IT is difficult not to notice a curious unrest in the philosophic1 atmosphere of the time, always loosening of old landmarks2, a softening3 of oppositions4, a mutual5 borrowing from one another reflecting on the part of systems anciently closed, and an interest in new suggestions, however vague, as if the one thing sure were the inadequacy7 of the extant school-solutions. The dissatisfaction with these seems due for the most part to a feeling that they are too abstract and academic. Life is confused and superabundant, and what the younger generation appears to crave8 is more of the temperament9 of life in its philosophy, even thought it were at some cost of logical rigor11 and of formal purity. Transcendental idealism is inclining to let the world wag incomprehensibly, in spite of its Absolute Subject and his unity12 of purpose. Berkeleyan idealism is abandoning the principle of parsimony13 and dabbling14 in panpsychic speculations15. Empiricism flirts16 with teleology17; and, strangest of all, natural realism, so long decently buried, raises its head above the turf, and finds glad hands outstretched from the most unlikely quarters to help it to its feet again. We are all biased18 by our personal feelings, I know, and I am personally discontented with extant solutions; so I seem to read the signs of a great unsettlement, as if the upheaval19 of more real conceptions and more fruitful methods were imminent20, as if a true landscape might result, less clipped, straight-edged and artificial.
If philosophy be really on the eve of any considerable rearrangement, the time should be propitious21 for any one who has suggestions of his own to bring forward. For many years past my mind has bee growing into a certain type of Weltanschauung. Rightly or wrongly, I have got to the point where I can hardly see things in any other pattern. I propose, therefore, to describe the pattern as clearly as I can consistently with great brevity, and to throw my description into the bubbling vat22 of publicity23 where, jostled by rivals and torn by critics, it will eventually either disappear from notice, or else, if better luck befall it, quietly subside25 to the profundities26, and serve as a possible ferment27 of new growths or a nucleus28 of new crystallization.
I. Radical29 Empiricism
I give the name of ‘radical empiricism’ to my Weltanschauung. Empiricism is known as the opposite of rationalism. Rationalism tends to emphasize universals and to make wholes prior to parts in the order of logic10 as well as in that of being. Empiricism, on the contrary, lays the explanatory stress upon the part, the element, the individual, and treats the whole as a collection and the universal as an abstraction. My description of things, accordingly, starts with the parts and makes of the whole a being of the second order. It is essentially30 a mosaic31 philosophy, a philosophy of plural32 facts, like that of Hume and his descendants, who refer these facts neither to Substances in which they inhere nor to an Absolute Mind that creates them as its objects. But it differs from the Humian type of empiricism in one particular which makes me add the epithet33 radical.
To be radical, an empiricism must neither admit into its constructions any element that is not directly experienced, nor exclude from them any element that is directly experienced. For such a philosophy, the relations that connect experiences must themselves be experienced relations, and any kind of relation experienced must be accounted as ‘real’ as anything else in the system. Elements may indeed be redistributed, the original placing of things getting corrected, but a real place must be found for every kind of thing experienced, whether term or relation, in the final philosophic arrangement.
Now, ordinary empiricism, in spite of the fact that conjunctive and disjunctive relations present themselves as being fully34 co-ordinate parts of experience, has always shown a tendency to do away with the connections of things, and to insist most on the disjunctions. Berkeley’s nominalism, Hume’s statement that whatever things we distinguish are as ‘loose and separate’ as if they had ‘no manner of connection.’ James Mill’s denial that similars have anything ‘really’ in common, the resolution of the causal tie into habitual35 sequence, John Mill’s account of both physical things and selves as composed of discontinuous possibilities, and the general pulverization36 of all Experience by association and the mind-dust theory, are examples of what I mean.
The natural result of such a world-picture has been the efforts of rationalism to correct its incoherencies by the addition of trans-experiential agents of unification, substances, intellectual categories and powers, or Selves; whereas, if empiricism had only been radical and taken everything that comes without disfavor, conjunction as well as separation, each at its face value, the results would have called for no such artificial correction. Radical empiricism, as I understand it, does full justice to conjunctive relations, without, however, treating them as rationalism always tends to treat them, as being true in some supernal38 way, as if the unity of things and their variety belonged to different orders of truth and vitality39 altogether.
II. Conjunctive Relations
Relations are of different degrees of intimacy40. Merely to be ‘with’ one another in a universe of discourse42 is the most external relation that terms can have, and seems to involve nothing whatever as to farther consequences. Simultaneity and time-interval come next, and then space-adjacency and distance. After them, similarity and difference, carrying the possibility of many inferences. Then relations of activity, tying terms into series involving change, tendency, resistance, and the causal order generally. Finally, the relation experienced between terms that form states of mind, and are immediately conscious of continuing each other. The organization of the Self as a system of memories, purposes, strivings, fulfilments or disappointments, is incidental to this most intimate of all relations, the terms of which seem in many cases actually to compenetrate and suffuse44 each other’s being.
Philosophy has always turned on grammatical particles. With, near, next, like, from, towards, against, because, for, through, my — these words designate types of conjunctive relation arranged in a roughly ascending45 order of intimacy and inclusiveness. A priori, we can imagine a universe of withness but no nextness; or one of nextness but no likeness46, or of likeness with no activity, or of activity with no purpose, or of purpose with no ego37. These would be universes, each with its own grade of unity. The universe of human experience is, by one or another of its parts, of each and all these grades. Whether or not it possibly enjoys some still more absolute grade of union does not appear upon the surface.
Taken as it does appear, our universe is to a large extent chaotic47. No one single type of connection runs through all the experiences that compose it. If we take space-relations, they fail to connect minds into any regular system. Causes and purposes obtain only among special series of facts. The self-relation seems extremely limited and does not link two different selves together. Prima facie, if you should liken the universe of absolute idealism to an aquarium48, a crystal globe in which goldfish are swimming, you would have to compare the empiricist universe to something more like one of those dried human heads with which the Dyaks of Borneo deck their lodges49. The skull50 forms a solid nucleus; but innumerable feathers, leaves, strings51, beads52, and loose appendices of every description float and dangle53 from it, and, save that they terminate in it, seem to have nothing to do with one another. Even so my experiences and yours float and dangle, terminating, it is true, in a nucleus of common perception, but for the most part out of sight and irrelevant54 and unimaginable to one another. This imperfect intimacy, this bare relation of withness) between some parts of the sum total of experience and other parts, is the fact that ordinary empiricism over-emphasizes against rationalism, the latter always tending to ignore it unduly55. Radical empiricism, on the contrary, is fair to both the unity and the disconnection. It finds no reason for treating either as illusory. It allots56 to each its definite sphere of description, and agrees that there appear to be actual forces at work which tend, as time goes on, to make the unity greater.
The conjunctive relation that has given most trouble to philosophy is the co-conscious transition, so to call it, by which one experience passes into another when both belong to the same self. My experiences and your experiences are ‘with’ each other in various external ways, but mine pass into mine, and yours pass into yours in a way in which yours and mine never pass into one another. Within each of our personal histories, subject, object, interest and purpose are continuous or may be continuous.18 Personal histories are processes of change in time, and the change itself is one of the things immediately experienced. ‘Change’ in this case means continuous as opposed to discontinuous transition. But continuous transition is one sort of a conjunctive relation; and to be a radical empiricist means to hold fast to this conjunctive relation of all others, for this is the strategic point, the position through which, if a hole be made, all the corruptions58 of dialectics and all the metaphysical fictions pour into our philosophy. The holding fast to this relation means taking it at its face value, neither less nor more; and to take it at its face value means first of all to take it just as we feel it, and not to confuse ourselves with abstract talk about it, involving words that drive us to invent secondary conceptions in order to neutralize59 their suggestions and to make our actual experience again seem rationally possible. what I do feel simply when a later moment of my experience succeeds an earlier one is that though they are two moments, the transition from the one to the other is continuous. Continuity here is a definite sort of experience; just as definite as is the discontinuity-experience which I find it impossible to avoid when I seek to make the transition from an experience of my own to one of yours. In this latter case I have to get on and off again, to pass from a thing lived to another thing only conceived, and the break is positively60 experienced and noted61. Though the functions exerted by my experience and by yours may be the same (.e.g., the same objects known and the same purposes followed), yet the sameness has in this case to be ascertained62 expressly (and often with difficulty and uncertainly) after the break has been felt; whereas in passing from one of my own moments to another the sameness of object and interest is unbroken, and both the earlier and the later experience are of things directly lived.
18 The psychology63 books have of late described the facts here with approximate adequacy. I may refer to the chapters on ‘The Stream of Thought’ and on the Self in my own Principles of Psychology, as well as to S.H.Hodgson’s Metaphysics of Experience, vol I., ch. VII and VIII.
There is no other nature, no other whatness than this absence of break and this sense of continuity in that most intimate of all conjunctive relations, the passing of one experience into another when the belong to the same self. And this whatness is real empirical ‘content,’ just as the whatness of separation and discontinuity is real content in the contrasted case. Practically to experience one’s personal continuum in this living way is to know the originals of the ideas of continuity and sameness, to know what the words stand for concretely, to own all that they can ever mean. But all experiences have their conditions; and over-subtle intellects, thinking about the facts here, and asking how they are possible, have ended by substituting a lot of static objects of conception for the direct perceptual experiences. “Sameness,” they have said, “must be a stark64 numerical identity; it can’t run on from next to next. Continuity can’t mean mere41 absence of gap; for if you say two things are in immediate43 contact, at the contact how can they be two? If, on the other hand, you put a relation of transition between them, that itself is a third thing, and needs to be related or hitched66 to its terms. An infinite series is involved,” and so on. The result is that from difficulty to difficulty, the plain conjunctive experience has been discredited68 by both schools, the empiricists leaving things permanently69 disjoined, and the rationalist remedying the looseness by their Absolutes or Substances, or whatever other fictitious70 agencies of union may have employed. From all which artificiality we can be saved by a couple of simple-reflections: first, that conjunctions and separations are, at all events, co-ordinate phenomena71 which, if we take experiences at their face value, must be accounted equally real; and second, that if we insist on treating things as really separate when they are given as continuously joined, invoking72, when union is required, transcendental principles to overcome the separateness we have assumed, then we ought to stand ready to perform the converse73 act. We ought to invoke74 higher principles of disunion, also, to make our merely experienced disjunctions more truly real. Failing thus, we ought to let the originally given continuities stand on their own bottom. We have no right to be lopsided or to blow capriciously hot and cold.
III. The Cognitive75 Relation
The first great pitfall76 from which such a radical standing77 by experience will save us is an artificial conception of the relations between knower and known. Throughout the history of philosophy the subject and its object have been treated as absolutely discontinuous entities78; and thereupon the presence of the latter to the former, or the ‘apprehension’ by the former of the latter, has assumed a paradoxical character which all sorts of theories had to be invented to overcome. Representative theories put a mental ‘representation,’ ‘image,’ or ‘content’ into the gap, as a sort of intermediary. Common-sense theories left the gap untouched, declaring our mind able to clear it by a self-transcending leap. Transcendentalist theories left it impossible to traverse by finite knowers, and brought an Absolute in to perform the saltatory act. All the while, in the very bosom80 of the finite experience, every conjunction required to make the relation intelligible81 is given in full. Either the knower and the known are:
(1) The self-same piece of experience taken twice over in different contexts; or they are
(2) two pieces of actual experience belonging to the same subject, with definite tracts82 of conjunctive transitional experience between them; or
(3) the known is a possible experience either of that subject or another, to which the said conjunctive transitions would lead, if sufficiently83 prolonged.
To discuss all the ways in which one experience may function as the knower of another, would be incompatible84 with the limits of this essay.19 I have just treated of type 1, the kind of knowledge called perception. This is the type of case in which the mind enjoys direct ‘acquaintance’ with a present object. In the other types the mind has ‘knowledge-about’ an object not immediately there. Of type 2, the simplest sort of conceptual knowledge, I have given some account in two articles.20 Type 3 can always formally and hypothetically be reduced to type 2, so that a brief description of that type will put the present reader sufficiently at my point of view, and make him see what the actual meanings of the mysterious cognitive relation may be.
19 For brevity’s sake I altogether omit mention of the type constituted by knowledge of the truth of general propositions. This type has been thoroughly85 and, so far as I can see, satisfactorily, elucidated86 in Dewey’s Studies in Logical Theory. Such propositions are reducible to the S-is-P form; and the ‘terminus’ that verifies and fulfils is the SP in combination. Of course percepts may be involved in the mediating87 experiences, or in the ‘satisfactoriness’ of the P in its new position.
20 These articles and their doctrine88, unnoticed apparently89 by any one else, have lately gained favorable comment from Professor Strong. Dr. Dickinson S. Miller90 has independently thought out the same results, which Strong accordingly dubs91 the James–Miller theory of cognition.
Suppose me to be sitting here in my library at Cambridge, at ten minutes’ walk from ‘Memorial Hall,’ and to be thinking truly of the latter object. My mind may have before it only the name, or it may have a clear image, or it may have a very dim image of the hall, but such intrinsic differences in the image make no difference in its cognitive function. Certain extrinsic92 phenomena, special experiences of conjunction, are what impart to the image, be it what it may, its knowing office.
For instance, if you ask me what hall I mean by my image, and I call tell you nothing; or if I fail to point or lead you towards the Harvard Delta93; or if, being led by you, I am uncertain whether the Hall I see be what I had in mind or not; you would rightly deny that I had ‘meant’ that particular hall at all, even though my mental image might to some degree have resembled it. The resemblance would count in that case as coincidental merely, for all sorts of things of a kind resemble one another in this world without being held for that reason to take cognizance of one another.
On the other hand, if I can lead you to the hall, and tell you of its history and present uses; if in its presence I feel my idea, however imperfect it may have been, to have led hither and to be now terminated; if the associates of the image and of the felt hall run parallel, so that each term of the one context corresponds serially94, as I walk, with an answering term of the others; why then my soul was prophetic, and my idea must be, and by common consent would be, called cognizant of reality. That percept was what I meant, for into it my idea has passed by conjunctive experiences of sameness and fulfilled intention. Nowhere is there jar, but every later moment continues and corroborates95 an earlier one.
In this continuing and corroborating96, taken in no transcendental sense, but denoting definitely felt transitions, lies all that the knowing of a percept by an idea can possibly contain or signify. Wherever such transitions are felt, the first experience knows that last one. Where they do not, or where even as possibles they can not, intervene, there can be no pretence97 of knowing. In this latter case the extremes will be connected, if connected at all, by inferior relations — bare likeness or succession, or by ‘withness’ alone. Knowledge of sensible realities thus comes to life inside the tissue of experience. It is made; and made by relations that unroll themselves in time. Whenever certain intermediaries are given, such that, as they develop towards their terminus, there is experience from point to point of one direction followed, and finally of one process fulfilled, the result is that their starting-point thereby98 becomes a knower and their terminus an object meant or known. That is all that knowing (in the simple case considered) can be known-as, that is the whole of its nature, put into experiential terms. Whenever such is the sequence of our experiences we may freely say that we had the terminal object ‘in mind’ from the outset, even although at the outset nothing was there in us but a flat piece of substantive99 experience like any other, with no self-transcendency about it, and ny mystery save the mystery of coming into existence and of being gradually followed by other pieces of substantive experience, with conjunctively transitional experiences between. That is what we mean here by the object’s being ‘in mind.’ Of any deeper more real way of being in mind we have no positive conception, and we have no right to discredit67 our actual experience by talking of such a way at all.
I know that many a reader will rebel at this. “Mere intermediaries,” he will say, “even though they be feelings of continuously growing fulfilment, only separate the knower from the known, whereas what we have in knowledge is a kind of immediate touch of the one by the other, an ‘apprehension’ in the etymological100 sense of the word, a leaping of the chasm101 as by lightning, an act by which two terms are smitten102 into one, over the head of their distinctness. All these dead intermediaries of yours are out of each other, and outside of their termini still.”
But do not such dialectic difficulties remind us of the dog dropping his bone and snapping at its image in the water? If we knew any more real kind of union aliunde, we might be entitled to brand all our empirical unions as a sham103. But unions by continuous transition are the only ones we know of, whether in this matter of a knowledge-about that terminates in an acquaintance, whether in personal identity, in logical predication through the copula ‘is,’ or elsewhere. If anywhere there were more absolute unions realized, they could only reveal themselves to us by just such conjunctive results. These are what the unions are worth, these are all that we can ever practically mean by union, by continuity. Is it not time to repeat what Lotze said of substances, that to act like one is to be one? Should we not say here that to be experienced as continuous is to be really continuous, in a world where experience and reality come to the same thing? In a picture gallery a painted hook will serve to hang a painted chain by, a painted cable will hold a painted ship. In a world where both the terms and their distinctions are affairs of experience, conjunctions that are experienced must be at least as real as anything else. They will be ‘absolutely’ real conjunctions, if we have no transphenomenal Absolute ready, to derealize the whole experienced world by, at a stroke. If, on the other hand, we had such an Absolute, not one of our opponents’ theories of knowledge could remain standing any better than ours could; for the distinctions as well as the conjunctions of experience would impartially104 fall its prey105. The whole question of how ‘one’ thing can know ‘another’ would cease to be a real one at all in a world where otherness itself was an illusion.21
21 Mr. Bradley, not professing106 to know his absolute aliunde, nevertheless derealizes Experience by alleging107 it to be everywhere infected with self-contradiction. His arguments seem almost purely108 verbal, but this is no place for arguing that point out.
So much for the essentials of the cognitive relation, where the knowledge is conceptual in type, or forms knowledge ‘about’ an object. It consists in intermediary experiences (possible, if not actual) of continuously developing progress, and, finally, of fulfilment, when the sensible percept, which is the object, is reached. The percept here not only verifies the concept, proves its function of knowing that percept to be true, but the percept’s existence as the terminus of the chain of intermediaries creates the function. Whatever terminates that chain was, because it now proves itself to be, what the concept ‘had in mind.’
The towering importance for human life of this kind of knowing lies in the fact that an experience that knows another can figure as its representative, not in any quasi-miraculous ‘epistemological’ sense, but in the definite practical sense of being its substitute in various operations, sometimes physical and sometimes mental, which lead us to its associates and results. By experimenting on our ideas of reality, we may save ourselves the trouble of experimenting on the real experiences which they severally mean. The ideas form related systems, corresponding point for point to the systems which the realities form; and by letting an ideal term call up its associates systematically109, we may be led to a terminus which the corresponding real term would have led to in case we had operated on the real world. And this brings us to the general question of substitution.
IV. Substitution
In Taine’s brilliant book on ‘Intelligence,’ substitution was for the first time named as a cardinal110 logical function, though of course the facts had always been familiar enough. What, exactly, in a system of experiences, does the ‘substitution’ of one of them for another mean?
According to my view, experience as a whole is a process in time, whereby innumerable particular terms lapse111 and are superseded112 by others that follow upon them by transitions which, whether disjunctive or conjunctive in content, are themselves experiences, and must in general be accounted at least as real as the terms which they relate. What the nature of the event called ‘superseding’ signifies, depends altogether on the kind of transition that obtains. Some experiences simply abolish their predecessors113 without continuing them in any way. Others are felt to increase or to enlarge their meaning, to carry out their purpose, or to bring us nearer to their goal. They ‘represent’ them, and may fulfil their function better than they fulfilled it themselves. But to ‘fulfil a function’ in a world of pure experience can be conceived and defined in only one possible way. IN such a world transitions and arrivals (or terminations) are the only events that happen, though they happen by so many sorts of path. The only experience that one experience can perform is to lead into another experience; and the only fulfilment we can speak of is the reaching of a certain experienced end. When one experience leads to (or can lead to) the same end as another, they agree in function. But the whole system of experiences as they are immediately given presents itself as a quasi-chaos through which one can pass out of an initial term in many directions and yet end in the same terminus, moving from next to next by a great many possible paths.
Either one of these paths might be a functional114 substitute for another, and to follow one rather than another might on occasion be an advantageous115 thing to do. As a matter of fact, and in a general way, the paths that run through conceptual experiences, that is, through ‘thoughts’ or ‘ideas’ that ‘know’ the things in which they terminate, are highly advantageous paths to follow. Not only do they yield inconceivably rapid transitions; but, owing to the ‘universal’ character22 which they frequently possess, and to their capacity for association with one another in great systems, they outstrip116 the tardy117 consecutions of the things themselves, and sweep us on towards our ultimate termini in a far more labor-saving way than the following of trains of sensible perception ever could. Wonderful are the new cuts and the short-circuits which the thought-paths make. Most thought-paths, it is true, are substitutes for nothing actual; they end outside the real world altogether, in wayward fancies, utopias, fictions or mistakes. But where they do re-enter reality and terminate therein, we substitute them always; and with these substitutes we pass the greater number of our hours.
22 Of which all that need be said in this essay is that it also can be conceived as functional, and defined in terms of transitions, or of the possibility of such.
This is why I called our experiences, taken together, a quasi-chaos. There is vastly more discontinuity in the sum total of experiences than we commonly suppose. The objective nucleus of every man’s experience, his own body, is, it is true, a continuous percept; and equally continuous as a percept (thought we may be inattentive to it) is the material environment of that body, changing by gradual transition when the body moves. But the distant parts of the physical world are at all times absent from us, and form conceptual objects merely, into the perceptual reality of which our life inserts itself at points discrete118 and relatively119 rare. Round their several objective nuclei120, partly shared and common and partly discrete, of the real physical world, innumerable thinkers, pursuing their several lines of physically121 true cogitation122, trace paths that intersect one another only at discontinuous perceptual points, and the rest of the time are quite incongruent; and around all the nuclei of shared ‘reality,’ as around the Dyak’s head of my late metaphor123, floats the vast cloud of experiences that are wholly subjective124, that are non-substitutional, that find not even an eventual24 ending for themselves in the perceptual world — there mere day-dreams and joys and sufferings and wishes of the individual minds. These exist with one another, indeed, and with the objective nuclei, but out of them it is probable that to all eternity125 no interrelated system of any kind will every be made.
This notion of the purely substitutional or conceptual physical world brings us to the most critical of all steps in the development of a philosophy of pure experience. The paradox79 of self-transcendency in knowledge comes back upon us here, but I think that our notions of pure experience and of substitution, and our radically126 empirical view of conjunctive transitions, are Denkmittel that will carry us safely through the pass.
V. What Objective Reference is.
Whosoever feels his experience to be something substitutional even while he has it, may be said to have an experience that reaches beyond itself. From inside of its own entity65 it says ‘more,’ and postulates128 reality existing elsewhere. For the transcendentalist, who holds knowing to consist in a salto mortale across an ‘epistemological chasm,’ such an idea presents no difficulty; but it seems at first sight as if it might be inconsistent with an empiricism like our own. Have we not explained that conceptual knowledge is made such wholly by the existence of things that fall outside of the knowing experience itself — by intermediary experience and by a terminus that fulfils? Can the knowledge be there before these elements that constitute its being have come? And, if knowledge be not there, how can objective reference occur?
The key to this difficulty lies in the distinction between knowing as verified and completed, and the same knowing as in transit57 and on its way. To recur129 to the Memorial Hall example lately used, it is only when our idea of the Hall has actually terminated in the percept that we know ‘for certain’ that from the beginning it was truly cognitive of that. Until established by the end of the process, its quality of knowing that, or indeed of knowing anything, could still be doubted; and yet the knowing really was there, as the result now shows. We were virtual knowers of the Hall long before we were certified130 to have been its actual knowers, by the percept’s retroactive validating131 power. Just so we are ‘mortal’ all the time, by reason of the virtuality of the inevitable133 event which will make us so when it shall have come.
Now the immensely greater part of all our knowing never gets beyond this virtual stage. It never is completed or nailed down. I speak not merely of our ideas of imperceptibles like ether-waves or dissociated ‘ions,’ or of ‘ejects’ like the contents of our neighbors’ minds; I speak also of ideas which we might verify if we would take the trouble, but which we hold for true although unterminated perceptually, because nothing says ‘no’ to us, and there is no contradicting truth in sight. To continue thinking unchallenged is, ninety-nine times out of a hundred, our practical substitute for knowing in the completed sense. As each experience runs by cognitive transition into the next one, and we nowhere feel a collision with what we elsewhere count as truth or fact, we commit ourselves to the current as if the port were sure. We live, as it were, upon the front edge of an advancing wave-crest, and our sense of a determinate direction in falling forward is all we cover of the future of our path. It is as if a differential quotient should be conscious and treat itself as an adequate substitute for a traced-out curve. Our experience, inter6 alia, is of variations of rate and of direction, and lives in these transitions more than in the journey’s end. The experiences of tendency are sufficient to act upon — what more could we have done at those moments even if the later verification comes complete?
This is what, as a radical empiricist, I say to the charge that the objective reference which is so flagrant a character of our experience involves a chasm and a mortal leap. A positively conjunctive transition involves neither chasm nor leap. Being the very original of what we mean by continuity, it makes a continuum wherever it appears. I know full well that such brief words as these will leave the hardened transcendentalist unshaken. Conjunctive experiences separate their terms, he will still say: they are third things interposed, that have themselves to be conjoined by new links, and to invoke them makes our trouble infinitely134 worse. To ‘feel’ our motion forward is impossible. Motion implies terminus; and how can terminus be felt before we have arrived? The barest start and sally forwards, the barest tendency to leave the instant, involves the chasm and the leap. Conjunctive transitions are the most superficial of appearances, illusions of our sensibility which philosophical135 reflection pulverizes136 at a touch. Conception is our only trustworthy instrument, conception and the Absolute working hand in hand. Conception disintegrates137 experience utterly138, but its disjunctions are easily overcome again when the Absolute takes up the task.
Such transcendentalists I must leave, provisionally at least, in full possession of their creed139. I have no space for polemics140 in this article, so I shall simply formulate141 the empiricist doctrine as my hypothesis, leaving it to work or not work as it may.
Objective reference, I say then, is an incident of the fact that so much of our experience comes as an insufficient142 and consists of process and transition. Our fields of experience have no more definite boundaries than have our fields of view. Both are fringed forever by a more that continuously develops, and that continuously supersedes143 them as life proceeds. The relations, generally speaking, are as real here as the terms are, and the only complaint of the transcendentalist’s with which I could at all sympathize would be his charge that, by first making knowledge consist in external relations as I have done, and by then confessing that nine-tenths of the time these are not actually but only virtually there, I have knocked the solid bottom out of the whole business, and palmed off a substitute of knowledge for the genuine thing. Only the admission, such a critic might say, that our ideas are self-transcendent and ‘true’ already, in advance of the experiences that are to terminate them, can bring solidity back to knowledge in a world like this, in which transitions and terminations are only by exception fulfilled.
This seems to me an excellent place for applying the pragmatic method. When a dispute arises, that method consists in auguring144 what practical consequences would be different if one side rather than the other were true. If no difference can be thought of, the dispute is a quarrel over words. What then would the self-transcendency affirmed to exist in advance of all experiential mediation145 or terminations, be known-as? What would it practically result in for us, were it true?
It could only result in our orientation146, in the turning of our expectations and practical tendencies into the right path; and the right path here, so long as we and the object are not yet face to face (or can never get face to face, as in the case of ejects), would be the path that led us into the object’s nearest neighborhood. Where direct acquaintance is lacking, ‘knowledge about’ is the next best thing, and an acquaintance with what actually lies about the object, and is most closely related to it, puts such knowledge within our gasp147. Ether-waves and your anger, for example, are things in which my thoughts will never perceptually terminate, but my concepts of them lead me to their very brink148, to the chromatic149 fringes and to the hurtful words and deeds which are their really next effects.
Even if our ideas did in themselves carry the postulated150 self-transcendency, it would still remain true that their putting us into possession of such effects would be the sole cash- value of the self-transcendency for us. And this cash-value, it is needless to say, is verbatim et literatim what our empiricist account pays in. On pragmatist principles, therefore, a dispute over self-transcendency is a pure logomachy. Call our concepts of ejective things self-transcendent or the reverse, it makes no difference, so long as we don’t differ about the nature of that exalted151 virtue’s fruits — fruits for us, of course, humanistic fruits. If an Absolute were proved to exist for other reasons, it might well appear that his knowledge is terminated in innumerable cases where ours is still incomplete. That, however, would be a fact indifferent to our knowledge. The latter would grow neither worse nor better, whether we acknowledged such an Absolute or left him out.
So the notion of a knowledge still in transitu and on its way joins hands here with that notion of a ‘pure experience’ which I tried to explain in my [essay] entitled ‘Does Consciousness Exist?’ The instant field of the present is always experienced in its ‘pure’ state. plain unqualified actuality, a simple that, as yet undifferentiated into thing and thought, and only virtually classifiable as objective fact or as some one’s opinion about fact. This is as true when the field is conceptual as when it is perceptual. ‘Memorial Hall’ is ‘there’ in my idea as much as when I stand before it. I proceed to act on its account in either case. Only in the later experience that supersedes the present one is this naif immediacy retrospectively split into two parts, a ‘consciousness’ and its ‘content,’ and the content corrected or confirmed. While still pure, or present, any experience — mine, for example, of what I write about in these very lines — passes for ‘truth.’ The morrow may reduce it to ‘opinion.’ The transcendentalist in all his particular knowledges is as liable to this reduction as I am: his Absolute does not save him. Why, then, need he quarrel with an account of knowing that merely leaves it liable to this inevitable condition? Why insist that knowing is a static relation out of time when it practically seems so much a function of our active life? For a thing to be valid132, says Lotze, is the same as to make itself valid. When the whole universe seems only to be making itself valid and to be still incomplete (else why its ceaseless changing?) why, of all things, should knowing be exempt152? Why should it not be making itself valid like everything else? That some parts of it may be already valid or verified beyond dispute, the empirical philosopher, of course, like any one else, may always hope.
VI. The Conterminousness of Different Minds
With transition and prospect153 thus enthroned in pure experience, it is impossible to subscribe154 to the idealism of the English school. Radical empiricism has, in fact, more affinities155 with natural realism than with the views of Berkeley or of Mill, and this can be easily shown.
For the Berkeleyan school, ideas (the verbal equivalent of what I term experiences) are discontinuous. The content of each is wholly immanent, and there are no transitions with which they are consubstantial and through which their beings may unite. Your Memorial Hall and mine, even when both are percepts, are wholly out of connection with each other. Our lives are a congeries of solipsisms, out of which in strict logic only a God could compose a universe even of discourse. No dynamic currents run between my objects and your objects. Never can our minds meet in the same.
The incredibility of such a philosophy is flagrant. It is ‘cold, strained, and unnatural’ in a supreme156 degree; and it may be doubted whether even Berkeley himself, who took it so religiously, really believed, when walking through the streets of London, that his spirit and the spirits of his fellow wayfarers157 had absolutely different towns in view.
To me the decisive reason in favor of our minds meeting in some common objects at least is that, unless I make that supposition, I have no motive158 for assuming that your mind exists at all. Why do I postulate127 your mind? Because I see your body acting159 in a certain way. Its gestures, facial movements, words and conduct generally, are ‘expressive,’ so I deem it actuated as my own is, by an inner life like mine. This argument from analogy is my reason, whether an instinctive160 belief runs before it or not. But what is ‘your body’ here but a percept in my field? It is only as animating161 that object, my object, that I have any occasion to think of you at all. If the body that you actuate be not the very body that I see there, but some duplicate body of your own with which that has nothing to do, we belong to different universes, you and I, and for me to speak of you is folly162. Myriads163 of such universes even now may coexist, irrelevant to one another; my concern is solely164 with the universe with which my own life is connected.
In that perceptual part of my universe which I call your body, your mind and my mind meet and may be called conterminous. Your mind actuates that body and mine sees it; my thoughts pass into it as into their harmonious165 cognitive fulfilment; your emotions and volitions pass into it as causes into their effects.
But that percept hangs together with all our other physical percepts. They are of one stuff with it; and if it be our common possession, they must be so likewise. For instance, your hand lays hold of one end of a rope and my hand lays hold of the other end. We pull against each other. Can our two hands be mutual objects in this experience, and the rope not be mutual also? What is true of the rope is true of any other percept. Your objects are over and over again the same as mine. If I ask you where some object of yours is, our old Memorial Hall, for example, you point to my Memorial Hall with your hand which I see. If you alter an object in your world, put out a candle, for example, when I am present, my candle ipso facto goes out. It is only as altering my objects that I guess you to exist. If your objects do not coalesce166 with my objects, if they be not identically where mine are, they must be proved to be positively somewhere else. But no other location can be assigned for them, so their place must be what it seems to be, the same.23
23 The notions that our objects are inside of our respective heads is not seriously defensible, so I pass it by.
Practically, then, our minds meet in a world of objects which they share in common, which would still be there, if one or several of the minds were destroyed. I can see no formal objection to this supposition’s being literally167 true. On the principles which I am defending, a ‘mind’ or ‘personal consciousness’ is the name for a series of experiences run together by certain definite transitions, and an objective reality is a series of similar experiences knit by different transitions. If one and the same experience can figure twice, once in a mental and once in a physical context (as I have tried, in my article on ‘Consciousness,’ to show that it can), one does not see why it might not figure thrice, or four times, or any number of times, by running into as many different mental contexts, just as the same point, lying at their intersection168, can be continued into many different lines. Abolishing any number of contexts would not destroy the experience itself or its other contexts, any more than abolishing some of the point’s linear continuations would destroy the others, or destroy the point itself.
I well know the subtle dialectic which insists that a term taken in another relation must needs be an intrinsically different term. The crux169 is always the old Greek one, that the same man can’t be tall in relation to one neighbor, and short in relation to another, for that would make him tall and short at once. In this essay I can not stop to refute this dialectic, so I pass on, leaving my flank for the time exposed. But if my reader will only allow that the same ‘now’ both ends his past and begins his future; or that, when he buys an acre of land from his neighbor, it is the same acre that successively figures in the two estates; or that when I pay him a dollar, the same dollar goes into his pocket that came out of mine; he will also in consistency170 have to allow that the same object may conceivably play a part in, as being related to the rest of, any number of otherwise entirely171 different minds. This is enough for my present point: the common-sense notion of minds sharing the same object offers no special logical or epistemological difficulties of its own; it stands or falls with the general possibility of things being in conjunctive relation with other things at all.
In principle, then, let natural realism pass for possible. Your mind and mine may terminate in the same percept, not merely against it, as if it were a third external thing, but by inserting themselves into it and coalescing172 with it, for such is the sort of conjunctive union that appears to be experienced when a perceptual terminus ‘fulfils.’ Even so, two hawsers173 may embrace the same pile, and yet neither one of them touch any other part except that pile, of what the other hawser174 is attached to.
It is therefore not a formal question, but a question of empirical fact solely, whether when you and I are said to know the ‘same’ Memorial Hall, our minds do terminate at or in a numerically identical percept. Obviously, as a plain matter of fact, they do not. Apart from color-blindness and such possibilities, we see the Hall in different perspectives. You may be on one side of it and I on another. The percept of each of us, as he sees the surface of the Hall, is moreover only his provisional terminus. The next thing beyond my percept is not your mind, but more percepts of my own into which my first percept develops, the interior of the Hall, for instance, or the inner structure of its bricks and mortar175. If our minds were in a literal sense conterminous, neither could get beyond the percept which they had in common, it would be an ultimate barrier between them — unless indeed they flowed over it and became ‘co-conscious’ over a still larger part of their content, which (thought-transference apart) is not supposed to be the case. In point of fact the ultimate common barrier can always be pushed, by both minds, farther than any actual percept of either, until at last it resolves itself into the mere notion of imperceptibles like atoms or either, so that, where we do terminate in percepts, our knowledge is only speciously176 completed, being, in theoretic strictness, only a virtual knowledge of those remoter objects which conception carries out.
Is natural realism, permissible177 in logic, refuted then by empirical fact? Do our minds have no object in common after all?
Yet, they certainly have Space in common. On pragmatic principles we are obliged to predicate sameness wherever we can predicate no assignable point of difference. If two named things have every quality and function indiscernible, and are at the same time in the same place, they must be written down as numerically one thing under two different names. But there is no test discoverable, so far as I know, by which it can be shown that the place occupied by your percept of Memorial Hall differs from the place occupied by mine. The percepts themselves may be shown to differ; but if each of us be asked to point out where his percept is, we point to an identical spot. All the relations, whether geometrical or causal, of the Hall originate or terminate in that spot wherein our hands meet, and where each of us begins to work if he wishes to make the Hall change before the other’s eyes. Just so it is with our bodies. That body of yours which you actuate and feel from within must be in the same spot as the body of yours which I see or touch from without. ‘There’ for me means where I place my finger. If you do not feel my finger’s contact to be ‘there’ in my sense, when I place it on your body, where then do you feel it? Your inner actuations of your body meet my finger there: it is there that you resist its push, or shrink back, or sweep the finger aside with your hand. Whatever farther knowledge either of us may acquire of the real constitution of the body which we thus feel, you from within and I from without, it is in that same place that the newly conceived or perceived constituents178 have to be located, and it is through that space that your and my mental intercourse179 with each other has always to be carried on, by the mediation of impressions which I convey thither180, and of the reactions thence which those impressions may provoke from you.
In general terms, then, whatever differing contents our minds may eventually fill a place with, the place itself is a numerically identical content of the two minds, a piece of common property in which, through which, and over which they join. The receptacle of certain of our experiences being thus common, the experiences themselves might some day become common also. If that day ever did come, our thoughts would terminate in a complete empirical identity, there would be an end, so far as those experiences went, to our discussions about truth. No points of difference appearing, they would have to count as the same.
VII. Conclusion
With this we have the outlines of a philosophy of pure experience before us. At the outset of my essay, I called it a mosaic philosophy. In actual mosaics181 the pieces are held together by their bedding, for which bedding of the Substances, transcendental Egos182, or Absolutes of other philosophies may be taken to stand. In radical empiricism there is no bedding; it is as if the pieces clung together by their edges, the transitions experienced between them forming their cement. Of course such a metaphor is misleading, for in actual experience the more substantive and the more transitive parts run into each other continuously, there is in general no separateness needing to be overcome by an external cement; and whatever separateness is actually experienced is not overcome, it stays and counts as separateness to the end. But the metaphor serves to symbolize183 the fact that Experience itself, taken at large, can grow by its edges. That one moment of it proliferates184 into the next by transitions which, whether conjunctive or disjunctive, continue the experiential tissue, can no, I contend, be denied. Life is in the transitions as much as in the terms connected; often, indeed, it seems to be there more emphatically, as if our spurts185 and sallies forward were the real firing-line of the battle, were like the thin line of flame advancing across the dry autumnal field which the farmer proceeds to burn. In this line we live prospectively186 as well as retrospectively. It is ‘of’ the past, inasmuch as it comes expressly as the past’s continuation; it is ‘of’ the future in so far as the future, when it comes, will have continued it.
These relations of continuous transition experienced are what make our experiences cognitive. In the simplest and completest cases the experiences are cognitive of one another. When one of them terminates a previous series of them with a sense of fulfilment, it, we say, is what those other experiences ‘had in view.’ The knowledge, in such a case, is verified; the truth is ‘salted down.’ Mainly, however, we live on speculative187 investments, or on our prospects188 only. But living on things in posse is as good as living in the actual, so long as our credit remains189 good. It is evident that for the most part it is good, and that the universe seldom protests our drafts.
In this sense we at every moment can continue to believe in an existing beyond. It is only in special cases that our confident rush forward gets rebuked190. The beyond must, of course, always in our philosophy be itself of an experiential nature. If not a future experience of our own or a present one of our neighbor, it must be a thing in itself in Dr. Prince’s and Professor Strong’s sense of the term — that is, it must be an experience for itself whose relation to other things we translate into the action of molecules191, ether-waves, or whatever else the physical symbols may be.24 This opens the chapter of the relations of radical empiricism to panspychism, into which I cannot enter now.
24 Our minds and these ejective realities would still have space (or pseudo-space, as I believe Professor Strong calls the medium of interaction between ‘things-inthemselves’) in common. These would exist where, and begin to act where, we locate the molecules, etc., and where we perceive the sensible phenomena explained thereby.
The beyond can in any case exist simultaneously192 — for it can be experienced to have existed simultaneously — with the experience that practically postulates it by looking in its direction, or by turning or changing in the direction of which it is the goal. Pending193 that actuality of union, in the virtuality of which the ‘truth,’ even now, of the postulation194 consists, the beyond and its knower are entities split off from each other. The world is in so far forth195 a pluralism of which the unity is not fully experienced as yet. But, as fast as verifications come, trains of experience, once separate, run into one another; and that is why I said, earlier in my article, that the unity of the world is on the whole undergoing increase. The universe continually grows in quantity by new experiences that graft196 themselves upon the older mass; but these very new experiences often help the mass to a more consolidated197 form.
These are the main features of a philosophy of pure experience. It has innumerable other aspects and arouses innumerable questions, but the points I have touched on seem enough to make an entering wedge. In my own mind such a philosophy harmonizes best with a radical pluralism, with novelty and indeterminism, moralism and theism, and with the ‘humanism’ lately sprung upon us by the Oxford198 and the Chicago schools.25 I can not, however, be sure that all these doctrines199 are its necessary and indispensable allies. It presents so many points of difference, both from the common sense and from the idealism that have made our philosophic language, that it is almost difficult to state it as it is to think it out clearly, and if it is ever to grow into a respectable system, it will have to be built up by the contributions of many co-operating minds. It seems to me, as I said at the outset of this essay, that many minds are, in point of fact, now turning in a direction that points towards radical empiricism. If they are carried farther by my words, and if then they add their stronger voices to my feebler one, the publication of this essay will have been worth while.
1 philosophic | |
adj.哲学的,贤明的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 landmarks | |
n.陆标( landmark的名词复数 );目标;(标志重要阶段的)里程碑 ~ (in sth);有历史意义的建筑物(或遗址) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 softening | |
变软,软化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 oppositions | |
(强烈的)反对( opposition的名词复数 ); 反对党; (事业、竞赛、游戏等的)对手; 对比 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 mutual | |
adj.相互的,彼此的;共同的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 inter | |
v.埋葬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 inadequacy | |
n.无法胜任,信心不足 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 crave | |
vt.渴望得到,迫切需要,恳求,请求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 temperament | |
n.气质,性格,性情 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 logic | |
n.逻辑(学);逻辑性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 rigor | |
n.严酷,严格,严厉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 unity | |
n.团结,联合,统一;和睦,协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 parsimony | |
n.过度节俭,吝啬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 dabbling | |
v.涉猎( dabble的现在分词 );涉足;浅尝;少量投资 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 speculations | |
n.投机买卖( speculation的名词复数 );思考;投机活动;推断 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 flirts | |
v.调情,打情骂俏( flirt的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 teleology | |
n.目的论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 biased | |
a.有偏见的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 upheaval | |
n.胀起,(地壳)的隆起;剧变,动乱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 imminent | |
adj.即将发生的,临近的,逼近的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 propitious | |
adj.吉利的;顺利的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 vat | |
n.(=value added tax)增值税,大桶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 publicity | |
n.众所周知,闻名;宣传,广告 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 eventual | |
adj.最后的,结局的,最终的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 subside | |
vi.平静,平息;下沉,塌陷,沉降 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 profundities | |
n.深奥,深刻,深厚( profundity的名词复数 );堂奥 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 ferment | |
vt.使发酵;n./vt.(使)激动,(使)动乱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 nucleus | |
n.核,核心,原子核 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 radical | |
n.激进份子,原子团,根号;adj.根本的,激进的,彻底的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 mosaic | |
n./adj.镶嵌细工的,镶嵌工艺品的,嵌花式的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 plural | |
n.复数;复数形式;adj.复数的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 epithet | |
n.(用于褒贬人物等的)表述形容词,修饰语 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 fully | |
adv.完全地,全部地,彻底地;充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 habitual | |
adj.习惯性的;通常的,惯常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 pulverization | |
n.弄成粉,粉碎;粉化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 ego | |
n.自我,自己,自尊 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 supernal | |
adj.天堂的,天上的;崇高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 vitality | |
n.活力,生命力,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 intimacy | |
n.熟悉,亲密,密切关系,亲昵的言行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 discourse | |
n.论文,演说;谈话;话语;vi.讲述,著述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 suffuse | |
v.(色彩等)弥漫,染遍 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 ascending | |
adj.上升的,向上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 likeness | |
n.相像,相似(之处) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 chaotic | |
adj.混沌的,一片混乱的,一团糟的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 aquarium | |
n.水族馆,养鱼池,玻璃缸 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 lodges | |
v.存放( lodge的第三人称单数 );暂住;埋入;(权利、权威等)归属 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 skull | |
n.头骨;颅骨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 strings | |
n.弦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 beads | |
n.(空心)小珠子( bead的名词复数 );水珠;珠子项链 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 dangle | |
v.(使)悬荡,(使)悬垂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 irrelevant | |
adj.不恰当的,无关系的,不相干的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 unduly | |
adv.过度地,不适当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 allots | |
分配,拨给,摊派( allot的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 transit | |
n.经过,运输;vt.穿越,旋转;vi.越过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 corruptions | |
n.堕落( corruption的名词复数 );腐化;腐败;贿赂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 neutralize | |
v.使失效、抵消,使中和 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 positively | |
adv.明确地,断然,坚决地;实在,确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 noted | |
adj.著名的,知名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 ascertained | |
v.弄清,确定,查明( ascertain的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 psychology | |
n.心理,心理学,心理状态 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 stark | |
adj.荒凉的;严酷的;完全的;adv.完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 entity | |
n.实体,独立存在体,实际存在物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 hitched | |
(免费)搭乘他人之车( hitch的过去式和过去分词 ); 搭便车; 攀上; 跃上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 discredit | |
vt.使不可置信;n.丧失信义;不信,怀疑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 discredited | |
不足信的,不名誉的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 permanently | |
adv.永恒地,永久地,固定不变地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 fictitious | |
adj.虚构的,假设的;空头的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 invoking | |
v.援引( invoke的现在分词 );行使(权利等);祈求救助;恳求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 converse | |
vi.谈话,谈天,闲聊;adv.相反的,相反 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 invoke | |
v.求助于(神、法律);恳求,乞求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 cognitive | |
adj.认知的,认识的,有感知的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 pitfall | |
n.隐患,易犯的错误;陷阱,圈套 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 standing | |
n.持续,地位;adj.永久的,不动的,直立的,不流动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 entities | |
实体对像; 实体,独立存在体,实际存在物( entity的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 paradox | |
n.似乎矛盾却正确的说法;自相矛盾的人(物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 bosom | |
n.胸,胸部;胸怀;内心;adj.亲密的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 intelligible | |
adj.可理解的,明白易懂的,清楚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 tracts | |
大片土地( tract的名词复数 ); 地带; (体内的)道; (尤指宣扬宗教、伦理或政治的)短文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 incompatible | |
adj.不相容的,不协调的,不相配的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 thoroughly | |
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 elucidated | |
v.阐明,解释( elucidate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 mediating | |
调停,调解,斡旋( mediate的现在分词 ); 居间促成; 影响…的发生; 使…可能发生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 apparently | |
adv.显然地;表面上,似乎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 miller | |
n.磨坊主 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 dubs | |
v.给…起绰号( dub的第三人称单数 );把…称为;配音;复制 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 extrinsic | |
adj.外部的;不紧要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 delta | |
n.(流的)角洲 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 serially | |
adv.连续地,连续刊载地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 corroborates | |
v.证实,支持(某种说法、信仰、理论等)( corroborate的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 corroborating | |
v.证实,支持(某种说法、信仰、理论等)( corroborate的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 pretence | |
n.假装,作假;借口,口实;虚伪;虚饰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 substantive | |
adj.表示实在的;本质的、实质性的;独立的;n.实词,实名词;独立存在的实体 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 etymological | |
adj.语源的,根据语源学的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 chasm | |
n.深坑,断层,裂口,大分岐,利害冲突 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 smitten | |
猛打,重击,打击( smite的过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 sham | |
n./adj.假冒(的),虚伪(的) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 impartially | |
adv.公平地,无私地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 prey | |
n.被掠食者,牺牲者,掠食;v.捕食,掠夺,折磨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 professing | |
声称( profess的现在分词 ); 宣称; 公开表明; 信奉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 alleging | |
断言,宣称,辩解( allege的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 purely | |
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 systematically | |
adv.有系统地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 cardinal | |
n.(天主教的)红衣主教;adj.首要的,基本的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 lapse | |
n.过失,流逝,失效,抛弃信仰,间隔;vi.堕落,停止,失效,流逝;vt.使失效 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 superseded | |
[医]被代替的,废弃的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 predecessors | |
n.前任( predecessor的名词复数 );前辈;(被取代的)原有事物;前身 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 functional | |
adj.为实用而设计的,具备功能的,起作用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 advantageous | |
adj.有利的;有帮助的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 outstrip | |
v.超过,跑过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 tardy | |
adj.缓慢的,迟缓的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 discrete | |
adj.个别的,分离的,不连续的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 relatively | |
adv.比较...地,相对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 nuclei | |
n.核 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 physically | |
adj.物质上,体格上,身体上,按自然规律 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 cogitation | |
n.仔细思考,计划,设计 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 metaphor | |
n.隐喻,暗喻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 subjective | |
a.主观(上)的,个人的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 eternity | |
n.不朽,来世;永恒,无穷 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 radically | |
ad.根本地,本质地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 postulate | |
n.假定,基本条件;vt.要求,假定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 postulates | |
v.假定,假设( postulate的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 recur | |
vi.复发,重现,再发生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 certified | |
a.经证明合格的;具有证明文件的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 validating | |
v.证实( validate的现在分词 );确证;使生效;使有法律效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 valid | |
adj.有确实根据的;有效的;正当的,合法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 inevitable | |
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 infinitely | |
adv.无限地,无穷地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 pulverizes | |
v.将…弄碎( pulverize的第三人称单数 );将…弄成粉末或尘埃;摧毁;粉碎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 disintegrates | |
n.(使)破裂[分裂,粉碎],(使)崩溃( disintegrate的名词复数 )v.(使)破裂[分裂,粉碎],(使)崩溃( disintegrate的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 utterly | |
adv.完全地,绝对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 creed | |
n.信条;信念,纲领 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 polemics | |
n.辩论术,辩论法;争论( polemic的名词复数 );辩论;辩论术;辩论法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141 formulate | |
v.用公式表示;规划;设计;系统地阐述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142 insufficient | |
adj.(for,of)不足的,不够的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143 supersedes | |
取代,接替( supersede的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144 auguring | |
v.预示,预兆,预言( augur的现在分词 );成为预兆;占卜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145 mediation | |
n.调解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146 orientation | |
n.方向,目标;熟悉,适应,情况介绍 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147 gasp | |
n.喘息,气喘;v.喘息;气吁吁他说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148 brink | |
n.(悬崖、河流等的)边缘,边沿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149 chromatic | |
adj.色彩的,颜色的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150 postulated | |
v.假定,假设( postulate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151 exalted | |
adj.(地位等)高的,崇高的;尊贵的,高尚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
152 exempt | |
adj.免除的;v.使免除;n.免税者,被免除义务者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
153 prospect | |
n.前景,前途;景色,视野 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
154 subscribe | |
vi.(to)订阅,订购;同意;vt.捐助,赞助 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
155 affinities | |
n.密切关系( affinity的名词复数 );亲近;(生性)喜爱;类同 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
156 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
157 wayfarers | |
n.旅人,(尤指)徒步旅行者( wayfarer的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
158 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
159 acting | |
n.演戏,行为,假装;adj.代理的,临时的,演出用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
160 instinctive | |
adj.(出于)本能的;直觉的;(出于)天性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
161 animating | |
v.使有生气( animate的现在分词 );驱动;使栩栩如生地动作;赋予…以生命 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
162 folly | |
n.愚笨,愚蠢,蠢事,蠢行,傻话 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
163 myriads | |
n.无数,极大数量( myriad的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
164 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
165 harmonious | |
adj.和睦的,调和的,和谐的,协调的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
166 coalesce | |
v.联合,结合,合并 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
167 literally | |
adv.照字面意义,逐字地;确实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
168 intersection | |
n.交集,十字路口,交叉点;[计算机] 交集 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
169 crux | |
adj.十字形;难事,关键,最重要点 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
170 consistency | |
n.一贯性,前后一致,稳定性;(液体的)浓度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
171 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
172 coalescing | |
v.联合,合并( coalesce的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
173 hawsers | |
n.(供系船或下锚用的)缆索,锚链( hawser的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
174 hawser | |
n.大缆;大索 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
175 mortar | |
n.灰浆,灰泥;迫击炮;v.把…用灰浆涂接合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
176 speciously | |
adv.似是而非地;外观好看地,像是真实地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
177 permissible | |
adj.可允许的,许可的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
178 constituents | |
n.选民( constituent的名词复数 );成分;构成部分;要素 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
179 intercourse | |
n.性交;交流,交往,交际 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
180 thither | |
adv.向那里;adj.在那边的,对岸的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
181 mosaics | |
n.马赛克( mosaic的名词复数 );镶嵌;镶嵌工艺;镶嵌图案 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
182 egos | |
自我,自尊,自负( ego的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
183 symbolize | |
vt.作为...的象征,用符号代表 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
184 proliferates | |
激增( proliferate的名词复数 ); (迅速)繁殖; 增生; 扩散 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
185 spurts | |
短暂而突然的活动或努力( spurt的名词复数 ); 突然奋起 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
186 prospectively | |
adv.预期; 前瞻性; 潜在; 可能 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
187 speculative | |
adj.思索性的,暝想性的,推理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
188 prospects | |
n.希望,前途(恒为复数) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
189 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
190 rebuked | |
责难或指责( rebuke的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
191 molecules | |
分子( molecule的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
192 simultaneously | |
adv.同时发生地,同时进行地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
193 pending | |
prep.直到,等待…期间;adj.待定的;迫近的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
194 postulation | |
n.假定;公设 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
195 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
196 graft | |
n.移植,嫁接,艰苦工作,贪污;v.移植,嫁接 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
197 consolidated | |
a.联合的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
198 Oxford | |
n.牛津(英国城市) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
199 doctrines | |
n.教条( doctrine的名词复数 );教义;学说;(政府政策的)正式声明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |