If the social tendency is not a constant approximation of all men towards this progressive elevation1, the economic laws are not harmonious2.
Now, how can the level of humanity be rising, if each given quantity of labour does not yield a constantly increasing amount of enjoyments4, a phenomenon which can be explained only by the transformation5 of onerous6 into gratuitous7 utility.
And, on the other hand, how can this utility, having become gratuitous, bring men nearer and nearer to a common level, if the utility has not at the same time itself become common?
Here, then, we discover the essential law of social harmony.
I should have been pleased had the language of Political Economy furnished me with two words other than the terms production and consumption, to designate services which are rendered and received. These terms savour too much of materiality. There are evidently services, like those of the clergyman, the professor, the soldier, the artist, which tend to the furtherance of morality, education, security, taste, which have nothing in common with mechanical or manufacturing industry, except this, that the end to be attained9 is satisfaction or enjoyment3.
The terms I have referred to are those generally employed, and I have no wish to become a neologist. But let it be understood that by production I mean what confers utility, and by consumption the enjoyment to which that utility gives rise.
Let the protectionist school—which is in reality a phase of Communism—believe that in employing the terms producer and consumer we are not absurd enough to wish to represent the human race as divided into two distinct classes, the one engaged [p324] exclusively in the work of producing, the other exclusively in that of consuming. The naturalist10 divides the human race into whites and blacks, or into men and women, and the economist11, forsooth, is not to classify them as producers and consumers, because, as the protectionist gentlemen sagely12 remark, producer and consumer make but one person!
Why, it is for the very reason that they do make but one that each individual comes to be considered by the science of Political Economy in this double capacity. Our business is not to divide the human race into two classes, but to study man under two very different aspects. If the protectionists were to forbid grammarians to employ the pronouns I and thou, on the pretext13 that every man is in turn the person speaking and the person spoken to, it would be a sufficient answer to say, that although it be perfectly14 true that we cannot place all the tongues on one side, and all the ears on the other, since every man has both ears and a tongue, it by no means follows that, with reference to each proposition enunciated15, the tongue does not pertain16 to one man and the ear to another. In the same way, with reference to every service, the man who renders it is quite distinct from the man who receives it. The producer and consumer are always set opposite each other, so much so that they have always a controversy17.
The very people who object to our studying mankind under the double aspect of producers and consumers have no difficulty in making this distinction when they address themselves to legislative18 assemblies. We then find them demanding monopoly or freedom of trade, according as the matter in dispute refers to a commodity which they sell, or a commodity which they purchase.
Without dwelling19 longer, then, on this preliminary exception taken by the protectionists, let us acknowledge that in the social order the separation of employments causes each man to occupy two situations, sufficiently20 distinct to render their action and relations worthy21 of our study.
In general, we devote ourselves to some special trade, profession, or career, and it is not from that particular source that we expect to derive22 our satisfactions. We render and receive services; we supply and demand values; we make purchases and sales; we work for others, and others work for us; in short, we are producers and consumers.
According as we present ourselves in the market in one or other of these capacities, we carry thither23 a spirit which is very different, or rather, I should say, very opposite. Suppose, for example, that corn is the subject of the transaction. The same man has very [p325] different views when he goes to market as a purchaser, from what he has when he goes there as a seller. As a purchaser, he desires abundance; as a seller, scarcity24. In either case, these desires may be traced to the same source—personal interest; but as to sell or buy, to give or to receive, to supply or to demand, are acts as opposite as possible, they cannot but give rise, and from the same motive25, to opposite desires.
Antagonistic26 desires cannot at one and the same time coincide with the general good.
In another work,66 I have endeavoured to show that the wishes or desires of men in their capacity of consumers are those which are in harmony with the public interest; and it cannot be otherwise. For seeing that enjoyment is the end and design of labour, and that the labour is determined27 only by the obstacle to be overcome, it is evident that labour is in this sense an evil, and that everything should tend to diminish it; that enjoyment is a good, and that everything should tend to increase it.
And here presents itself the great, the perpetual, the deplorable illusion which springs from the erroneous definition of value, and from confounding value with utility.
Value being simply a relation, is of as much greater importance to each individual as it is of less importance to society at large.
What renders service to the masses is utility alone; and value is not at all the measure of it.
What renders service to the individual is still only utility. But value is the measure of it; for, with each determinate value, he obtains from society the utility of his choice, in the proportion of that value.
If we regard man as an isolated28 being, it is as clear as day that consumption, and not production, is the essential thing; for consumption to a certain extent implies labour, but labour does not imply consumption.
The separation of employments has led certain economists29 to measure the general prosperity, not by consumption, but by labour. And by following these economists we have come to this strange subversion30 of principle, to favour labour at the expense of its results.
The reasoning has been this: The more difficulties are overcome the better. Then augment31 the difficulties to be conquered.
The error of this reasoning is manifest.
No doubt, a certain amount of difficulties being given, it is fortunate that a certain quantity of labour also given should [p326] surmount32 as many of these difficulties as possible. But to diminish the power of the labourer or augment that of the difficulties, in order to increase value, is positively33 monstrous34.
An individual member of society is interested in this, that his services, while preserving even the same degree of utility, should increase in value. Suppose his desires in this respect to be realized, it is easy to perceive what will happen. He is better off, but his brethren are worse off, seeing that the total amount of utility has not been increased.
We cannot then reason from particulars to generals, and say: Pursue such measures as in their result will satisfy the desire which all individuals entertain to see the value of their services augmented35.
Value being a relation, we should have accomplished36 nothing if the increase in all departments were proportionate to the anterior37 value; if it were arbitrary and unequal for different services, we should have done nothing but introduce injustice38 into the distribution of utilities.
It is of the nature of every bargain or mercantile transaction to give rise to a debate. But by using this word debate, shall I not bring down upon myself all the sentimental39 schools which are nowadays so numerous? Debate implies antagonism40, it will be said. You admit, then, that antagonism is the natural state of society. Here again I have to break another lance; for in this country economic science is so little understood, that one cannot make use of a word without raising up an opponent.
I have been justly reproached for using the phrase that “Between the seller and buyer there exists a radical41 antagonism.” The word antagonism, when strengthened by the word radical, implies much more than I meant to express. It would seem to imply a permanent opposition42 of interests, consequently an indestructible social dissonance; while what I wished to indicate was merely that transient debate or discussion which precedes every commercial transaction, and which is inherent in the very idea of a bargain.
As long as, to the regret of the sentimental utopiast, there shall remain a vestige43 of liberty in the world, buyers and sellers will discuss their interests, and higgle about prices; nor will the social laws cease to be harmonious on that account. Is it possible to conceive that the man who offers and the man who demands a service should meet each other in the market without having for the moment a different idea of its value? Is that to set the world on fire? Must all commercial transactions, all exchanges, all barter44, all liberty, be banished45 from this earth, or are we to allow each of [p327] the contracting parties to defend his position, and urge and put forward his motives46? It is this very free debate or discussion which gives rise to the equivalence of services and the equity47 of transactions. By what other means can our system-makers ensure this equity which is so desirable? Would they by legislation trammel the liberty of one of the parties only? Then the one must be in the power of the other. Would they take away from both the liberty of managing their own affairs, under the pretext that they ought henceforth to buy and sell on the principle of fraternity? Let me tell the Socialists49 that it is here their absurdity50 becomes apparent, for, in the long-run, these interests must be regulated and adjusted. Is the discussion to be inverted51, the purchaser taking the part of the seller and vice8 versa? Such transactions would be very diverting, we must allow. “Please, sir, give me only 10 francs for this cloth.” “What say you? I will give you 20 for it.” “But, my good sir, it is worth nothing—it is out of fashion—it will be worn out in a fortnight,” says the merchant. “It is of the best quality, and will last two winters,” replies the customer. “Very well, sir, to please you, I will add 5 francs—this is all the length that fraternity will allow me to go.” “It is against my Socialist48 principles to pay less than 20 francs, but we must learn to make sacrifices, and I agree.” Thus this whimsical transaction will just arrive at the ordinary result, and our system-makers will regret to see accursed liberty still surviving, although turned upside down and engendering52 a new antagonism.
That is not what we want, say the organisateurs; what we desire is liberty. Then, what would you be at? for services must still be exchanged, and conditions adjusted. We expect that the care of adjusting them should be left to us. I suspected as much. . . . . .
Fraternity! bond of brotherhood53, sacred flame kindled54 by heaven in man’s soul, how has thy name been abused! In thy name all freedom has been stifled55. In thy name a new despotism, such as the world had never before seen, has been erected56; and we are at length driven to fear that the very name of fraternity, after being thus sullied, and having served as the rallying cry of so many incapables, the mask of so much ambition, and proud contempt of human dignity, should end by losing altogether its grand and noble significance.
Let us no longer, then, aim at overturning everything, domineering over everything and everybody, and withdrawing all—men and things—from the operation of natural laws. Let us leave the world as God has made it. Let us, poor scribblers, not imagine [p328] ourselves anything else than observers, more or less exact, of what is passing around us. Let us no longer render ourselves ridiculous by pretending to change human nature, as if we were ourselves beyond humanity and its errors and weaknesses. Let us leave producers and consumers to take care of their own interests, and to arrange and adjust these interests by honest and peaceful conventions. Let us confine ourselves to the observation of relations, and the effects to which they give rise. This is precisely57 what I am about to do, keeping always in view this general law, which I apprehend58 to be the law of human society, namely, the gradual equalization of individuals and of classes, combined with general progress.
A line no more resembles a force or a velocity59, than it does a value or a utility. Mathematicians60, nevertheless, make use of diagrams; and why should not the economist do the same?
We have values which are equal, values the mutual61 relations of which are known as the half, the quarter, double, triple, etc. There is nothing to prevent our representing these differences by lines of various lengths.
But the same thing does not hold with reference to utility. General utility, as we have seen, may be resolved into gratuitous utility and onerous utility, the former due to the action of nature, the latter the result of human labour. This last being capable of being estimated and measured, may be represented by a line of determinate length; but the other is not susceptible62 of estimation or of measurement. No doubt in the production of a measure of wheat, of a cask of wine, of an ox, of a stone of wool, a ton of coals, a bundle of faggots, nature does much. But we have no means of measuring this natural co-operation of forces, most of which are unknown to us, and which have been in operation since the beginning of time. Nor have we any interest in doing so. We may represent gratuitous utility, then, by an indefinite line.
Now, let there be two products, the value of the one being double that of the other, they may be represented by these lines:—
IB, ID, represent the total product, general utility, what satisfies man’s wants, absolute wealth. IA, IC, the co-operation of nature, gratuitous utility, the part which belongs to the domain63 of community. AB, CD, human service, onerous utility, value, relative wealth, the part which belongs to the domain of property.
I need not say that AB, which you may suppose, if you will, to represent a house, a piece of furniture, a book, a song sung by Jenny Lind, a horse, a bale of cloth, a consultation64 of physicians, etc., will exchange for twice CD, and that the two men who effect the exchange will give into the bargain, and without even being aware of it, the one, once IA, the other twice IC.
Man is so constituted that his constant endeavour is to diminish the proportion of effort to result, to substitute the action of nature for his own action; in a word, to accomplish more with less. This is the constant aim of his skill, his intelligence, and his energy.
Let us suppose then that John, the producer of IB, discovers a process by means of which he accomplishes his work with one-half the labour which it formerly65 cost him, taking everything into account, even the construction of the instrument by means of which he avails himself of the co-operation of nature.
As long as he preserves his secret, we shall have no change in the figures we have given above; AB and CD will represent the same values, the same relations; for John alone of all the world being acquainted with the improved process, he will turn it exclusively to his own profit and advantage. He will take his ease for half the day, or else he will make, each day, twice the quantity of IB, and his labour will be better remunerated. The discovery he has made is for the good of mankind, but mankind in this case is represented by one man.
And here let us remark, in passing, how fallacious is the axiom of the English Economists that value comes from labour, if thereby67 it is intended to represent value and labour as proportionate. Here we have the labour diminished by one-half, and yet no change in the value. This is what constantly happens, and why? Because the service is the same. Before as after the discovery, as long as it is a secret, he who gives or transfers IB renders the same service. But things will no longer be in the same position when Peter, the producer of ID, is enabled to say, “You ask me for two hours of my labour in exchange for one hour of yours; but I have found out your process, and if you set so high a price on your service, I shall serve myself.”
Now this day must necessarily come. A process once realized [p330] is not long a mystery. Then the value of the product IB will fall by one-half, and we shall have these two figures.
AA′ represent value annihilated68, relative wealth which has disappeared, property become common, utility formerly onerous, now gratuitous.
For, as regards John, who here represents the producer, he is reinstated in his former condition. With the same effort which it cost him formerly to produce IB, he can now produce twice as much. In order to obtain twice ID, we see him constrained69 to give twice IB, or what IB represents, be it furniture, books, houses, or what it may.
Who profits by all this? Clearly Peter, the producer of ID, who here represents consumers in general, including John himself. If, in fact, John desires to consume his own product, he profits by the saving of time represented by the suppression of AA′. As regards Peter, that is to say as regards consumers in general, they can now purchase IB with half the expenditure70 of time, effort, labour, value, compared with what it would have cost them before the intervention71 of natural forces. These forces, then, are gratuitous, and, moreover, common.
Since I have ventured to illustrate72 my argument by geometrical figures, perhaps I may be permitted to give another example, and I shall be happy if by this method—somewhat whimsical, I allow, as applied73 to Political Economy—I can render more intelligible74 to the reader the phenomena75 which I wish to describe.
As a producer, or as a consumer, every man may be considered as a centre from whence radiate the services which he renders, and to which tend the services which he receives in exchange.
Suppose then that there is placed at A (Fig66. 1) a producer, a copyist, for example, or transcriber76 of manuscripts, who here represents all producers, or production in general. He furnishes to society four manuscripts. If at the present moment the value of each of these manuscripts is equal to 15, he renders services equal to 60, and receives an equal value, variously spread over a multitude of services. To simplify the demonstration77, I suppose only [p331] four of them, proceeding78 from four points of the circumference79 BCDE.
Fig. 1. Fig. 2.
Value produced = 60
Value received = 60
Utility produced = 4 Value produced = 60
Value received = 60
Utility produced = 6
This man, we now suppose, discovers the art of printing. He can thenceforth produce in 40 hours what formerly would have cost him 60. Admit that competition forces him to reduce proportionally the price of his books, and that in place of being worth 15, they are now worth only 10. But then in place of four our workman can now produce six books. On the other hand, the fund of remuneration proceeding from the circumference, amounting to 60, has not changed. There is remuneration for six books, worth 10 each, just as there was formerly remuneration for four manuscripts, each worth 15.
This, let me remark briefly80, is what is always lost sight of in discussing the question of machinery81, of free-trade, and of progress in general. Men see the labour set free and rendered disposable by the expeditive process, and they become alarmed. They do not see that a corresponding proportion of remuneration is rendered disposable also by the same circumstance.
The new transactions we have supposed are represented by Fig. 2, where we see radiate from the centre A, a total value of 60, spread over six books, in place of four manuscripts. From the circumference still proceeds a value, equal to 60, necessary now as formerly, to make up the balance.
Who then has gained by the change? As regards value, no one. As regards real wealth, positive satisfactions, the countless82 body of consumers ranged round the circumference. Each of them can now purchase a book with an amount of labour reduced by one-third. But the consumers are the human race. For observe that [p332] A himself, if he gains nothing in his capacity of producer,—if he is obliged, as formerly, to perform 60 hours’ labour in order to obtain the old remuneration,—nevertheless, in as far as he is a consumer of books, gains exactly as others do. Like them, if he desires to read, he can procure84 this enjoyment with an economy of labour equal to one-third.
But if, in his character of producer, he finds himself at length deprived of the profit of his own inventions, by competition, where in that case is his compensation?
His compensation consists, 1st, in this, that as long as he was able to preserve his secret, he continued to sell 15 of what he produced at the cost of 10; 2dly, In this, that he obtains books for his own use at a smaller cost, and thus participates in the advantages he has procured85 for society. But, 3dly, His compensation consists above all in this, that just in the same way as he has been forced to impart to his fellow-men the benefit of his own progress, he benefits by the progress of his fellow-men.
Fig. 3.
Just as the progress accomplished by A has profited B, C, D, E, the progress realized by B, C, D, E has profited A. By turns A finds himself at the centre and at the circumference of universal industry, for he is by turns producer and consumer. If B, for example, is a cotton-spinner who has introduced improved machinery, the profit will redound86 to A as well as to C, D. If C is a mariner87 who has replaced the oar88 by the sail, the economy of labour will profit B, A, E.
Progress benefits the producer, as such, only during the time necessary to recompense his skill. It soon produces a fall of value, and leaves to the first imitators a fair, but small, recompense. At length value becomes proportioned to the diminished labour, and the whole saving accrues91 to society at large.
Thus all profit by the progress of each, and each profits by the progress of all. The principle, each for all, all for each, put forward by the Socialists, and which they would have us receive as a novelty, the germ of which is to be discovered in their organizations founded on oppression and constraint92, God himself has given us; and He has educed83 it from liberty. [p333]
God, I say, has given us this principle, and He has not established it in a model community, presided over by M. Considérant, or in a Phalanstère of six hundred harmoniens, or in a tentative Icarie,67 on condition that a few fanatics93 should submit themselves to the arbitrary power of a monomaniac, and that the faithless should pay for the true believers. No, God has established the principle each for all and all for each generally, universally, by a marvellous mechanism, in which justice, liberty, utility, and sociability94 are mingled95 and reconciled in such a degree as ought to discourage these manufacturers of social organizations.
Observe that this great law of each for all and all for each is much more universal than my demonstration supposes it. Words are dull and heavy, and the pen still more so. The writer is obliged to exhibit successively, and one after the other, with despairing slowness, phenomena which recommend themselves to our admiration96 only in the aggregate97.
Thus, I have just spoken of inventions. You might conclude that this was the only case in which progress, once attained, escapes from the producer, and goes to enlarge the common fund of mankind. It is not so. It is a general law that every advantage of whatever kind, proceeding from local situation, climate, or any other liberality of nature, slips rapidly from the hands of the person who first discovered and appropriated it—not on that account to be lost, but to go to feed the vast reservoir from which the enjoyments of mankind are derived98. One condition alone is attached, which is, that labour and transactions should be free. To run counter to liberty is to run counter to the designs of Providence99; it is to suspend the operation of God’s law, and limit progress in a double sense.
What I have just said with reference to the transfer of advantages holds equally true of evils and disadvantages. Nothing remains100 permanently101 with the producer—neither advantages nor inconveniences. Both tend to disseminate102 themselves through society at large.
We have just seen with what avidity the producer seeks to avail himself of whatever may facilitate his work; and we have seen, too, in how short a time the profit arising from inventions and discoveries slips from the inventor’s hands. It seems as if that profit were not in the hands of a superior intelligence, but of a blind and obedient instrument of general progress.
With the same ardour he shuns103 all that can shackle104 his action; and this is a happy thing for the human race, for it is to mankind [p334] at large that in the long-run obstacles are prejudicial. Suppose, for example, that A, the producer of books, is subjected to a heavy tax. He must add the amount of that tax to the price of his books. It will enter into the value of the books as a constituent105 part, the effect of which will be that B, C, D, E must give more labour in exchange for the same satisfaction. Their compensation will consist in the purpose to which Government applies the tax. If the use to which it is applied is beneficial, they may gain instead of losing by the arrangement. If it is employed to oppress them, they will suffer in a double sense. But as far as A is concerned, he is relieved of the tax, although he pays it in the first instance.
I do not mean to say that the producer does not frequently suffer from obstacles of various kinds, and from taxes among others. Sometimes he suffers most seriously from the operation of taxes, and it is precisely on that account that taxes tend to shift their incidence, and to fall ultimately on the masses.
Thus, in France, wine has been subjected to a multitude of exactions. And then a system has been introduced which restricts its sale abroad.
It is curious to observe what skips and bounds such burdens make in passing from the producer to the consumer. No sooner has the tax or restriction106 begun to operate than the producer endeavours to indemnify himself. But the demand of the consumers, as well as the supply of wine, remaining the same, the price cannot rise. The producer gets no more for his wine after, than he did before, the imposition of the tax. And as before the tax he received no more than an ordinary and adequate price, determined by services freely exchanged, he finds himself a loser by the whole amount of the tax. To cause the price to rise, he is obliged to diminish the quantity of wine produced.68 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
The consumer, then,—the public,—is relatively107 to the loss or profit which affects in the first instance certain classes of producers what the earth is to electricity—the great common reservoir. All proceeds from it, and after some detours108, longer or shorter as the case may be, and after having given rise to certain phenomena more or less varied109, all returns to it again.
We have just shown that the economic effects only glance upon the producer, so to speak, on their way to the consumer, and that consequently all great and important questions of this kind must [p335] be regarded from the consumer’s point of view if we wish to make ourselves masters of their general and permanent consequences.
This subordination of the interests of the producer to that of the consumer, which we have deduced from the consideration of utility, is fully110 confirmed when we advert111 to the consideration of morality.
Responsibility, in fact, always rests with the initiative. Now where is the initiative? In demand.
Demand (which implies the means of remuneration) determines all—the direction of capital and of labour, the distribution of population, the morality of professions, etc. Demand answers to Desire, while Supply answers to Effort. Desire is reasonable or unreasonable112, moral or immoral113. Effort, which is only an effect, is morally neuter, or has only a reflected morality.
Demand or Consumption says to the producer, “Make that for me.” The producer obeys. And this would be evident in every case if the producer always and everywhere waited for the demand.
But in practice this is not the case.
Is it exchange which has led to the division of labour, or the division of labour which has given rise to exchange? This is a subtle and thorny114 question. Let us say that man makes exchanges, because, being intelligent and sociable115, he comprehends that this is one means of increasing the proportion of result to effort. That which results exclusively from the division of labour and from foresight116, is that a man does not wait for a specific request to work for another. Experience teaches him tacitly that demand exists.
He makes the effort beforehand which is to satisfy the demand, and this gives rise to trades and professions. Beforehand he makes shoes, hats, etc., or prepares himself to sing, to teach, to plead, to fight, etc. But is it really the supply which precedes the demand, and determines it?
No. It is because there is a sufficient certainty that these different services will be demanded that men prepare to render them, although they do not always know precisely from what quarter the demand may come. And the proof of it is, that the relation between these different services is sufficiently well known, that their value has been so widely tested that one may devote himself with some security to a particular manufacture, or embrace a particular career.
The impulse of demand is then pre-existent, seeing that one may calculate the intensity117 of it with so much precision. [p336]
Moreover, when a man betakes himself to a particular trade or profession, and sets himself to produce commodities, about what is he solicitous118? Is it about the utility of the article which he manufactures, or its results, good or bad, moral or immoral? Not at all; he thinks only of its value. It is the demander who looks to the utility. Utility answers to his want, his desire, his caprice. Value, on the contrary, has relation only to the effort made, to the service transferred. It is only when, by means of exchange, the producer in his turn becomes the demander that utility is looked to. When I resolve to manufacture hats rather than shoes, I do not ask myself the question, whether men have a greater interest in protecting their heads or their heels. No, that concerns the demander, and determines the demand. The demand in its turn determines the value, or the degree of esteem119 in which the public holds the service. Value, in short, determines the effort or the supply.
Hence result some very remarkable120 consequences in a moral point of view. Two nations may be equally furnished with values, that is to say, with relative wealth (see chap. vi), and very unequally provided with real utilities, or absolute wealth; and this happens when one of them forms desires which are more unreasonable than those of the other—when the one considers its real wants, and the other creates for itself wants which are factitious or immoral.
Among one people a taste for education may predominate; among another a taste for good living. In such circumstances we render a service to the first when we have something to teach them; to the other, when we please their palate.
Now, services are remunerated according to the degree of importance we attach to them. If we do not exchange, if we render these services to ourselves, what should determine us if not the nature and intensity of our desires?
In one of the countries we have supposed, professors and teachers will abound121; in the other, cooks.
In both, the services exchanged may be equal in the aggregate, and may consequently represent equal values, or equal relative wealth, but not the same absolute wealth. In other words, the one employs its labour well, and the other employs it ill.
And as regards satisfactions the result will be this, that the one people will have much instruction, and the other good dinners. The ultimate consequences of this diversity of tastes will have considerable influence not only upon real, but upon relative wealth; [p337] for education may develop new means of rendering122 services, which good dinners never can.
We remark among nations a prodigious123 diversity of tastes, arising from their antecedents, their character, their opinions, their vanity, etc.
No doubt there are some wants so imperious (hunger and thirst, for example) that we regard them as determinate quantities. And yet it is not uncommon124 to see a man scrimp himself of food in order to have good clothes, while another never thinks of his dress until his appetite is satisfied. The same thing holds of nations.
But these imperious wants once satisfied, everything else depends greatly on the will. It becomes an affair of taste, and in that region morality and good sense have much influence.
The intensity of the various national desires determines always the quantity of labour which each people subtracts from the aggregate of its efforts in order to satisfy each of its desires. An Englishman must, above all things, be well fed. For this reason he devotes an enormous amount of his labour to the production of food, and if he produces any other commodities, it is with the intention of exchanging them abroad for alimentary125 substances. The quantity of corn, meat, butter, milk, sugar, etc., consumed in England is frightful126. A Frenchman desires to be amused. He delights in what pleases his eye, and in frequent changes. His labours are in accordance with his tastes. Hence we have in France multitudes of singers, mountebanks, milliners, elegant shops, coffee-rooms, etc. In China, the natives dream away life agreeably under the influence of opium127, and this is the reason why so great an amount of their national labour is devoted128 to procuring129 this precious narcotic130, either by direct production, or indirectly131 by means of exchange. In Spain, where the pomp of religious worship is carried to so great a height, the exertions132 of the people are bestowed133 on the decoration of churches, etc.
I shall not go the length of asserting that there is no immorality134 in services which pander135 to immoral and depraved desires. But the immoral principle is obviously in the desire itself.
That would be beyond doubt were man living in a state of isolation136; and it is equally true as regards man in society, for society is only individuality enlarged.
Who then would think of blaming our labourers in the south of France for producing brandy? They satisfy a demand. They dig their vineyards, dress their vines, gather and distil137 the grapes, without concerning themselves about the use which will be made of the product. It is for the man who seeks the enjoyment to [p338] consider whether it is proper, moral, rational, or productive of good. The responsibility rests with him. The business of the world could be conducted on no other footing. Is the tailor to tell his customer that he cannot make him a coat of the fashion he wants because it is extravagant138, or because it prevents his breathing freely, etc., etc.
Then what concern is it of our poor vine-dressers if rich diners-out in London indulge too freely in claret? Or can we seriously accuse the English of raising opium in India with the deliberate intention of poisoning the Chinese?
A frivolous139 people requires frivolous manufactures, just as a serious people requires industry of a more serious kind. If the human race is to be improved, it must be by the improved morality of the consumer, not of the producer.
This is the design of religion in addressing the rich—the great consumers—so seriously on their immense responsibility. From another point of view, and employing a different language, Political Economy arrives at the same conclusion, when she affirms that we cannot check the supply of any commodity which is in demand; that as regards the producer, the commodity is simply a value, a sort of current coin which represents nothing either good or evil, whilst it is in the intention of the consumer that utility, or moral or immoral enjoyment, is to be discovered; consequently, that it is incumbent140 on the man who manifests the desire or makes the demand for the commodity to weigh the consequences, whether useful or hurtful, and to answer before God and man for the good or bad direction which he impresses upon industry.
Thus from whatever point of view we regard the subject, we see clearly that consumption is the great end of Political Economy; and that good and evil, morality and immorality, harmonies and dissonances, all come to centre in the consumer, for he represents mankind at large.
点击收听单词发音
1 elevation | |
n.高度;海拔;高地;上升;提高 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 harmonious | |
adj.和睦的,调和的,和谐的,协调的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 enjoyment | |
n.乐趣;享有;享用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 enjoyments | |
愉快( enjoyment的名词复数 ); 令人愉快的事物; 享有; 享受 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 transformation | |
n.变化;改造;转变 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 onerous | |
adj.繁重的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 gratuitous | |
adj.无偿的,免费的;无缘无故的,不必要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 naturalist | |
n.博物学家(尤指直接观察动植物者) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 economist | |
n.经济学家,经济专家,节俭的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 sagely | |
adv. 贤能地,贤明地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 pretext | |
n.借口,托词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 enunciated | |
v.(清晰地)发音( enunciate的过去式和过去分词 );确切地说明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 pertain | |
v.(to)附属,从属;关于;有关;适合,相称 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 controversy | |
n.争论,辩论,争吵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 legislative | |
n.立法机构,立法权;adj.立法的,有立法权的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 dwelling | |
n.住宅,住所,寓所 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 worthy | |
adj.(of)值得的,配得上的;有价值的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 derive | |
v.取得;导出;引申;来自;源自;出自 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 thither | |
adv.向那里;adj.在那边的,对岸的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 scarcity | |
n.缺乏,不足,萧条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 antagonistic | |
adj.敌对的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 isolated | |
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 economists | |
n.经济学家,经济专家( economist的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 subversion | |
n.颠覆,破坏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 augment | |
vt.(使)增大,增加,增长,扩张 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 surmount | |
vt.克服;置于…顶上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 positively | |
adv.明确地,断然,坚决地;实在,确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 monstrous | |
adj.巨大的;恐怖的;可耻的,丢脸的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 Augmented | |
adj.增音的 动词augment的过去式和过去分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 accomplished | |
adj.有才艺的;有造诣的;达到了的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 anterior | |
adj.较早的;在前的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 injustice | |
n.非正义,不公正,不公平,侵犯(别人的)权利 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 sentimental | |
adj.多愁善感的,感伤的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 antagonism | |
n.对抗,敌对,对立 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 radical | |
n.激进份子,原子团,根号;adj.根本的,激进的,彻底的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 vestige | |
n.痕迹,遗迹,残余 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 barter | |
n.物物交换,以货易货,实物交易 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 banished | |
v.放逐,驱逐( banish的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 equity | |
n.公正,公平,(无固定利息的)股票 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 socialist | |
n.社会主义者;adj.社会主义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 socialists | |
社会主义者( socialist的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 absurdity | |
n.荒谬,愚蠢;谬论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 inverted | |
adj.反向的,倒转的v.使倒置,使反转( invert的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 engendering | |
v.产生(某形势或状况),造成,引起( engender的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 brotherhood | |
n.兄弟般的关系,手中情谊 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 kindled | |
(使某物)燃烧,着火( kindle的过去式和过去分词 ); 激起(感情等); 发亮,放光 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 stifled | |
(使)窒息, (使)窒闷( stifle的过去式和过去分词 ); 镇压,遏制; 堵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 ERECTED | |
adj. 直立的,竖立的,笔直的 vt. 使 ... 直立,建立 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 apprehend | |
vt.理解,领悟,逮捕,拘捕,忧虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 velocity | |
n.速度,速率 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 mathematicians | |
数学家( mathematician的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 mutual | |
adj.相互的,彼此的;共同的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 susceptible | |
adj.过敏的,敏感的;易动感情的,易受感动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 domain | |
n.(活动等)领域,范围;领地,势力范围 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 consultation | |
n.咨询;商量;商议;会议 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 formerly | |
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 fig | |
n.无花果(树) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 annihilated | |
v.(彻底)消灭( annihilate的过去式和过去分词 );使无效;废止;彻底击溃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 constrained | |
adj.束缚的,节制的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 expenditure | |
n.(时间、劳力、金钱等)支出;使用,消耗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 intervention | |
n.介入,干涉,干预 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 illustrate | |
v.举例说明,阐明;图解,加插图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 intelligible | |
adj.可理解的,明白易懂的,清楚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 transcriber | |
抄写者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 demonstration | |
n.表明,示范,论证,示威 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 proceeding | |
n.行动,进行,(pl.)会议录,学报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 circumference | |
n.圆周,周长,圆周线 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 briefly | |
adv.简单地,简短地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 machinery | |
n.(总称)机械,机器;机构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 countless | |
adj.无数的,多得不计其数的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 educed | |
v.引出( educe的过去式和过去分词 );唤起或开发出(潜能);推断(出);从数据中演绎(出) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 procure | |
vt.获得,取得,促成;vi.拉皮条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 procured | |
v.(努力)取得, (设法)获得( procure的过去式和过去分词 );拉皮条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 redound | |
v.有助于;提;报应 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 mariner | |
n.水手号不载人航天探测器,海员,航海者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 oar | |
n.桨,橹,划手;v.划行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 mechanism | |
n.机械装置;机构,结构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 reposes | |
v.将(手臂等)靠在某人(某物)上( repose的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 accrues | |
v.增加( accrue的第三人称单数 );(通过自然增长)产生;获得;(使钱款、债务)积累 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 constraint | |
n.(on)约束,限制;限制(或约束)性的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 fanatics | |
狂热者,入迷者( fanatic的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 sociability | |
n.好交际,社交性,善于交际 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 mingled | |
混合,混入( mingle的过去式和过去分词 ); 混进,与…交往[联系] | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 admiration | |
n.钦佩,赞美,羡慕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 aggregate | |
adj.总计的,集合的;n.总数;v.合计;集合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 providence | |
n.深谋远虑,天道,天意;远见;节约;上帝 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 permanently | |
adv.永恒地,永久地,固定不变地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 disseminate | |
v.散布;传播 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 shuns | |
v.避开,回避,避免( shun的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 shackle | |
n.桎梏,束缚物;v.加桎梏,加枷锁,束缚 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 constituent | |
n.选民;成分,组分;adj.组成的,构成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 restriction | |
n.限制,约束 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 relatively | |
adv.比较...地,相对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 detours | |
绕行的路( detour的名词复数 ); 绕道,兜圈子 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 varied | |
adj.多样的,多变化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 advert | |
vi.注意,留意,言及;n.广告 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 unreasonable | |
adj.不讲道理的,不合情理的,过度的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 immoral | |
adj.不道德的,淫荡的,荒淫的,有伤风化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 thorny | |
adj.多刺的,棘手的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 sociable | |
adj.好交际的,友好的,合群的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 foresight | |
n.先见之明,深谋远虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 intensity | |
n.强烈,剧烈;强度;烈度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 solicitous | |
adj.热切的,挂念的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 esteem | |
n.尊敬,尊重;vt.尊重,敬重;把…看作 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 remarkable | |
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 abound | |
vi.大量存在;(in,with)充满,富于 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 rendering | |
n.表现,描写 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 prodigious | |
adj.惊人的,奇妙的;异常的;巨大的;庞大的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 uncommon | |
adj.罕见的,非凡的,不平常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 alimentary | |
adj.饮食的,营养的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 frightful | |
adj.可怕的;讨厌的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 opium | |
n.鸦片;adj.鸦片的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 devoted | |
adj.忠诚的,忠实的,热心的,献身于...的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 procuring | |
v.(努力)取得, (设法)获得( procure的现在分词 );拉皮条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 narcotic | |
n.麻醉药,镇静剂;adj.麻醉的,催眠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 indirectly | |
adv.间接地,不直接了当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 exertions | |
n.努力( exertion的名词复数 );费力;(能力、权力等的)运用;行使 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 bestowed | |
赠给,授予( bestow的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 immorality | |
n. 不道德, 无道义 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 pander | |
v.迎合;n.拉皮条者,勾引者;帮人做坏事的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 isolation | |
n.隔离,孤立,分解,分离 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 distil | |
vt.蒸馏;提取…的精华,精选出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 extravagant | |
adj.奢侈的;过分的;(言行等)放肆的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 frivolous | |
adj.轻薄的;轻率的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 incumbent | |
adj.成为责任的,有义务的;现任的,在职的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |