It may be seen, from the last chapter, that the way in which general business is managed may give a clear enough indication of the actual state of morals and the health of the body politic1. The more concert reigns2 in the assemblies, that is, the nearer opinion approaches unanimity3, the greater is the dominance of the general will. On the other hand, long debates, dissensions and tumult4 proclaim the ascendancy5 of particular interests and the decline of the State.
This seems less clear when two or more orders enter into the constitution, as patricians6 and plebeians7 did at Rome; for quarrels between these two orders often disturbed the comitia, even in the best days of the Republic. But the exception is rather apparent than real; for then, through the defect that is inherent in the body politic, there were, so to speak, two States in one, and what is not true of the two together is true of either separately. Indeed, even in the most stormy times, the plebiscita of the people, when the Senate did not interfere8 with them, always went through quietly and by large majorities. The citizens having but one interest, the people had but a single will.
At the other extremity9 of the circle, unanimity recurs10; this is the case when the citizens, having fallen into servitude, have lost both liberty and will. Fear and flattery then change votes into acclamation; deliberation ceases, and only worship or malediction11 is left. Such was the vile12 manner in which the senate expressed its views under the Emperors. It did so sometimes with absurd precautions. Tacitus observes that, under Otho, the senators, while they heaped curses on Vitellius, contrived13 at the same time to make a deafening14 noise, in order that, should he ever become their master, he might not know what each of them had said.
On these various considerations depend the rules by which the methods of counting votes and comparing opinions should be regulated, according as the general will is more or less easy to discover, and the State more or less in its decline.
There is but one law which, from its nature, needs unanimous consent. This is the social compact; for civil association is the most voluntary of all acts. Every man being born free and his own master, no-one, under any pretext15 whatsoever16, can make any man subject without his consent. To decide that the son of a slave is born a slave is to decide that he is not born a man.
If then there are opponents when the social compact is made, their opposition17 does not invalidate the contract, but merely prevents them from being included in it. They are foreigners among citizens. When the State is instituted, residence constitutes consent; to dwell within its territory is to submit to the Sovereign.[1]
Apart from this primitive18 contract, the vote of the majority always binds19 all the rest. This follows from the contract itself. But it is asked how a man can be both free and forced to conform to wills that are not his own. How are the opponents at once free and subject to laws they have not agreed to?
I retort that the question is wrongly put. The citizen gives his consent to all the laws, including those which are passed in spite of his opposition, and even those which punish him when he dares to break any of them. The constant will of all the members of the State is the general will; by virtue20 of it they are citizens and free.[2] When in the popular assembly a law is proposed, what the people is asked is not exactly whether it approves or rejects the proposal, but whether it is in conformity21 with the general will, which is their will. Each man, in giving his vote, states his opinion on that point; and the general will is found by counting votes. When therefore the opinion that is contrary to my own prevails, this proves neither more nor less than that I was mistaken, and that what I thought to be the general will was not so. If my particular opinion had carried the day I should have achieved the opposite of what was my will and it is in that case that I should not have been free.
This presupposes, indeed, that all the qualities of the general will still reside in the majority: when they cease to do so, whatever side a man may take, liberty is no longer possible.
In my earlier demonstration22 of how particular wills are substituted for the general will in public deliberation, I have adequately pointed23 out the practicable methods of avoiding this abuse; and I shall have more to say of them later on. I have also given the principles for determining the proportional number of votes for declaring that will. A difference of one vote destroys equality; a single opponent destroys unanimity; but between equality and unanimity, there are several grades of unequal division, at each of which this proportion may be fixed24 in accordance with the condition and the needs of the body politic.
There are two general rules that may serve to regulate this relation. First, the more grave and important the questions discussed, the nearer should the opinion that is to prevail approach unanimity. Secondly25, the more the matter in hand calls for speed, the smaller the prescribed difference in the numbers of votes may be allowed to become: where an instant decision has to be reached, a majority of one vote should be enough. The first of these two rules seems more in harmony with the laws, and the second with practical affairs. In any case, it is the combination of them that gives the best proportions for determining the majority necessary.
[1] This should of course be understood as applying to a free State; for elsewhere family, goods, lack of a refuge, necessity, or violence may detain a man in a country against his will; and then his dwelling26 there no longer by itself implies his consent to the contract or to its violation27.
[2] At Genoa, the word Liberty may be read over the front of the prisons and on the chains of the galley-slaves. This application of the device is good and just It is indeed only malefactors of all estates who prevent the citizen from being free. In the country in which all such men were in the galleys28, the most perfect liberty would be enjoyed.
点击收听单词发音
1 politic | |
adj.有智虑的;精明的;v.从政 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 reigns | |
n.君主的统治( reign的名词复数 );君主统治时期;任期;当政期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 unanimity | |
n.全体一致,一致同意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 tumult | |
n.喧哗;激动,混乱;吵闹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 ascendancy | |
n.统治权,支配力量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 patricians | |
n.(古罗马的)统治阶层成员( patrician的名词复数 );贵族,显贵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 plebeians | |
n.平民( plebeian的名词复数 );庶民;平民百姓;平庸粗俗的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 interfere | |
v.(in)干涉,干预;(with)妨碍,打扰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 extremity | |
n.末端,尽头;尽力;终极;极度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 recurs | |
再发生,复发( recur的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 malediction | |
n.诅咒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 vile | |
adj.卑鄙的,可耻的,邪恶的;坏透的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 contrived | |
adj.不自然的,做作的;虚构的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 deafening | |
adj. 振耳欲聋的, 极喧闹的 动词deafen的现在分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 pretext | |
n.借口,托词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 whatsoever | |
adv.(用于否定句中以加强语气)任何;pron.无论什么 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 binds | |
v.约束( bind的第三人称单数 );装订;捆绑;(用长布条)缠绕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 conformity | |
n.一致,遵从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 demonstration | |
n.表明,示范,论证,示威 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 pointed | |
adj.尖的,直截了当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 secondly | |
adv.第二,其次 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 dwelling | |
n.住宅,住所,寓所 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 violation | |
n.违反(行为),违背(行为),侵犯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 galleys | |
n.平底大船,战舰( galley的名词复数 );(船上或航空器上的)厨房 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |