The common element of all contracts might be said to be a promise, although even a promise was not necessary to a liability in debt as formerly3 understood. But as it will not be possible to discuss covenants4 further, and as consideration formed the main topic of the last Lecture, I will take up that first. Furthermore, as there is an historical difference between consideration in debt and in assumpsit, I shall confine myself to the latter, which is the later and more philosophical6 form.
It is said that any benefit conferred by the promisee on the promisor, or any detriment7 incurred8 by the promisee, [290] may be a consideration. It is also thought that every consideration may be reduced to a case of the latter sort, using the word "detriment" in a somewhat broad sense.
To illustrate10 the general doctrine11, suppose that a man is desirous of having a cask of brandy carried from Boston to Cambridge, and that a truckman, either out of kindness or from some other motive12, says that he will carry it, and it is delivered to him accordingly. If he carelessly staves in the cask, there would perhaps be no need to allege13 that he undertook to carry it, and on principle, and according to the older cases, if an undertaking14 was alleged15, no consideration for the assumpsit need be stated. /1/ The ground of complaint in that case would be a wrong, irrespective of contract. But if the complaint was that he did not carry it as agreed, the plaintiff's difficulty would be that the truckman was not bound to do so unless there was a consideration for his promise. Suppose, therefore, that it was alleged that he promised to do so in consideration of the delivery to him. Would this be a sufficient consideration? The oldest cases, going on the notion of benefit to the promisor, said that it could not be, for it was a trouble, not a benefit. /2/ Then take it from the side of detriment. The delivery is a necessary condition to the promisor's doing the kindness, and if he does it, the delivery, so far from being a detriment to the promisee, is a clear benefit to him.
But this argument is a fallacy. Clearly the delivery would be sufficient consideration to enable the owner to declare in assumpsit for the breach16 of those duties which [291] arose, irrespective of contract, from the defendant17's having undertaken to deal with the thing. /1/ It would be a sufficient consideration for any promise not involving a dealing18 with the thing for its performance, for instance, to pay a thousand dollars. /2/ And the law has not pronounced the consideration good or bad according to the nature of the promise founded upon it. The delivery is a sufficient consideration for any promise. /3/
The argument on the other side leaves out of sight the point of time at which the sufficiency of the consideration is to be determined19. This is the moment when the consideration is furnished. At that moment the delivery of the cask is a detriment in the strictest sense. The owner of the cask has given up a present control over it, which he has a right to keep, and he has got in return, not a performance for which a delivery was necessary, but a mere20 promise of performance. The performance is still future. /4/
But it will be seen that, although the delivery may be a consideration, it will not necessarily be one. A promise to carry might be made and accepted on the understanding that it was mere matter of favor, without consideration, and not legally binding21. In that case the detriment of delivery would be incurred by the promisee as before, but obviously it would be incurred for the sole purpose of enabling the promisor to carry as agreed.
[292] It appears to me that it has not always been sufficiently23 borne in mind that the same thing may be a consideration or not, as it is dealt with by the parties. The popular explanation of Coggs v. Bernard is, that the delivery was a consideration for a promise to carry the casks safely. I have given what I believe to be the true explanation, and that which I think Lord Holt had in view, in the fifth Lecture. /1/ But whether that which I have offered be true or not, a serious objection to the one which is commonly accepted is that the declaration does not allege that the delivery was the consideration.
The same caution should be observed in construing24 the terms of an agreement. It is hard to see the propriety25 of erecting26 any detriment which an instrument may disclose or provide for, into a consideration, unless the parties have dealt with it on that footing. In many cases a promisee may incur9 a detriment without thereby27 furnishing a consideration. The detriment may be nothing but a condition precedent28 to performance of the promise, as where a man promises another to pay him five hundred dollars if he breaks his leg. /2/
The courts, however, have gone far towards obliterating29 this distinction. Acts which by a fair interpretation30 of language would seem to have been contemplated31 as only the compliance33 with a condition, have been treated as the consideration of the promise. /3/ And so have counter promises in an agreement which expressly stated other matters as the consideration. /4/ So it should be mentioned, subject [293] to the question whether there may not be a special explanation for the doctrine, that it is said that an assignment of a leasehold34 cannot be voluntary under the statute35 of 27 Elizabeth, c. 4, because the assignee comes into the obligations of the tenant36. /1/ Yet the assignee's incurring37 this detriment may not be contemplated as the inducement of the assignment, and in many cases only amounts to a deduction38 from the benefit conferred, as a right of way would be, especially if the only obligation is to pay rent, which issues out of the land in theory of law.
But although the courts may have sometimes gone a little far in their anxiety to sustain agreements, there can be no doubt of the Principle which I have laid down, that the same thing may be a consideration or not, as it is dealt with by the parties. This raises the question how a thing must be dealt with, in order to make it a consideration.
It is said that consideration must not be confounded with motive. It is true that it must not be confounded with what may be the prevailing39 or chief motive in actual fact. A man may promise to paint a picture for five hundred dollars, while his chief motive may be a desire for fame. A consideration may be given and accepted, in fact, solely40 for the purpose of making a promise binding. But, nevertheless, it is the essence of a consideration, that, by the terms of the agreement, it is given and accepted as the motive or inducement of the promise. Conversely, the promise must be made and accepted as the conventional motive or inducement for furnishing the consideration. The root of the whole matter is the relation of reciprocal [294] conventional inducement, each for the other, between consideration and promise.
A good example of the former branch of the proposition is to be found in a Massachusetts case. The plaintiff refused to let certain wood be removed from his land by one who had made an oral bargain and given his note for it, unless he received additional security. The purchaser and the plaintiff accordingly went to the defendant, and the defendant put his name upon the note. The plaintiff thereupon let the purchaser carry off the wood. But, according to the testimony41, the defendant signed without knowing that the plaintiff was to alter his position in any way on the faith of the signature, and it was held that, if that story was believed, there was no consideration. /1/
An illustration of the other half of the rule is to be found in those cases where a reward is offered for doing something, which is afterwards done by a person acting42 in ignorance of the offer. In such a case the reward cannot be claimed, because the alleged consideration has not been furnished on the faith of the offer. The tendered promise has not induced the furnishing of the consideration. The promise cannot be set up as a conventional motive when it was not known until after the alleged consideration was performed. /2/
Both sides of the relation between consideration and promise, and the conventional nature of that relation, may be illustrated43 by the case of the cask. Suppose that the [295] truckman is willing to carry the cask, and the owner to let him carry it, without any bargain, and that each knows the other's state of mind; but that the truckman, seeing his own advantage in the matter, says to the owner, "In consideration of your delivering me the cask, and letting me carry it, I promise to carry it," and that the owner thereupon delivers it. I suppose that the promise would be binding. The promise is offered in terms as the inducement for the delivery, and the delivery is made in terms as the inducement for the promise. It may be very probable that the delivery would have been made without a promise, and that the promise would have been made in gratuitous44 form if it had not been accepted upon consideration; but this is only a guess after all. The delivery need not have been made unless the owner chose, and having been made as the term of a bargain, the promisor cannot set up what might have happened to destroy the effect of what did happen. It would seem therefore that the same transaction in substance and spirit might be voluntary or obligatory45, according to the form of words which the parties chose to employ for the purpose of affecting the legal consequences.
If the foregoing principles be accepted, they will be seen to explain a doctrine which has given the courts some trouble to establish. I mean the doctrine that an executed consideration will not sustain a subsequent promise. It has been said, to be sure, that such a consideration was sufficient if preceded by a request. But the objections to the view are plain. If the request was of such a nature, and so put, as reasonably to imply that the other person was to have a reward, there was an express promise, although not put in words, and that promise was made at [296] the same time the consideration was given, and not afterwards. If, on the other hand, the words did not warrant the understanding that the service was to be paid for, the service was a gift, and a past gift can no more be a consideration than any other act of the promisee not induced by the promise.
The source of the error can be traced partially46, at least, in history. Some suggestions touching47 the matter were made in the last Lecture. A few words should be added here. In the old cases of debt, where there was some question whether the plaintiff had showed enough to maintain his action, a "contract precedent" was spoken of several times as raising the duty. Thus, where a man had granted that he would be bound in one hundred shillings to pay his servant on a certain day for his services, and for payments made by the servant on his account, it was argued that there was no contract precedent, and that by parol the party is not obliged; and, further, that, so far as appeared, the payments were made by the servant out of his own head and at no request, from which no duty could commence. /1/
So when debt was brought on a deed to pay the plaintiff ten marks, if he would take the defendant's daughter to wife, and it was objected that the action should have been covenant5, it was answered that the plaintiff had a contract precedent which gave him debt. /2/
The first case in assumpsit /3/ only meant to adopt this long familiar thought. A man went bail48 for his friend's servant, who had been arrested. Afterwards the master [297] promised to indemnify the bail, and on his failure to do so was sued by him in assumpsit. It was held that there was no consideration wherefore the defendant should be charged unless the master had first promised to indemnify the plaintiff before the servant was bailed49; "for the master did never make request to the plaintiff for his servant to do so much, but he did it of his own head." This is perfectly50 plain sailing, and means no more than the case in the Year Books. The report, however, also states a case in which it was held that a subsequent promise, in consideration that the plaintiff at the special instance of the defendant had married the defendant's cousin, was binding, and that the marriage was "good cause... because [it] ensued the request of the defendant." Whether this was intended to establish a general principle, or was decided51 with reference to the peculiar52 consideration of marriage, /1/ it was soon interpreted in the broader sense, as was shown in the last Lecture. It was several times adjudged that a past and executed matter was a sufficient consideration for a promise at a later day, if only the matter relied on had been done or furnished at the request of the promisor. /2/
second and most conspicuous54 element in a simple contract. The
Indian Contract Act, 1872, Section 2,8 says:—
"(a.) When one person signifies to another his willingness [298]
make a proposal:
"(b.) When the person to whom the proposal is made signifies his
assent thereto, the proposal is said to be accepted. A proposal
when accepted becomes a promise."
According to this definition the scope of promises is confined to conduct on the part of the promisor. If this only meant that the promisor alone must bear the legal burden which his promise may create, it would be true. But this is not the meaning. For the definition is of a promise, not of a legally binding promise. We are not seeking for the legal effects of a contract, but for the possible contents of a promise which the law may or may not enforce. We must therefore only consider the question what can possibly be promised in a legal sense, not what will be the secondary consequence of a promise binding, but not performed.
An assurance that it shall rain to-morrow, /1/ or that a third person shall paint a picture, may as well be a promise as one that the promisee shall receive from some source one hundred bales of cotton, or that the promisor will pay the promisee one hundred dollars. What is the difference in the cases? It is only in the degree of power possessed57 by the promisor over the event. He has none in the first case. He has equally little legal authority to make a man paint a picture, although he may have larger means of persuasion58. He probably will be able to make sure that the promisee has the cotton. Being a rich man, he is certain [299] to be able to pay the one hundred dollars, except in the event of some most improbable accident.
But the law does not inquire, as a general thing, how far the accomplishment59 of an assurance touching the future is within the power of the promisor. In the moral world it may be that the obligation of a promise is confined to what lies within reach of the will of the promisor (except so far as the limit is unknown on one side, and misrepresented on the other). But unless some consideration of public policy intervenes, I take it that a man may bind22 himself at law that any future event shall happen. He can therefore promise it in a legal sense. It may be said that when a man covenants that it shall rain to-morrow, or that A shall paint a picture, he only says, in a short form, I will pay if it does not rain, or if A does not paint a picture. But that is not necessarily so. A promise could easily be framed which would be broken by the happening of fair weather, or by A not painting. A promise, then, is simply an accepted assurance that a certain event or state of things shall come to pass.
But if this be true, it has more important bearings than simply to enlarge the definition of the word promise. It concerns the theory of contract. The consequences of a binding promise at common law are not affected60 by the degree of power which the promisor possesses over the promised event. If the promised event does not come to pass, the plaintiff's property is sold to satisfy the damages, within certain limits, which the promisee has suffered by the failure. The consequences are the same in kind whether the promise is that it shall rain, or that another man shall paint a picture, or that the promisor will deliver a bale of cotton.
[300] If the legal consequence is the same in all cases, it seems proper that all contracts should be considered from the same legal point of view. In the case of a binding promise that it shall rain to-morrow, the immediate61 legal effect of what the promisor does is, that he takes the risk of the event, within certain defined limits, as between himself and the promisee. He does no more when he promises to deliver a bale of cotton.
If it be proper to state the common-law meaning of promise and contract in this way, it has the advantage of freeing the subject from the superfluous62 theory that contract is a qualified63 subjection of one will to another, a kind of limited slavery. It might be so regarded if the law compelled men to perform their contracts, or if it allowed promisees to exercise such compulsion. If, when a man promised to labor64 for another, the law made him do it, his relation to his promisee might be called a servitude ad hoc with some truth. But that is what the law never does. It never interferes65 until a promise has been broken, and therefore cannot possibly be performed according to its tenor66. It is true that in some instances equity67 does what is called compelling specific performance. But, in the first place, I am speaking of the common law, and, in the next, this only means that equity compels the performance of certain elements of the total promise which are still capable of performance. For instance, take a promise to convey land within a certain time, a court of equity is not in the habit of interfering68 until the time has gone by, so that the promise cannot be performed as made. But if the conveyance69 is more important than the time, and the promisee prefers to have it late rather than never, the law may compel the performance of [301] that. Not literally70 compel even in that case, however, but put the promisor in prison unless he will convey. This remedy is an exceptional one. The only universal consequence of a legally binding promise is, that the law makes the promisor pay damages if the promised event does not come to pass. In every case it leaves him free from interference until the time for fulfilment has gone by, and therefore free to break his contract if he chooses.
A more practical advantage in looking at a contract as the taking of a risk is to be found in the light which it throws upon the measure of damages. If a breach of contract were regarded in the same light as a tort, it would seem that if, in the course of performance of the contract the promisor should be notified of any particular consequence which would result from its not being performed, he should be held liable for that consequence in the event of non-performance. Such a suggestion has been made. /1/ But it has not been accepted as the law. On the contrary, according to the opinion of a very able judge, which seems to be generally followed, notice, even at the time of making the contract, of special circumstances out of which special damages would arise in case of breach, is not sufficient unless the assumption of that risk is to be taken as having fairly entered into the contract. /2/ If a carrier should undertake to carry the machinery71 of a saw-mill from Liverpool to Vancouver's Island, and should fail [302] to do so, he probably would not be held liable for the rate of hire of such machinery during the necessary delay, although he might know that it could not be replaced without sending to England, unless he was fairly understood to accept "the contract with the special condition attached to it." /1/
It is true that, when people make contracts, they usually contemplate32 the performance rather than the breach. The express language used does not generally go further than to define what will happen if the contract is fulfilled. A statutory requirement of a memorandum72 in writing would be satisfied by a written statement of the promise as made, because to require more would be to run counter to the ordinary habits of mankind, as well as because the statement that the effect of a contract is the assumption of the risk of a future event does not mean that there is a second subsidiary promise to assume that risk, but that the assumption follows as a consequence directly enforced by the law, without the promisor's co-operation. So parol evidence would be admissible, no doubt, to enlarge or diminish the extent of the liability assumed for nonperformance, where it would be inadmissible to affect the scope of the promise.
But these concessions73 do not affect the view here taken. As the relation of contractor74 and contractee is voluntary, the consequences attaching to the relation must be voluntary. What the event contemplated by the promise is, or in other words what will amount to a breach of contract, is a matter of interpretation and construction. What consequences of the breach are assumed is more remotely, in like manner, a matter of construction, having regard [303] to the circumstances under which the contract is made. Knowledge of what is dependent upon performance is one of those circumstances. It is not necessarily conclusive75, but it may have the effect of enlarging the risk assumed.
The very office of construction is to work out, from what is expressly said and done, what would have been said with regard to events not definitely before the minds of the parties, if those events had been considered. The price paid in mercantile contracts generally excludes the construction that exceptional risks were intended to be assumed. The foregoing analysis is believed to show that the result which has been reached by the courts on grounds of practical good sense, falls in with the true theory of contract under the common law.
The discussion of the nature of a promise has led me to analyze contract and the consequences of contract somewhat in advance of their place. I must say a word more concerning the facts which constitute a promise. It is laid down, with theoretical truth, that, besides the assurance or offer on the one side, there must be an acceptance on the other. But I find it hard to think of a case where a simple contract fails to be made, which could not be accounted for on other grounds, generally by the want of relation between assurance or offer and consideration as reciprocal inducements each of the other. Acceptance of an offer usually follows by mere implication from the furnishing of the consideration; and inasmuch as by our law an accepted offer, or promise, until the consideration is furnished, stands on no different footing from an offer not yet accepted, each being subject to revocation76 until that time, and each continuing [304] until then unless it has expired or has been revoked77, the question of acceptance is rarely of practical importance.
Assuming that the general nature of consideration and promise is understood, some questions peculiar to bilateral78 contracts remain to be considered. These concern the sufficiency of the consideration and the moment when the contract is made.
A promise may be a consideration for a promise, although not every promise for every other. It may be doubted whether a promise to make a gift of one hundred dollars would be supported by a promise to accept it. But in a case of mutual79 promises respectively to transfer and to accept unpaid80 shares in a railway company, it has been held that a binding contract was made. Here one party agrees to part with something which may prove valuable, and the other to assume a liability which may prove onerous81. /1/
But now suppose that there is no element of uncertainty82 except in the minds of the parties. Take, for instance, a wager83 on a past horse-race. It has been thought that this would amount to an absolute promise on one side, and no promise at all on the other. /2/ But this does not seem to me sound. Contracts are dealings between men, by which they make arrangements for the future. In making such arrangements the important thing is, not what is objectively true, but what the parties know. Any present fact which is unknown to the parties is just as uncertain for the purposes of making an arrangement at this moment, as any future fact. It is therefore a detriment to undertake to be ready to pay if the event turns out not [305] to have been as expected. This seems to be the true explanation why forbearance to sue upon a claim believed the plaintiff to be good is a sufficient consideration, although the claim was bad in fact, and known by the defendant to be bad. /1/ Were this view unsound, it is hard to see how wagers84 on any future event, except a miracle, could be sustained. For if the happening or not happening of the event is subject to the law of causation, the only uncertainty about it is in our foresight85, not in its happening.
The question when a contract is made arises for the most part with regard to bilateral contracts by letter, the doubt being whether the contract is complete at the moment when the return promise is put into the post, or at the moment when it is received. If convenience preponderates86 in favor of either view, that is a sufficient reason for its adoption87. So far as merely logical grounds go, the most ingenious argument in favor of the later moment is Professor Langdell's. According to him the conclusion follows from the fact that the consideration which makes the offer binding is itself a promise. Every promise, he says, is an offer before it is a promise, and the essence of an offer is that it should be communicated. /2/ But this reasoning seems unsound. When, as in the case supposed, the consideration for the return promise has been put into the power of the offeree and the return promise has been accepted in advance, there is not an instant, either in time or logic88, when the return promise is an offer. It is a promise and a term of a binding contract as soon as it is anything. An offer is a revocable and unaccepted communication of willingness to promise. [306] When an offer of a certain bilateral contract has been made, the same contract cannot be offered by the other side. The so-called offer would neither be revocable nor unaccepted. It would complete the contract as soon as made.
If it be said that it is of the essence of a promise to be communicated, whether it goes through the stage of offer or not, meaning by communicated brought to the actual knowledge of the promisee, the law is believed to be otherwise. A covenant is binding when it is delivered and accepted, whether it is read or not. On the same principle, it is believed that, whenever the obligation is to be entered into by a tangible89 sign, as, in the case supposed, by letter containing the return promise, and the consideration for and assent to the promise are already given, the only question is when the tangible sign is sufficiently put into the power of the promisee. I cannot believe that, if the letter had been delivered to the promisee and was then snatched from his hands before he had read it, there would be no contract. /1/ If I am right, it appears of little importance whether the post-office be regarded as agent or bailee for the offerer, or as a mere box to which he has access. The offeree, when he drops the letter containing the counter-promise into the letter-box, does an overt90 act, which by general understanding renounces91 control over the letter, and puts it into a third hand for the benefit of the offerer, with liberty to the latter at any moment thereafter to take it.
The principles governing revocation are wholly different. One to whom an offer is made has a right to assume that it remains92 open according to its terms until he has actual [307] notice to the contrary. The effect of the communication must be destroyed by a counter communication. But the making of a contract does not depend on the state of the parties' minds, it depends on their overt acts. When the sign of the counter promise is a tangible object, the contract is completed when the dominion93 over that object changes.
点击收听单词发音
1 ascertain | |
vt.发现,确定,查明,弄清 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 purport | |
n.意义,要旨,大要;v.意味著,做为...要旨,要领是... | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 formerly | |
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 covenants | |
n.(有法律约束的)协议( covenant的名词复数 );盟约;公约;(向慈善事业、信托基金会等定期捐款的)契约书 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 covenant | |
n.盟约,契约;v.订盟约 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 detriment | |
n.损害;损害物,造成损害的根源 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 incurred | |
[医]招致的,遭受的; incur的过去式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 incur | |
vt.招致,蒙受,遭遇 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 illustrate | |
v.举例说明,阐明;图解,加插图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 allege | |
vt.宣称,申述,主张,断言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 undertaking | |
n.保证,许诺,事业 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 alleged | |
a.被指控的,嫌疑的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 breach | |
n.违反,不履行;破裂;vt.冲破,攻破 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 defendant | |
n.被告;adj.处于被告地位的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 dealing | |
n.经商方法,待人态度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 binding | |
有约束力的,有效的,应遵守的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 bind | |
vt.捆,包扎;装订;约束;使凝固;vi.变硬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 construing | |
v.解释(陈述、行为等)( construe的现在分词 );翻译,作句法分析 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 propriety | |
n.正当行为;正当;适当 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 erecting | |
v.使直立,竖起( erect的现在分词 );建立 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 precedent | |
n.先例,前例;惯例;adj.在前的,在先的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 obliterating | |
v.除去( obliterate的现在分词 );涂去;擦掉;彻底破坏或毁灭 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 interpretation | |
n.解释,说明,描述;艺术处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 contemplated | |
adj. 预期的 动词contemplate的过去分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 contemplate | |
vt.盘算,计议;周密考虑;注视,凝视 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 compliance | |
n.顺从;服从;附和;屈从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 leasehold | |
n.租赁,租约,租赁权,租赁期,adj.租(来)的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 statute | |
n.成文法,法令,法规;章程,规则,条例 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 tenant | |
n.承租人;房客;佃户;v.租借,租用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 incurring | |
遭受,招致,引起( incur的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 deduction | |
n.减除,扣除,减除额;推论,推理,演绎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 prevailing | |
adj.盛行的;占优势的;主要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 testimony | |
n.证词;见证,证明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 acting | |
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 illustrated | |
adj. 有插图的,列举的 动词illustrate的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 gratuitous | |
adj.无偿的,免费的;无缘无故的,不必要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 obligatory | |
adj.强制性的,义务的,必须的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 partially | |
adv.部分地,从某些方面讲 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 touching | |
adj.动人的,使人感伤的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 bail | |
v.舀(水),保释;n.保证金,保释,保释人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 bailed | |
保释,帮助脱离困境( bail的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 decided | |
adj.决定了的,坚决的;明显的,明确的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 analyze | |
vt.分析,解析 (=analyse) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 conspicuous | |
adj.明眼的,惹人注目的;炫耀的,摆阔气的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 abstain | |
v.自制,戒绝,弃权,避免 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 assent | |
v.批准,认可;n.批准,认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 persuasion | |
n.劝说;说服;持有某种信仰的宗派 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 accomplishment | |
n.完成,成就,(pl.)造诣,技能 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 affected | |
adj.不自然的,假装的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 superfluous | |
adj.过多的,过剩的,多余的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 qualified | |
adj.合格的,有资格的,胜任的,有限制的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 labor | |
n.劳动,努力,工作,劳工;分娩;vi.劳动,努力,苦干;vt.详细分析;麻烦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 interferes | |
vi. 妨碍,冲突,干涉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 tenor | |
n.男高音(歌手),次中音(乐器),要旨,大意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 equity | |
n.公正,公平,(无固定利息的)股票 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 interfering | |
adj. 妨碍的 动词interfere的现在分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 conveyance | |
n.(不动产等的)转让,让与;转让证书;传送;运送;表达;(正)运输工具 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 literally | |
adv.照字面意义,逐字地;确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 machinery | |
n.(总称)机械,机器;机构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 memorandum | |
n.备忘录,便笺 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 concessions | |
n.(尤指由政府或雇主给予的)特许权( concession的名词复数 );承认;减价;(在某地的)特许经营权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 contractor | |
n.订约人,承包人,收缩肌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 conclusive | |
adj.最后的,结论的;确凿的,消除怀疑的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 revocation | |
n.废止,撤回 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 revoked | |
adj.[法]取消的v.撤销,取消,废除( revoke的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 bilateral | |
adj.双方的,两边的,两侧的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 mutual | |
adj.相互的,彼此的;共同的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 unpaid | |
adj.未付款的,无报酬的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 onerous | |
adj.繁重的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 uncertainty | |
n.易变,靠不住,不确知,不确定的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 wager | |
n.赌注;vt.押注,打赌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 wagers | |
n.赌注,用钱打赌( wager的名词复数 )v.在(某物)上赌钱,打赌( wager的第三人称单数 );保证,担保 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 foresight | |
n.先见之明,深谋远虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 preponderates | |
v.超过,胜过( preponderate的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 adoption | |
n.采用,采纳,通过;收养 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 logic | |
n.逻辑(学);逻辑性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 tangible | |
adj.有形的,可触摸的,确凿的,实际的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 overt | |
adj.公开的,明显的,公然的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 renounces | |
v.声明放弃( renounce的第三人称单数 );宣布放弃;宣布与…决裂;宣布摒弃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 dominion | |
n.统治,管辖,支配权;领土,版图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |