‘THOUGHTS’ and ‘things’ are names for two sorts of object, which common sense will always find contrasted and will always practically oppose to each other. Philosophy, reflecting on the contrast, has varied1 in the past in her explanations of it, and may be expected to vary in the future. At first, ‘spirit and matter,’ ‘soul and body,’ stood for a pair of equipollent substances quite on a par2 in weight and interest. But one day Kant undermined the soul and brought in the transcendental ego3, and ever since then the bipolar relation has been very much off its balance. The transcendental ego seems nowadays in rationalist quarters to stand for everything, in empiricist quarters for almost nothing. In the hands of such writers as Schuppe, Rehmke, Natorp, Munsterberg — at any rate in his earlier writings, Schubert–Soldern and others, the spiritual principle attenuates4 itself to a thoroughly5 ghostly condition, being only a name for the fact that the ‘content’ of experience is known. It loses personal form and activity — these passing over to the content — and becomes a bare Bewusstheit or Bewusstsein uberhaupt of which in its own right absolutely nothing can be said.
I believe that ‘consciousness,’ when once it has evaporated to this estate of pure diaphaneity, is on the point of disappearing altogether. It is the name of a nonentity6, and has no right to a place among first principles. Those who still cling to it are clinging to a mere8 echo, the faint rumor9 left behind by the disappearing ‘soul’ upon the air of philosophy. During the past year, I have read a number of articles whose authors seemed just on the point of abandoning the notion of consciousness,2 and substituting for it that of an absolute experience not due to two factors. But they were not quite radical10 enough, not quite daring enough in their negations. For twenty years past I have mistrusted ‘consciousness’ as an entity7; for seven or eight years past I have suggested its non-existence to my students, and tried to give them its pragmatic equivalent in realities of experience. It seems to me that the hour is ripe for it to be openly and universally discarded.
To deny plumply that ‘consciousness’ exists seems so absurd on the face of it — for undeniably ‘thoughts’ do exist — that I fear some readers will follow me no farther. Let me then immediately explain that I mean only to deny that the word stands for an entity, but to insist most emphatically that it does stand for a function. There is, I mean, no aboriginal12 stuff or quality of being, contrasted with that of which material objects are made, out of which our thoughts of them are made; but there is a function in experience which thoughts perform, and for the performance of which this quality of being is invoked13. That function is knowing. ‘Consciousness’ is supposed necessary to explain the fact that things not only are, but get reported, are known. Whoever blots14 out the notion of consciousness from his list of first principles must still provide in some way for that function’s being carried on.
2 Articles by Bawden, King, Alexander, and others. Dr. Perry is frankly15 over the border
I
My thesis is that if we start with the supposition that there is only one primal16 stuff or material in the world, a stuff of which everything is composed, and if we call that stuff ‘pure experience,’ the knowing can easily be explained as a particular sort of relation towards one another into which portions of pure experience may enter. The relation itself is a part of pure experience; one if its ‘terms’ becomes the subject or bearer of the knowledge, the knower,3 the other becomes the object known. This will need much explanation before it can be understood. The best way to get it understood is to contrast it with the alternative view; and for that we may take the recentest alternative, that in which the evaporation17 of the definite soul-substance has proceeded as far as it can go without being yet complete. If neo-Kantism has expelled earlier forms of dualism, we shall have expelled all forms if we are able to expel neo-kantism in its turn.
3 In my Psychology19 I have tried to show that we need no knower other than the ‘passing thought.’ [Principles of Psychology, vol. I, pp. 338 ff.]
For the thinkers I call neo-Kantian, the word consciousness today does no more than signalize the fact that experience is indefeasibly dualistic in structure. It means that not subject, not object, but object-plus-subject is the minimum that can actually be. The subject-object distinction meanwhile is entirely20 different from that between mind and matter, from that between body and soul. Souls were detachable, had separate destinies; things could happen to them. To consciousness as such nothing can happen, for, timeless itself, it is only a witness of happenings in time, in which it plays no part. It is, in a word, but the logical correlative of ‘content’ in an Experience of which the peculiarity22 is that fact comes to light in it, that awareness23 of content takes place. Consciousness as such is entirely impersonal24 — ‘self’ and its activities belong to the content. To say that I am self-conscious, or conscious of putting forth25 volition26, means only that certain contents, for which ‘self’ and ‘effort of will’ are the names, are not without witness as they occur.
Thus, for these belated drinkers at the Kantian spring, we should have to admit consciousness as an ‘epistemological’ necessity, even if we had no direct evidence of its being there.
But in addition to this, we are supposed by almost every one to have an immediate11 consciousness of consciousness itself. When the world of outer fact ceases to be materially present, and we merely recall it in memory, or fancy it, the consciousness is believed to stand out and to be felt as a kind of impalpable inner flowing, which, once known in this sort of experience, may equally be detected in presentations of the outer world. “The moment we try to fix out attention upon consciousness and to see what, distinctly, it is,” says a recent writer, “it seems to vanish. It seems as if we had before us a mere emptiness. When we try to introspect the sensation of blue, all we can see is the blue; the other element is as if it were diaphanous27. Yet it can be distinguished28, if we look attentively29 enough, and know that there is something to look for.”4 “Consciousness” (Bewusstheit), says another philosopher, “is inexplicable30 and hardly describable, yet all conscious experiences have this in common that what we call their content has a peculiar21 reference to a centre for which ‘self’ is the name, in virtue31 of which reference alone the content is subjectively32 given, or appears. . . . While in this way consciousness, or reference to a self, is the only thing which distinguishes a conscious content from any sort of being that might be there with no one conscious of it, yet this only ground of the distinction defies all closer explanations. The existence of consciousness, although it is the fundamental fact of psychology, can indeed be laid down as certain, can be brought out by analysis, but can neither be defined nor deduced from anything but itself.”5
4 G.E. Moore: Mind, vol. XII, N.S., 1903, p.450.
5 Paul Natorp: Einleitung in die Psychologie, 1888, pp. 14, 112.
‘Can be brought out by analysis,’ this author says. This supposes that the consciousness is one element, moment, factor — call it what you like — of an experience of essentially34 dualistic inner constitution, from which, if you abstract the content, the consciousness will remain revealed to its own eye. Experience, at this rate, would be much like a paint of which the world pictures were made. Paint has a dual18 constitution, involving, as it does, a menstruum 6 (oil, size or what not) and a mass of content in the form of pigment35 suspended therein. We can get the pure menstruum by letting the pigment settle, and the pure pigment by pouring off the size or oil. We operate here by physical subtraction36; and the usual view is, that by mental subtraction we can separate the two factors of experience in an analogous37 way — not isolating38 them entirely, but distinguishing them enough to know that they are two.
6 “Figuratively speaking, consciousness may be said to be the one universal solvent39, or menstruum, in which the different concrete kinds of psychic40 acts and facts are contained, whether in concealed41 or in obvious form.” G.T.Ladd: Psychology, Descriptive and Explanatory, 1894, p.30.
II
Now my contention42 is exactly the reverse of this. Experience, I believe, has no such inner duplicity; and the separation of it into consciousness and content comes, not by way of subtraction, but by way of addition — the addition, to a given concrete piece of it, other sets of experiences, in connection with which severally its use or function may be of two different kinds. The paint will also serve here as an illustration. In a pot in a paint-shop, along with other paints, it serves in its entirety as so much saleable matter. Spread on a canvas, with other paints around it, it represents, on the contrary, a feature in a picture and performs a spiritual function. Just so, I maintain, does a given undivided portion of experience, taken in one context of associates, play the part of a knower, of a state of mind, of ‘consciousness’; while in a different context the same undivided bit of experience plays the part of a thing known, of an objective ‘content.’ In a word, in one group it figures as a thought, in another group as a thing. And, since it can figure in both groups simultaneously43 we have every right to speak of it as subjective33 and objective, both at once. The dualism connoted by such double-barrelled terms as ‘experience,’ ‘phenomenon,’ ‘datum44,’ ‘Vorfindung’ — terms which, in philosophy at any rate, tend more and more to replace the single-barrelled terms of ‘thought’ and ‘thing’ — that dualism, I say, is still preserved in this account, but reinterpreted, so that, instead of being mysterious and elusive45, it becomes verifiable and concrete. It is an affair of relations, it falls outside, not inside, the single experience considered, and can always be particularized and defined.
The entering wedge for this more concrete way of understanding the dualism was fashioned by Locke when he made the word ‘idea’ stand indifferently for thing and thought, and by Berkeley when he said that what common sense means by realities is exactly what the philosopher means by ideas. Neither Locke nor Berkeley thought his truth out into perfect clearness, but it seems to me that the conception I am defending does little more than consistently carry out the ‘pragmatic’ method which they were the first to use.
If the reader will take his own experiences, he will see what I mean. Let him begin with a perceptual experience, the ‘presentation,’ so called, of a physical object, his actual field of vision, the room he sits in, with the book he is reading as its centre; and let him for the present treat this complex object in the common-sense way as being ‘really’ what it seems to be, namely, a collection of physical things cut out from an environing world of other physical things with which these physical things have actual or potential relations. Now at the same time it is just those self-same things which his mind, as we say, perceives; and the whole philosophy of perception from Democritus’s time downwards47 has just been one long wrangle48 over the paradox49 that what is evidently one reality should be in two places at once, both in outer space and in a person’s mind. ‘Representative’ theories of perception avoid the logical paradox, but on the other hand the violate the reader’s sense of life, which knows no intervening mental image but seems to see the room and the book immediately just as they physically50 exist.
The puzzle of how the one identical room can be in two places is at bottom just the puzzle of how one identical point can be on two lines. It can, if it be situated51 at their intersection52; and similarly, if the ‘pure experience’ of the room were a place of intersection of two processes, which connected it with different groups of associates respectively, it could be counted twice over, as belonging to either group, and spoken of loosely as existing in two places, although it would remain all the time a numerically single thing.
Well, the experience is a member of diverse processes that can be followed away from it along entirely different lines. The one self-identical thing has so many relations to the rest of experience that you can take it in disparate systems of association, and treat it as belonging with opposite contexts. In one of these contexts it is your ‘field of consciousness’; in another it is ‘the room in which you sit,’ and it enters both contexts in its wholeness, giving no pretext54 for being said to attach itself to consciousness by one of its parts or aspects, and to out reality by another. What are the two processes, now, into which the room-experience simultaneously enters in this way?
One of them is the reader’s personal biography, the other is the history of the house of which the room is part. The presentation, the experience, the that in short (for until we have decided55 what it is it must be a mere that) is the last term in a train of sensations, emotions, decisions, movements, classifications, expectations, etc., ending in the present, and the first term in a series of ‘inner’ operations extending into the future, on the reader’s part. On the other hand, the very same that is the terminus ad quem of a lot of previous physical operations, carpentering, papering, furnishing, warming, etc., and the terminus a quo of a lot of future ones, in which it will be concerned when undergoing the destiny of a physical room. The physical and the mental operations form curiously56 incompatible57 groups. As a room, the experience has occupied that spot and had that environment for thirty years. As your field of consciousness it may never have existed until now. As a room, attention will go on to discover endless new details in it. As your mental state merely, few new ones will emerge under attention’s eye. AS a room, it will taken an earthquake, or a gang of men, and in any case a certain amount of time, to destroy it. As your subjective state, the closing of your eyes, or any instantaneous play of your fancy will suffice. IN the real world, fire will consume it. IN your mind, you can let fire play over it without effect. As an outer object, you must pay so much a month to inhabit it. As an inner content, you may occupy it for any length of time rent-free. If, in short, you follow it in the mental direction, taking it along with events of personal biography solely58, all sorts of things are true of it which are false, and false of it which are true if you treat it as a real thing experienced, follow it in the physical direction, and relate it to associates in the outer world.
III
So far, all seems plain sailing, but my thesis will probably grow less plausible59 to the reader when I pass form percepts to concepts, or from the case of things presented to that of things remote. I believe, nevertheless, that here also the same law holds good. If we take conceptual manifolds, or memories, or fancies, they also are in their first intention mere bits of pure experience, and, as such, are single thats which act in one context as objects, and in another context figure as mental states. By taking them in their first intention, I mean ignoring their relation to possible perceptual experiences with which they may be connected, which they may lead to and terminate in, and which then they may be supposed to ‘represent.’ Taking them in this way first, we confine the problem to a world merely ‘thought-of’ and not directly felt or seen. This world, just like the world of percepts, comes to us at first as a chaos60 of experiences, but lines of order soon get traced. We find that any bit of it which we may cut out as an example is connected with distinct groups of associates, just as our perceptual experiences are, that these associates link themselves with it by different relations,7 and that one forms the inner history of a person, while the other acts as an impersonal ‘objective’ world, either spatial61 and temporal, or else merely logical or mathematical, or otherwise ‘ideal.’
7 Here as elsewhere the relations are of course experienced relations, members of the same originally chaotic62 manifold of non-perceptual experience of which the related terms themselves are parts.
The first obstacle on the part of the reader to seeing that these non-perceptual experiences have objectivity as well as subjectivity63 will probably be due to the intrusion into his mind of percepts, that third group of associates with which the non-perceptual experiences have relations, and which, as a whole, they ‘represent,’ standing46 to them as thoughts to things. This important function of non-perceptual experiences complicates64 the question and confuses it; for, so used are we to treat percepts as the sole genuine realities that, unless we keep them out of the discussion, we tend altogether to overlook the objectivity that lies in non-perceptual experiences by themselves. We treat them, ‘knowing’ percepts as they do, as through and through subjective, and say that they are wholly constituted of the stuff called consciousness, using this term now for a kind of entity, after the fashion which I am seeking to refute.8
8 Of the representative functions of non-perceptual experience as a whole, I will say a word in a subsequent article; it leads too far into the general theory of knowledge for much to be said about it in a short paper like this.
Abstracting, then, from percepts altogether, what I maintain is, that any single non-perceptual experience tends to get counted twice over, just as a perceptual experience does, figuring in one context as an object or field of objects, in another as a state of mind: and all this without the least internal self-diremption on its own part into consciousness and content. It is all consciousness in one taking; and, in the other, all content.
I find this objectivity of non-perceptual experiences, this complete parallelism in point of reality between the presently felt and the remotely thought, so well set forth in a page of Munsterberg’s Grundzuge, that I will quote it as it stands.
“I may only think of my objects,” says Professor Munsterberg; “yet, in my living thought they stand before me exactly as perceived objects would do, no matter how different the two ways of apprehending65 them may be in their genesis. The book here lying on the table before me, and the book in the next room of which I think and which I mean to get, are both in the same sense given realities for me, realities which I acknowledge and of which I take account. If you agree that the perceptual object is not an idea within me, but that percept and thing, as indistinguishably one, are really experienced there, outside, you ought not to believe that the merely thought-of object is hid away inside of the thinking subject. The object of which I think, and of whose existence I take cognizance without letting it now work upon my senses, occupies its definite place in the outer world as much as does the object which I directly see.”
“What is true of the here and the there, is also true of the now and the then. I know of the thing which is present and perceived, but I know also of the thing which yesterday was but is no more, and which I only remember. Both can determine my present conduct, both are parts of the reality of which I keep account. It is true that of much of the past I am uncertain, just as I am uncertain of much of what is present if it be but dimly perceived. But the interval66 of time does not in principle alter my relation to the object, does not transform it from an object known into a mental state. . . . The things in the room here which I survey, and those in my distant home of which I think, the things of this minute and those of my long-vanished boyhood, influence and decide me alike, with a reality which my experience of them directly feels. They both make up my real world, they make it directly, they do not have first to be introduced to me and mediated67 by ideas which now and here arise within me. . . . This not-me character of my recollections and expectations does not imply that the external objects of which I am aware in those experiences should necessarily be there also for others. The objects of dreamers and hallucinated persons are wholly without general validity. But even were they centaurs69 and golden mountains, they still would be ‘off there,’ in fairy land, and not ‘inside’ of ourselves.”9
9 Munsterberg: Grundzuge der Psychologie, vol. I, p. 48.
This certainly is the immediate, primary, naif, or practical way of taking our thought-of world. Were there no perceptual world to serve as its ‘reductive,’ in Taine’s sense, by being ‘stronger’ and more genuinely ‘outer’ (so that the whole merely thought-of world seems weak and inner in comparison), our world of thought would be the only world, and would enjoy complete reality in our belief. This actually happens in our dreams, and in our day-dreams so long as percepts do not interrupt them.
And yet, just as the seen room (to go back to our late example) is also a field of consciousness, so the conceived or recollected70 room is also a state of mind; and the doubling-up of the experience has in both cases similar grounds.
The room thought-of, namely, has many thought-of couplings with many thought-of things. Some of these couplings are inconstant, others are stable. In the reader’s personal history the room occupies a single date — he saw it only once perhaps, a year ago. Of the house’s history, on the other hand, it forms a permanent ingredient. Some couplings have the curious stubbornness, to borrow Royce’s term, of fact; others show the fluidity of fancy — we let them come and go as we please. Grouped with the rest of its house, with the name of its town, of its owner, builder, value, decorative71 plan, the room maintains a definite foothold, to which, if we try to loosen it, it tends to return and to reassert itself with force.10 With these associates, in a word, it coheres72, while to other houses, other towns, other owners, etc., it shows no tendency to cohere73 at all. The two collections, first of its cohesive74, and, second, of its loose associates, inevitably75 come to be contrasted. We call the first collection the system of external realities, in the midst of which the room, as ‘real,’ exists; the other we call the stream of internal thinking, in which, as a ‘mental image,’ it for a moment floats.11 The room thus again gets counted twice over. It plays two different roles, being Gedanke and Gedachtes, the thought-of-an-object, and the object-thought-of, both in one; and all this without paradox or mystery, just as the same material thing may be both low and high, or small and great, or bad and good, because of its relations to opposite parts of an environing world.
10 Cf. A.L. Hodder: The Adversaries76 of the Sceptic, pp.94–99.
11 For simplicity’s sake I confine my exposition to ‘external’ reality. But there is also the system of ideal reality in which the room plays its part. Relations of comparison, of classification, serial77 order, value, also are stubborn, assign a definite place to the room, unlike the incoherence of its places in the mere rhapsody of our successive thoughts.
As ‘subjective’ we say that the experience represents; as ‘objective’ it is represented. What represents and what is represented is here numerically the same; but we must remember that no dualism of being represented and representing resides in the experience per se. In its pure state, or when isolated78, there is no self-splitting of it into consciousness and what the consciousness is ‘of’. Its subjectivity and objectivity are functional79 attributes solely, realized only when the experience is ‘take,’ i.e., talked-of, twice, considered along with its two differing contexts respectively, by a new retrospective experience, of which that whole past complication now forms the fresh content.
The instant field of the present is at all times what I call the ‘pure’ experience. It is only virtually or potentially either object or subject as yet. For the time being, it is plain, unqualified actuality, or existence, a simple that. In this naif immediacy it is of course valid68; it is there, we act upon it; and the doubling of it in retrospection into a state of mind and a reality intended thereby81, is just one of the acts. The ‘state of mind,’ first treated explicitly82 as such in retrospection, will stand corrected or confirmed, and the retrospective experience in its turn will get a similar treatment; but the immediate experience in its passing is always ‘truth,’12 practical truth, something to act on, at its own movement. If the world were then and there to go out like a candle, it would remain truth absolute and objective, for it would be ‘the last word,’ would have no critic, and no one would ever oppose the thought in it to the reality intended.13
12 Note the ambiguity83 of this term, which is taken sometimes objectively and sometimes subjectively.
13 In the Psychological Review for July 1904, Dr. R.B.Perry has published a view of Consciousness which comes nearer to mine than any other with which I am acquainted. At present, Dr. Perry thinks, every field of experience is so much ‘fact.’ It becomes ‘opinion’ or ‘thought’ only in retrospection, when a fresh experience, thinking the same object, alters and corrects it. But the corrective experience becomes itself in turn corrected, and thus the experience as a whole is a process in which what is objective originally forever turns subjective, turns into our apprehension84 of the object. I strongly recommend Dr. Perry’s admirable article to my readers.
I think I may now claim to have made my thesis clear. Consciousness connotes a kind of external relation, and does not denote a special stuff or way of being. The peculiarity of our experiences, that they not only are, but are known, which their ‘conscious’ quality is invoked to explain, is better explained by their relations — these relations themselves being experiences — to one another.
IV
Were I now to go on to treat of the knowing of perceptual by conceptual experiences, it would again prove to be an affair of external relations. One experience would be the knower, the other the reality known; and I could perfectly85 well define, without the notion of ‘consciousness,’ what the knowing actually and practically amounts to — leading-towards, namely, and terminating-in percepts, through a series of transitional experiences which the world supplies. But I will not treat of this, space being insufficient86.14 I will rather consider a few objections that are sure to be urged against the entire theory as it stands.
14 I have given a partial account of the matter in Mind, vol. X, p. 27, 1885, and in the Psychological Review, vol. II, p. 105, 1895. See also C.A. Strong’s article in the Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, vol I, p. 253, May 12, 1904. I hope myself very soon to recur87 to the matter.
V
First of all, this will be asked: “If experience has not ‘conscious’ existence, if it be not partly made of ‘consciousness,’ of what then is it made? Matter we know, and thought we know, and conscious content we know, but neutral and simple ‘pure experience’ is something we know not at all. Say what it consists of — for it must consist of something — or be willing to give it up!”
To this challenge the reply is easy. Although for fluency’s sake I myself spoke53 early in this article of a stuff of pure experience, I have now to say that there is no general stuff of which experience at large is made. There are as many stuffs as there are ‘natures’ in the things experienced. If you ask what any one bit of pure experience is made of, the answer is always the same: “It is made of that, of just what appears, of space, of intensity88, of flatness, brownness, heaviness, or what not.” Shadworth Hodgson’s analysis here leaves nothing to be desired. Experience is only a collective name for all these sensible natures, and save for time and space (and, if you like, for ‘being’) there appears no universal element of which all things are made.
VI
The next objection is more formidable, in fact it sounds quite crushing when one hears it first.
“If it be the self-same piece of pure experience, taken twice over, that serves now as thought and now as thing” — so the objection runs — “how comes it that its attributes should differ so fundamentally in the two takings. As thing, the experience is extended; as thought, it occupies no space or place. As thing, it is red, hard, heavy; but who ever heard of a red, hard or heavy thought? Yet even now you said that an experience is made of just what appears, and what appears is just such adjectives. How can the one experience in its thing-function be made of them, consist of them, carry them as its own attributes, while in its thought-function it disowns them and attributes them elsewhere. There is a self-contradiction here from which the radical dualism of thought and thing is the only truth that can save us. Only if the thought is one kind of being can the adjectives exist in it ‘intentionally’ (to use the scholastic89 term); only if the thing is another kind, can they exist in it constituitively and energetically. No simple subject can take the same adjectives and at one time be qualified80 by it, and at another time be merely ‘of’ it, as of something only meant or known.”
The solution insisted on by this objector, like many other common-sense solutions, grows the less satisfactory the more one turns it in one’s mind. To begin with, are thought and thing as heterogeneous90 as is commonly said?
No one denies that they have some categories in common. Their relations to time are identical. Both, moreover, may have parts (for psychologists n general treat thoughts as having them); and both may be complex or simple. Both are of kinds, can be compared, added and subtracted and arranged in serial orders. All sorts of adjectives qualify our thoughts which appear incompatible with consciousness, being as such a bare diaphaneity. For instance, they are natural and easy, or laborious91. They are beautiful, happy, intense, interesting, wise, idiotic92, focal, marginal, insipid93, confused, vague, precise, rational, causal, general, particular, and many things besides. Moreover, the chapters on ‘Perception’ in the psychology-books are full of facts that make for the essential homogeneity of thought with thing. How, if ‘subject’ and ‘object’ were separated ‘by the whole diameter of being,’ and had no attributes and common, could it be so hard to tell, in a presented and recognized material object, what part comes in thought the sense-organs and what part comes ‘out of one’s own head’? Sensations and apperceptive ideas fuse here so intimately that you can no more tell where one begins and the other ends, than you can tell, in those cunning circular panoramas94 that have lately been exhibited, where the real foreground and the painted canvas join together.15
15 Spencer’s proof of his ‘Transfigured Realism’ (his doctrine95 that there is an absolutely non-mental reality) comes to mind as a splendid instance of the impossibility of establishing radical heterogeneity96 between thought and thing. All his painfully accumulated points of difference run gradually into their opposites, and are full of exceptions.
Descartes for the first time defined thought as the absolutely unextended, and later philosophers have accepted the description as correct. But what possible meaning has it to say that, when we think of a foot-rule or a square yard, extension is not attributable to our thought? Of every extended object the adequate mental picture must have all the extension of the object itself. The difference between objective and subjective extension is one of relation to a context solely. In the mind the various extents maintain no necessarily stubborn order relatively98 to each other, while in the physical world they bound each other stably, and, added together, make the great enveloping99 Unit which we believe in and call real Space. As ‘outer,’ they carry themselves adversely100, so to speak, to one another, exclude one another and maintain their distances; while, as ‘inner,’ their order is loose, and they form a durcheinander in which unity101 is lost.16 But to argue from this that inner experience is absolutely inextensive seems to me little short of absurd. The two worlds differ, not by the presence or absence of extension, but by the relations of the extensions which in both worlds exist.
16
Does not this case of extension now put us on the track of truth in the case of other qualities? It does; and I am surprised that the facts should not have been noticed long ago. Why, for example, do we call a fire hot, and water wet, and yet refuse to say that our mental state, when it is ‘of’ these objects, is either wet or hot? ‘Intentionally,’ at any rate, and when the mental state is a vivid image, hotness and wetness are in it just as much as they are in the physical experience. The reason is this, that, as the general chaos of all our experiences gets sifted102, we find that there are some fires that will always burn sticks and always warm our bodies, and that there are some waters that will always put out fires; while there are other fires and waters that will not act at all. The general group of experiences that act, that do not only possess their natures intrinsically, but wear them adjectively and energetically, turning them against one another, comes inevitably to be contrasted with the group whose members, having identically the same natures, fail to manifest them in the ‘energetic’ way.17 I make for myself now an experience of blazing fire; I place it near my body; but it does not warm me in the least. I lay a stick upon it, and the stick either burns or remains103 green, as I please. I call up water, and pour it on the fire, and absolutely no difference ensues. I account for all such facts by calling this whole train of experiences unreal, a mental train. Mental fire is what won’t burn real sticks; mental water is what won’t necessarily (though of course it may) put out even a mental fire. Mental knives may be sharp, but they won’t cut real wood. Mental triangles are pointed104, but their points won’t wound. With ‘real’ objects, on the contrary, consequences always accrue105; and thus the real experiences get sifted from the mental ones, the things from out thoughts of them, fanciful or true, and precipitated106 together as the stable part of the whole experience-chaos, under the name of the physical world. Of this our perceptual experiences are the nucleus107, they being the originally strong experiences. We add a lot of conceptual experiences to them, making these strong also in imagination, and building out the remoter parts of the physical world by their means; and around this core of reality the world of laxly connected fancies and mere rhapsodical objects floats like a bank of clouds. In the clouds, all sorts of rules are violated which in the core are kept. Extensions there can be indefinitely located; motion there obeys no Newton’s laws.
17
VII
There is a peculiar class of experience to which, whether we take them as subjective or as objective, we assign their several natures as attributes, because in both contexts they affect their associates actively108, though in neither quite as ‘strongly’ or as sharply as things affect one another by their physical energies. I refer here to appreciations109, which form an ambiguous sphere of being, belonging with emotion on the one hand, and having objective ‘value’ on the other, yet seeming not quite inner nor quite outer, as if a diremption had begun but had not made itself complete.
Experiences of painful objects, for example, are usually also painful experiences; perceptions of loveliness, of ugliness, tend to pass muster110 as lovely or as ugly perceptions; intuitions of the morally lofty are lofty intuitions. Sometimes the adjective wanders as if uncertain where to fix itself. Shall we speak of seductive visions or of visions of seductive things? Of healthy thoughts or of thoughts of healthy objects? Of good impulses, or of impulses towards the good? Of feelings of anger, or of angry feelings? Both in the mind and in the thing, these natures modify their context, exclude certain associates and determine others, have their mates and incompatibles. Yet not as stubbornly as in the case of physical qualities, for beauty and ugliness, love and hatred111, pleasant and painful can, in certain complex experiences, coexist.
If one were to make an evolutionary112 construction of how a lot of originally chaotic pure experience became gradually differentiated113 into an orderly inner and outer world, the whole theory would turn upon one’s success in explaining how or why the quality of an experience, once active, could become less so, and, from being an energetic attribute in some cases, elsewhere lapse114 into the status of an inert115 or merely internal ‘nature.’ This would be the ‘evolution’ of the psychical116 from the bosom117 of the physical, in which the esthetic118, moral and otherwise emotional experiences would represent a halfway119 stage.
VIII
But a last cry of non possumus will probably go up from many readers. “All very pretty as a piece of ingenuity,” they will say, “but our consciousness itself intuitively contradicts you. We, for our part, know that we are conscious. We feel our thought, flowing as a life within us, in absolute contrast with the objects which it so unremittingly escorts. We can not be faithless to this immediate intuition. The dualism is a fundamental datum: Let no man join what God has put asunder120.”
My reply to this is my last word, and I greatly grieve that to many it will sound materialistic121. I can not help that, however, for I, too, have my intuitions and I must obey them. Let the case be what it may in others, I am as confident as I am of anything that, in myself, the stream of thinking (which I recognize emphatically as a phenomenon) is only a careless name for what, when scrutinized122, reveals itself to consist chiefly of the stream of my breathing. The ‘I think’ which Kant said must be able to accompany all my objects, is the ‘I breath’ which actually does accompany them. There are other internal facts besides breathing (intracephalic muscular adjustments, etc., of which I have said a word in my larger Psychology), and these increase the assets of ‘consciousness,’ so far as the latter is subject to immediate perception; but breath, which was ever the original of ‘spirit,’ breath moving outwards123, between the glottis and the nostrils124, is, I am persuaded, the essence out of which philosophers have constructed the entity known to them as consciousness. That entity is fictitious125, while thoughts in the concrete are fully97 real. But thoughts in the concrete are made of the same stuff as things are.
I wish I might believe myself to have made that plausible in this article. IN another article I shall try to make the general notion of a world composed of pure experiences still more clear.
1 varied | |
adj.多样的,多变化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 par | |
n.标准,票面价值,平均数量;adj.票面的,平常的,标准的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 ego | |
n.自我,自己,自尊 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 attenuates | |
v.(使)变细( attenuate的第三人称单数 );(使)变薄;(使)变小;减弱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 thoroughly | |
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 nonentity | |
n.无足轻重的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 entity | |
n.实体,独立存在体,实际存在物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 rumor | |
n.谣言,谣传,传说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 radical | |
n.激进份子,原子团,根号;adj.根本的,激进的,彻底的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 aboriginal | |
adj.(指动植物)土生的,原产地的,土著的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 invoked | |
v.援引( invoke的过去式和过去分词 );行使(权利等);祈求救助;恳求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 blots | |
污渍( blot的名词复数 ); 墨水渍; 错事; 污点 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 frankly | |
adv.坦白地,直率地;坦率地说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 primal | |
adj.原始的;最重要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 evaporation | |
n.蒸发,消失 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 dual | |
adj.双的;二重的,二元的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 psychology | |
n.心理,心理学,心理状态 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 peculiarity | |
n.独特性,特色;特殊的东西;怪癖 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 awareness | |
n.意识,觉悟,懂事,明智 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 impersonal | |
adj.无个人感情的,与个人无关的,非人称的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 volition | |
n.意志;决意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 diaphanous | |
adj.(布)精致的,半透明的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 attentively | |
adv.聚精会神地;周到地;谛;凝神 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 inexplicable | |
adj.无法解释的,难理解的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 subjectively | |
主观地; 臆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 subjective | |
a.主观(上)的,个人的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 pigment | |
n.天然色素,干粉颜料 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 subtraction | |
n.减法,减去 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 analogous | |
adj.相似的;类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 isolating | |
adj.孤立的,绝缘的v.使隔离( isolate的现在分词 );将…剔出(以便看清和单独处理);使(某物质、细胞等)分离;使离析 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 solvent | |
n.溶剂;adj.有偿付能力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 psychic | |
n.对超自然力敏感的人;adj.有超自然力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 concealed | |
a.隐藏的,隐蔽的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 contention | |
n.争论,争辩,论战;论点,主张 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 simultaneously | |
adv.同时发生地,同时进行地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 datum | |
n.资料;数据;已知数 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 elusive | |
adj.难以表达(捉摸)的;令人困惑的;逃避的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 standing | |
n.持续,地位;adj.永久的,不动的,直立的,不流动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 downwards | |
adj./adv.向下的(地),下行的(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 wrangle | |
vi.争吵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 paradox | |
n.似乎矛盾却正确的说法;自相矛盾的人(物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 physically | |
adj.物质上,体格上,身体上,按自然规律 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 situated | |
adj.坐落在...的,处于某种境地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 intersection | |
n.交集,十字路口,交叉点;[计算机] 交集 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 spoke | |
n.(车轮的)辐条;轮辐;破坏某人的计划;阻挠某人的行动 v.讲,谈(speak的过去式);说;演说;从某种观点来说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 pretext | |
n.借口,托词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 decided | |
adj.决定了的,坚决的;明显的,明确的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 curiously | |
adv.有求知欲地;好问地;奇特地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 incompatible | |
adj.不相容的,不协调的,不相配的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 plausible | |
adj.似真实的,似乎有理的,似乎可信的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 chaos | |
n.混乱,无秩序 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 spatial | |
adj.空间的,占据空间的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 chaotic | |
adj.混沌的,一片混乱的,一团糟的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 subjectivity | |
n.主观性(主观主义) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 complicates | |
使复杂化( complicate的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 apprehending | |
逮捕,拘押( apprehend的现在分词 ); 理解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 interval | |
n.间隔,间距;幕间休息,中场休息 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 mediated | |
调停,调解,斡旋( mediate的过去式和过去分词 ); 居间促成; 影响…的发生; 使…可能发生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 valid | |
adj.有确实根据的;有效的;正当的,合法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 centaurs | |
n.(希腊神话中)半人半马怪物( centaur的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 recollected | |
adj.冷静的;镇定的;被回忆起的;沉思默想的v.记起,想起( recollect的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 decorative | |
adj.装饰的,可作装饰的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 coheres | |
v.黏合( cohere的第三人称单数 );联合;结合;(指看法、推理等)前后一致 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 cohere | |
vt.附着,连贯,一致 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 cohesive | |
adj.有粘着力的;有结合力的;凝聚性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 inevitably | |
adv.不可避免地;必然发生地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 adversaries | |
n.对手,敌手( adversary的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 serial | |
n.连本影片,连本电视节目;adj.连续的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 isolated | |
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 functional | |
adj.为实用而设计的,具备功能的,起作用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 qualified | |
adj.合格的,有资格的,胜任的,有限制的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 explicitly | |
ad.明确地,显然地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 ambiguity | |
n.模棱两可;意义不明确 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 apprehension | |
n.理解,领悟;逮捕,拘捕;忧虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 insufficient | |
adj.(for,of)不足的,不够的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 recur | |
vi.复发,重现,再发生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 intensity | |
n.强烈,剧烈;强度;烈度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 scholastic | |
adj.学校的,学院的,学术上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 heterogeneous | |
adj.庞杂的;异类的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 laborious | |
adj.吃力的,努力的,不流畅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 idiotic | |
adj.白痴的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 insipid | |
adj.无味的,枯燥乏味的,单调的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 panoramas | |
全景画( panorama的名词复数 ); 全景照片; 一连串景象或事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 heterogeneity | |
n.异质性;多相性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 relatively | |
adv.比较...地,相对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 enveloping | |
v.包围,笼罩,包住( envelop的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 adversely | |
ad.有害地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 unity | |
n.团结,联合,统一;和睦,协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 sifted | |
v.筛( sift的过去式和过去分词 );筛滤;细查;详审 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 pointed | |
adj.尖的,直截了当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 accrue | |
v.(利息等)增大,增多 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 precipitated | |
v.(突如其来地)使发生( precipitate的过去式和过去分词 );促成;猛然摔下;使沉淀 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 nucleus | |
n.核,核心,原子核 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 actively | |
adv.积极地,勤奋地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 appreciations | |
n.欣赏( appreciation的名词复数 );感激;评定;(尤指土地或财产的)增值 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 muster | |
v.集合,收集,鼓起,激起;n.集合,检阅,集合人员,点名册 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 hatred | |
n.憎恶,憎恨,仇恨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 evolutionary | |
adj.进化的;演化的,演变的;[生]进化论的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 differentiated | |
区分,区别,辨别( differentiate的过去式和过去分词 ); 区别对待; 表明…间的差别,构成…间差别的特征 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 lapse | |
n.过失,流逝,失效,抛弃信仰,间隔;vi.堕落,停止,失效,流逝;vt.使失效 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 inert | |
adj.无活动能力的,惰性的;迟钝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 psychical | |
adj.有关特异功能现象的;有关特异功能官能的;灵魂的;心灵的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 bosom | |
n.胸,胸部;胸怀;内心;adj.亲密的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 esthetic | |
adj.美学的,审美的;悦目的,雅致的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 halfway | |
adj.中途的,不彻底的,部分的;adv.半路地,在中途,在半途 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 asunder | |
adj.分离的,化为碎片 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 materialistic | |
a.唯物主义的,物质享乐主义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 scrutinized | |
v.仔细检查,详审( scrutinize的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 outwards | |
adj.外面的,公开的,向外的;adv.向外;n.外形 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 nostrils | |
鼻孔( nostril的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 fictitious | |
adj.虚构的,假设的;空头的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |