the working of the rest; incongruous ones inserted to conciliate some private interest, or some crotchety member who threatens to delay the bill; articles foisted84 in on the motion of some sciolist with a mere smattering of the subject, leading to consequences which the member who introduced or those who supported the bill did not at the moment foresee, and which need an amending85 act in the next session to correct their mischiefs86. It is one of the evils of the present mode of managing these things, that the explaining and defending of a bill, and of its various provisions, is scarcely ever performed by the person from whose mind they emanated87, who probably has not a seat in the House. Their defense88 rests upon some minister or member of Parliament who did not frame them, who is dependent on cramming89 for all his arguments but those which are perfectly90 obvious, who does not know the full strength of his case, nor the best reasons by which to support it, and is wholly incapable of meeting unforeseen objections. This evil, as far as government bills are concerned, admits of remedy, and has been remedied in some representative constitutions, by allowing the government to be represented in either House by persons in its confidence, having a right to speak, though not to vote.
If that, as yet considerable, majority of the House of Commons who never desire to move an amendment91 or make a speech would no longer leave the whole regulation of business to those who do; if they would bethink themselves that better qualifications for legislation exist, and may be found if sought for, than a fluent tongue, and the faculty92 of getting elected by a constituency, it would soon be recognized that, in legislation as well as administration, the only task to which a representative assembly can possibly be competent is not that of doing the work, but of causing it to be done; of determining to whom or to what sort of people it shall be confided93, and giving or withholding94 the national sanction to it when performed. Any government fit for a high state of civilization would have as one of its fundamental elements a small body, not exceeding in number the members of a cabinet, who should act as a Commission of Legislation, having for its appointed office to make the laws. If the laws of this country were, as surely they will soon be, revised and put into a connected form, the Commission of Codification95 by which this is effected should remain as a permanent institution, to watch over the work, protect it from deterioration96, and make further improvements as often as required. No one would wish that this body should of itself have any power of enacting97 laws; the Commission would only embody98 the element of intelligence in their construction; Parliament would represent that of will. No measure would become a law until expressly sanctioned by Parliament; and Parliament, or either house, would have the power not only of rejecting but of sending back a bill to the commission for reconsideration or improvement. Either house might also exercise its initiative by referring any subject to the commission, with directions to prepare a law. The commission, of course, would have no power of refusing its instrumentality to any legislation which the country desired. Instructions, concurred99 in by both houses, to draw up a bill which should effect a particular purpose, would be imperative54 on the commissioners100, unless they preferred to resign their office. Once framed, however, Parliament should have no power to alter the measure, but solely101 to pass or reject it; or, if partially102 disapproved103 of, remit104 it to the commission for reconsideration. The commissioners should be appointed by the crown, but should hold their offices for a time certain, say five years, unless removed on an address from the two Houses of Parliament, grounded either on personal misconduct (as in the case of judges), or on refusal to draw up a bill in obedience105 to the demands of Parliament. At the expiration106 of the five years a member should cease to hold office unless reappointed, in order to provide a convenient mode of getting rid of those who had not been found equal to their duties, and of infusing new and younger blood into the body.
The necessity of some provision corresponding to this was felt even in the Athenian Democracy, where, in the time of its most complete ascendancy107, the popular Ecclesia could pass psephisms (mostly decrees on single matters of policy), but laws, so called, could only be made or altered by a different and less numerous body, renewed annually108, called the Nomothet?, whose duty it also was to revise the whole of the laws, and keep them consistent with one another. In the English Constitution there is great difficulty in introducing any arrangement which is new both in form and in substance, but comparatively little repugnance109 is felt to the attainment110 of new purposes by an adaptation of existing forms and traditions. It appears to me that the means might be devised of enriching the Constitution with this great improvement through the machinery of the House of Lords. A commission for preparing bills would in itself be no more an innovation on the Constitution than the Board for the administration of the Poor Laws, or the Inclosure Commission. If, in consideration of the great importance and dignity of the trust, it were made a rule that every person appointed a member of the Legislative Commission, unless removed from office on an address from Parliament, should be a peer for life, it is probable that the same good sense and taste which leave the judicial111 functions of the peerage practically to the exclusive care of the law lords would leave the business of legislation, except on questions involving political principles and interests, to the professional legislators; that bills originating in the Upper House would always be drawn up by them; that the government would devolve on them the framing of all its bills; and that private members of the House of Commons would gradually find it convenient, and likely to facilitate the passing of their measures through the two houses, if, instead of bringing in a bill and submitting it directly to the house, they obtained leave to introduce it and have it referred to the Legislative Commission; for it would, of course, be open to the House to refer for the consideration of that body not a subject merely, but any specific proposal, or a Draft of a Bill in extenso, when any member thought himself capable of preparing one such as ought to pass; and the House would doubtless refer every such draft to the commission, if only as materials, and for the benefit of the suggestions it might contain, as they would, in like manner, refer every amendment or objection which might be proposed in writing by any member of the House after a measure had left the commissioners' hands. The alteration112 of bills by a committee of the whole House would cease, not by formal abolition113, but by desuetude114; the right not being abandoned, but laid up in the same armoury with the royal veto, the right of withholding the supplies, and other ancient instruments of political warfare115, which no one desires to see used, but no one likes to part with, lest they should any time be found to be still needed in an extraordinary emergency. By such arrangements as these, legislation would assume its proper place as a work of skilled labor69 and special study and experience; while the most important liberty of the nation, that of being governed only by laws assented116 to by its elected representatives, would be fully preserved, and made more valuable by being detached from the serious, but by no means unavoidable drawbacks which now accompany it in the form of ignorant and ill-considered legislation.
Instead of the function of governing, for which it is radically117 unfit, the proper office of a representative assembly is to watch and control the government; to throw the light of publicity on its acts; to compel a full exposition and justification118 of all of them which any one considers questionable119; to cinsure them if found condemnable120, and, if the men who compose the government abuse their trust, or fulfill72 it in a manner which conflicts with the deliberate sense of the nation, to expel them from office, and either expressly or virtually appoint their successors. This is surely ample power, and security enough for the liberty of the nation. In addition to this, the Parliament has an office not inferior even to this in importance; to be at once the nation's Committee of Grievances121 and its Congress of Opinions; an arena122 in which not only the general opinion of the nation, but that of every section of it, and, as far as possible, of every eminent123 individual whom it contains, can produce itself in full light and challenge discussion; where every person in the country may count upon finding somebody who speaks his mind as well or better than he could speak it himself—not to friends and partisans exclusively, but in the face of opponents, to be tested by adverse124 controversy125; where those whose opinion is overruled, feel satisfied that it is heard, and set aside not by a mere act of will, but for what are thought superior reasons, and commend themselves as such to the representatives of the majority of the nation; where every party or opinion in the country can muster126 its strength, and be cured of any illusion concerning the number or power of its adherents127; where the opinion which prevails in the nation makes itself manifest as prevailing128, and marshals its hosts in the presence of the government, which is thus enabled and compelled to give way to it on the mere manifestation129, without the actual employment of its strength; where statesmen can assure themselves, far more certainly than by any other signs, what elements of opinion and power are growing and what declining, and are enabled to shape their measures with some regard not solely to present exigencies130, but to tendencies in progress. Representative assemblies are often taunted131 by their enemies with being places of mere talk and bavardage. There has seldom been more misplaced derision. I know not how a representative assembly can more usefully employ itself than in talk, when the subject of talk is the great public interests of the country, and every sentence of it represents the opinion either of some important body of persons in the nation, or of an individual in whom some such body have reposed132 their confidence. A place where every interest and shade of opinion in the country can have its cause even passionately133 pleaded, in the face of the government and of all other interests and opinions, can compel them to listen, and either comply, or state clearly why they do not, is in itself, if it answered no other purpose, one of the most important political institutions that can exist any where, and one of the foremost benefits of free government. Such "talking" would never be looked upon with disparagement134 if it were not allowed to stop "doing"; which it never would, if assemblies knew and acknowledged that talking and discussion are their proper business, while doing, as the result of discussion, is the task not of a miscellaneous body, but of individuals specially trained to it; that the fit office of an assembly is to see that those individuals are honestly and intelligently chosen, and to interfere no further with them, except by unlimited135 latitude136 of suggestion and criticism, and by applying or withholding the final seal of national assent. It is for want of this judicious137 reserve that popular assemblies attempt to do what they can not do well—to govern and legislate—and provide no machinery but their own for much of it, when of course every hour spent in talk is an hour withdrawn138 from actual business. But the very fact which most unfits such bodies for a council of legislation, qualifies them the more for their other office—namely, that they are not a selection of the greatest political minds in the country, from whose opinions little could with certainty be inferred concerning those of the nation, but are, when properly constituted, a fair sample of every grade of intellect among the people which is at all entitled to a voice in public affairs. Their part is to indicate wants, to be an organ for popular demands, and a place of adverse discussion for all opinions relating to public matters, both great and small; and, along with this, to check by criticism, and eventually by withdrawing their support, those high public officers who really conduct the public business, or who appoint those by whom it is conducted. Nothing but the restriction139 of the function of representative bodies within these rational limits will enable the benefits of popular control to be enjoyed in conjunction with the no less important requisites140 (growing ever more important as human affairs increase in scale and in complexity) of skilled legislation and administration. There are no means of combining these benefits except by separating the functions which guaranty the one from those which essentially require the other; by disjoining the office of control and criticism from the actual conduct of affairs, and devolving the former on the representatives of the Many, while securing for the latter, under strict responsibility to the nation, the acquired knowledge and practiced intelligence of a specially trained and experienced Few.
The preceding discussion of the functions which ought to devolve on the sovereign representative assembly of the nation would require to be followed by an inquiry141 into those properly vested in the minor142 representative bodies, which ought to exist for purposes that regard only localities. And such an inquiry forms an essential part of the present treatise143; but many reasons require its postponement144, until we have considered the most proper composition of the great representative body, destined145 to control as sovereign the enactment146 of laws and the administration of the general affairs of the nation.
点击收听单词发音
1 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 monarchy | |
n.君主,最高统治者;君主政体,君主国 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 preponderates | |
v.超过,胜过( preponderate的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 machinery | |
n.(总称)机械,机器;机构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 nominally | |
在名义上,表面地; 应名儿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 thwarting | |
阻挠( thwart的现在分词 ); 使受挫折; 挫败; 横过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 obstructing | |
阻塞( obstruct的现在分词 ); 堵塞; 阻碍; 阻止 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 assailed | |
v.攻击( assail的过去式和过去分词 );困扰;质问;毅然应对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 maxim | |
n.格言,箴言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 maxims | |
n.格言,座右铭( maxim的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 assent | |
v.批准,认可;n.批准,认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 remonstrances | |
n.抱怨,抗议( remonstrance的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 lawful | |
adj.法律许可的,守法的,合法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 habitually | |
ad.习惯地,通常地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 supremacy | |
n.至上;至高权力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 radical | |
n.激进份子,原子团,根号;adj.根本的,激进的,彻底的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 expediently | |
adv.方便地,得当地,便利地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 appropriation | |
n.拨款,批准支出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 expenditure | |
n.(时间、劳力、金钱等)支出;使用,消耗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 judgment | |
n.审判;判断力,识别力,看法,意见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 taxation | |
n.征税,税收,税金 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 specially | |
adv.特定地;特殊地;明确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 conversant | |
adj.亲近的,有交情的,熟悉的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 administrative | |
adj.行政的,管理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 advisers | |
顾问,劝告者( adviser的名词复数 ); (指导大学新生学科问题等的)指导教授 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 dictate | |
v.口授;(使)听写;指令,指示,命令 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 interfere | |
v.(in)干涉,干预;(with)妨碍,打扰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 initiated | |
n. 创始人 adj. 新加入的 vt. 开始,创始,启蒙,介绍加入 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 intelligible | |
adj.可理解的,明白易懂的,清楚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 nought | |
n./adj.无,零 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 thoroughly | |
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 supercilious | |
adj.目中无人的,高傲的;adv.高傲地;n.高傲 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 pretensions | |
自称( pretension的名词复数 ); 自命不凡; 要求; 权力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 corruption | |
n.腐败,堕落,贪污 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 publicity | |
n.众所周知,闻名;宣传,广告 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 bias | |
n.偏见,偏心,偏袒;vt.使有偏见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 vigilant | |
adj.警觉的,警戒的,警惕的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 judgments | |
判断( judgment的名词复数 ); 鉴定; 评价; 审判 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 partisans | |
游击队员( partisan的名词复数 ); 党人; 党羽; 帮伙 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 proceedings | |
n.进程,过程,议程;诉讼(程序);公报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 exculpated | |
v.开脱,使无罪( exculpate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 disastrous | |
adj.灾难性的,造成灾害的;极坏的,很糟的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 administrators | |
n.管理者( administrator的名词复数 );有管理(或行政)才能的人;(由遗嘱检验法庭指定的)遗产管理人;奉派暂管主教教区的牧师 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 annoyance | |
n.恼怒,生气,烦恼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 ward | |
n.守卫,监护,病房,行政区,由监护人或法院保护的人(尤指儿童);vt.守护,躲开 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 imperatively | |
adv.命令式地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 imperative | |
n.命令,需要;规则;祈使语气;adj.强制的;紧急的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 nomination | |
n.提名,任命,提名权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 qualified | |
adj.合格的,有资格的,胜任的,有限制的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 meritorious | |
adj.值得赞赏的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 conscientious | |
adj.审慎正直的,认真的,本着良心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 disarming | |
adj.消除敌意的,使人消气的v.裁军( disarm的现在分词 );使息怒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 gallows | |
n.绞刑架,绞台 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 decided | |
adj.决定了的,坚决的;明显的,明确的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 conformity | |
n.一致,遵从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 inclinations | |
倾向( inclination的名词复数 ); 倾斜; 爱好; 斜坡 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 tempted | |
v.怂恿(某人)干不正当的事;冒…的险(tempt的过去分词) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 laborious | |
adj.吃力的,努力的,不流畅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 labor | |
n.劳动,努力,工作,劳工;分娩;vi.劳动,努力,苦干;vt.详细分析;麻烦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 conclusive | |
adj.最后的,结论的;确凿的,消除怀疑的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 fulfill | |
vt.履行,实现,完成;满足,使满意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 incongruity | |
n.不协调,不一致 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 legislating | |
v.立法,制定法律( legislate的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 chaos | |
n.混乱,无秩序 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 incapable | |
adj.无能力的,不能做某事的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 legislative | |
n.立法机构,立法权;adj.立法的,有立法权的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 legislate | |
vt.制定法律;n.法规,律例;立法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 deliberately | |
adv.审慎地;蓄意地;故意地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 conversancy | |
n.熟练,精通 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 meddling | |
v.干涉,干预(他人事务)( meddle的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 depict | |
vt.描画,描绘;描写,描述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 foisted | |
强迫接受,把…强加于( foist的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 amending | |
改良,修改,修订( amend的现在分词 ); 改良,修改,修订( amend的第三人称单数 )( amends的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 mischiefs | |
损害( mischief的名词复数 ); 危害; 胡闹; 调皮捣蛋的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 emanated | |
v.从…处传出,传出( emanate的过去式和过去分词 );产生,表现,显示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 defense | |
n.防御,保卫;[pl.]防务工事;辩护,答辩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 cramming | |
n.塞满,填鸭式的用功v.塞入( cram的现在分词 );填塞;塞满;(为考试而)死记硬背功课 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 amendment | |
n.改正,修正,改善,修正案 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 faculty | |
n.才能;学院,系;(学院或系的)全体教学人员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 confided | |
v.吐露(秘密,心事等)( confide的过去式和过去分词 );(向某人)吐露(隐私、秘密等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 withholding | |
扣缴税款 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 codification | |
n.法典编纂,法律成文化;法规汇编 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 deterioration | |
n.退化;恶化;变坏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 enacting | |
制定(法律),通过(法案)( enact的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 embody | |
vt.具体表达,使具体化;包含,收录 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 concurred | |
同意(concur的过去式与过去分词形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 commissioners | |
n.专员( commissioner的名词复数 );长官;委员;政府部门的长官 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 partially | |
adv.部分地,从某些方面讲 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 disapproved | |
v.不赞成( disapprove的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 remit | |
v.汇款,汇寄;豁免(债务),免除(处罚等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 obedience | |
n.服从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 expiration | |
n.终结,期满,呼气,呼出物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 ascendancy | |
n.统治权,支配力量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 annually | |
adv.一年一次,每年 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 repugnance | |
n.嫌恶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 attainment | |
n.达到,到达;[常pl.]成就,造诣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 judicial | |
adj.司法的,法庭的,审判的,明断的,公正的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 alteration | |
n.变更,改变;蚀变 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 abolition | |
n.废除,取消 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 desuetude | |
n.废止,不用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 warfare | |
n.战争(状态);斗争;冲突 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 assented | |
同意,赞成( assent的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 radically | |
ad.根本地,本质地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 justification | |
n.正当的理由;辩解的理由 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 questionable | |
adj.可疑的,有问题的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 condemnable | |
adj.该罚的,该受责备的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 grievances | |
n.委屈( grievance的名词复数 );苦衷;不满;牢骚 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 arena | |
n.竞技场,运动场所;竞争场所,舞台 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 eminent | |
adj.显赫的,杰出的,有名的,优良的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 adverse | |
adj.不利的;有害的;敌对的,不友好的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 controversy | |
n.争论,辩论,争吵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 muster | |
v.集合,收集,鼓起,激起;n.集合,检阅,集合人员,点名册 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 adherents | |
n.支持者,拥护者( adherent的名词复数 );党羽;徒子徒孙 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 prevailing | |
adj.盛行的;占优势的;主要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 manifestation | |
n.表现形式;表明;现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 exigencies | |
n.急切需要 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 taunted | |
嘲讽( taunt的过去式和过去分词 ); 嘲弄; 辱骂; 奚落 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 reposed | |
v.将(手臂等)靠在某人(某物)上( repose的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 passionately | |
ad.热烈地,激烈地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 disparagement | |
n.轻视,轻蔑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 unlimited | |
adj.无限的,不受控制的,无条件的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 latitude | |
n.纬度,行动或言论的自由(范围),(pl.)地区 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 judicious | |
adj.明智的,明断的,能作出明智决定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 withdrawn | |
vt.收回;使退出;vi.撤退,退出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 restriction | |
n.限制,约束 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 requisites | |
n.必要的事物( requisite的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142 minor | |
adj.较小(少)的,较次要的;n.辅修学科;vi.辅修 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143 treatise | |
n.专著;(专题)论文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144 postponement | |
n.推迟 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146 enactment | |
n.演出,担任…角色;制订,通过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |