Happiness is an abstract idea composed of certain pleasurable sensations. Plato, who wrote better than he reasoned, conceived the notion of his world in archetype; that is, his original world — of his general ideas of the beautiful, the good, the orderly, and the just, as if there had existed eternal beings, called order, good, beauty, and justice; whence might be derived1 the feeble copies exhibited here below of the just, the beautiful, and the good.
It is, then, in consequence of his suggestions that philosophers have occupied themselves in seeking for the sovereign good, as chemists seek for the philosopher’s stone; but the sovereign good has no more existence than the sovereign square, or the sovereign crimson2: there is the crimson color, and there are squares; but there is no general existence so denominated. This chimerical3 manner of reasoning was for a long time the bane of philosophy.
Animals feel pleasure in performing all the functions for which they are destined4. The happiness which poetical5 fancy has imagined would be an uninterrupted series of pleasures; but such a series would be incompatible6 with our organs and our destination. There is great pleasure in eating, drinking, and connubial7 endearments8; but it is clear that if a man were always eating, or always in the full ecstasy9 of enjoyment10, his organs would be incapable11 of sustaining it: it is further evident that he would be unable to fulfil the destinies he was born to, and that, in the case supposed, the human race would absolutely perish through pleasure.
To pass constantly and without interruption from one pleasure to another is also a chimera12. The woman who has conceived must go through childbirth, which is a pain; the man is obliged to cleave13 wood and hew14 stone, which is not a pleasure.
If the name of happiness is meant to be applied15 to some pleasures which are diffused16 over human life, there is in fact, we must admit, happiness. If the name attaches only to one pleasure always permanent, or a continued although varied17 range of delicious enjoyment, then happiness belongs not to this terraqueous globe. Go and seek for it elsewhere.
If we make happiness consist in any particular situation that a man may be in, as for instance, a situation of wealth, power, or fame, we are no less mistaken. There are some scavengers who are happier than some sovereigns. Ask Cromwell whether he was more happy when he was lord protector of England, than when, in his youthful days, he enjoyed himself at a tavern18; he will probably tell you in answer, that the period of his usurpation19 was not the period most productive of pleasures. How many plain or even ugly country women are more happy than were Helen and Cleopatra.
We must here however make one short remark; that when we say such a particular man is probably happier than some other; that a young muleteer has advantages very superior to those of Charles V.; that a dressmaker has more enjoyment than a princess, we should adhere to the probability of the case. There is certainly every appearance that a muleteer, in full health, must have more pleasure than Charles the Fifth, laid up with the gout; but nevertheless it may also be, that Charles, on his crutches20, revolves21 in his mind with such ecstasy the facts of his holding a king of France and a pope prisoners, that his lot is absolutely preferable to that of the young and vigorous muleteer.
It certainly belongs to God alone, to a being capable of seeing through all hearts, to decide which is the happiest man. There is only one case in which a person can affirm that his actual state is worse or better than that of his neighbor; this case is that of existing rivalship, and the moment that of victory.
I will suppose that Archimedes has an assignation at night with his mistress. Nomentanus has the same assignation at the same hour. Archimedes presents himself at the door, and it is shut in his face; but it is opened to his rival, who enjoys an excellent supper, which he enlivens by his repeated sallies of wit upon Archimedes, and after the conclusion of which he withdraws to still higher enjoyments22, while the other remains23 exposed in the street to all the pelting24 of a pitiless storm. There can be no doubt that Nomentanus has a right to say: “I am more happy to-night than Archimedes: I have more pleasure than he”; but it is necessary, in order to admit the truth and justness of the inference of the successful competitors in his own favor, to suppose that Archimedes is thinking only about the loss of his good supper, about being despised and deceived by a beautiful woman, about being supplanted25 by his rival, and annoyed by the tempest; for, if the philosopher in the street should be calmly reflecting that his soul ought to be above being discomposed by a strumpet or a storm, if he should be absorbed in a profound and interesting problem, and if he should discover the proportions between the cylinder26 and the sphere, he may experience a pleasure a hundred times superior to that of Nomentanus.
It is only therefore in the single case of actual pleasure and actual pain, and without a reference to anything else whatever, that a comparison between any two individuals can be properly made. It is unquestionable that he who enjoys the society of his mistress is happier at the moment than his scorned rival deploring27 over his misfortune. A man in health, supping on a fat partridge, is undoubtedly28 happier at the time than another under the torment29 of the colic; but we cannot safely carry our inferences farther; we cannot estimate the existence of one man against that of another; we possess no accurate balance for weighing desires and sensations.
We began this article with Plato and his sovereign good; we will conclude it with Solon and the saying of his which has been so highly celebrated30, that “we ought to pronounce no man happy before his death.” This maxim31, when examined into, will be found nothing more than a puerile32 remark, just like many other apothegms consecrated33 by their antiquity34. The moment of death has nothing in common with the lot experienced by any man in life; a man may perish by a violent and ignominious35 death, and yet, up to that moment, may have enjoyed all the pleasures of which human nature is susceptible36. It is very possible and very common for a happy man to cease to be so; no one can doubt it; but he has not the less had his happy moments.
What, then, can Solon’s expression strictly37 and fairly mean? that a man happy to-day is not certain of being so to-morrow! In this case it is a truth so incontestable and trivial that, not merely is it not worthy38 of being elevated into a maxim, but it is not worthy delivering at all.
§ II.
Well-being39 is a rare possession. May not the sovereign good in this world be considered as a sovereign chimera? The Greek philosophers discussed at great length, according to their usual practice, this celebrated question. The reader will, probably, compare them to just so many mendicants reasoning about the philosopher’s stone.
The sovereign good! What an expression! It might as well have been asked: What is the sovereign blue, or the sovereign ragout, or the sovereign walk, or the sovereign reading?
Every one places his good where he can, and has as much of it as he can, in his own way, and in very scanty40 measure. Castor loved horses; his twin brother, to try a fall —
Quid dem? quid non dem? renuis tu quod jubet alter . . . .
Castor gaudet equis, ovo prognatus eodem
Pugnis, etc.
The greatest good is that which delights us so powerfully as to render us incapable of feeling anything else; as the greatest evil is that which goes so far as to deprive us of all feeling. These are the two extremes of human nature, and these moments are short. Neither extreme delight nor extreme torture can last a whole life. The sovereign good and the sovereign evil are nothing more than chimeras41.
We all know the beautiful fable42 of Crantor. He introduces upon the stage at the Olympic games, Wealth, Pleasure, Health, and Virtue43. Each claims the apple. Wealth says, I am the sovereign good, for with me all goods are purchased. Pleasure says, the apple belongs to me, for it is only on my account that wealth is desired. Health asserts, that without her there can be no pleasure, and wealth is useless. Finally, Virtue states that she is superior to the other three, because, although possessed44 of gold, pleasures, and health, a man may make himself very contemptible45 by misconduct. The apple was conferred on Virtue.
The fable is very ingenious; it would be still more so if Crantor had said that the sovereign good consists in the combination of the four rivals, Virtue, Health, Wealth, and Pleasure; but this fable neither does, nor can, resolve the absurd question about the sovereign good. Virtue is not a good; it is a duty. It is of a different nature; of a superior order. It has nothing to do with painful or with agreeable sensations. A virtuous46 man, laboring47 under stone and gout, without aid, without friends, destitute48 of necessaries, persecuted49, and chained down to the floor by a voluptuous50 tyrant51 who enjoys good health, is very wretched; and his insolent52 persecutor53, caressing54 a new mistress on his bed of purple, is very happy. Say, if you please, that the persecuted sage55 is preferable to the persecuting56 profligate57; say that you admire the one and detest58 the other; but confess that the sage in chains is scarcely less than mad with rage and pain; if he does not himself admit that he is so, he completely deceives you; he is a charlatan59.
点击收听单词发音
1 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 crimson | |
n./adj.深(绯)红色(的);vi.脸变绯红色 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 chimerical | |
adj.荒诞不经的,梦幻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 poetical | |
adj.似诗人的;诗一般的;韵文的;富有诗意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 incompatible | |
adj.不相容的,不协调的,不相配的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 connubial | |
adj.婚姻的,夫妇的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 endearments | |
n.表示爱慕的话语,亲热的表示( endearment的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 ecstasy | |
n.狂喜,心醉神怡,入迷 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 enjoyment | |
n.乐趣;享有;享用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 incapable | |
adj.无能力的,不能做某事的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 chimera | |
n.神话怪物;梦幻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 cleave | |
v.(clave;cleaved)粘着,粘住;坚持;依恋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 hew | |
v.砍;伐;削 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 diffused | |
散布的,普及的,扩散的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 varied | |
adj.多样的,多变化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 tavern | |
n.小旅馆,客栈;小酒店 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 usurpation | |
n.篡位;霸占 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 crutches | |
n.拐杖, 支柱 v.支撑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 revolves | |
v.(使)旋转( revolve的第三人称单数 );细想 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 enjoyments | |
愉快( enjoyment的名词复数 ); 令人愉快的事物; 享有; 享受 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 pelting | |
微不足道的,无价值的,盛怒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 supplanted | |
把…排挤掉,取代( supplant的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 cylinder | |
n.圆筒,柱(面),汽缸 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 deploring | |
v.悲叹,痛惜,强烈反对( deplore的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 undoubtedly | |
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 torment | |
n.折磨;令人痛苦的东西(人);vt.折磨;纠缠 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 celebrated | |
adj.有名的,声誉卓著的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 maxim | |
n.格言,箴言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 puerile | |
adj.幼稚的,儿童的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 consecrated | |
adj.神圣的,被视为神圣的v.把…奉为神圣,给…祝圣( consecrate的过去式和过去分词 );奉献 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 antiquity | |
n.古老;高龄;古物,古迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 ignominious | |
adj.可鄙的,不光彩的,耻辱的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 susceptible | |
adj.过敏的,敏感的;易动感情的,易受感动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 worthy | |
adj.(of)值得的,配得上的;有价值的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 well-being | |
n.安康,安乐,幸福 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 scanty | |
adj.缺乏的,仅有的,节省的,狭小的,不够的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 chimeras | |
n.(由几种动物的各部分构成的)假想的怪兽( chimera的名词复数 );不可能实现的想法;幻想;妄想 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 fable | |
n.寓言;童话;神话 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 contemptible | |
adj.可鄙的,可轻视的,卑劣的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 virtuous | |
adj.有品德的,善良的,贞洁的,有效力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 laboring | |
n.劳动,操劳v.努力争取(for)( labor的现在分词 );苦干;详细分析;(指引擎)缓慢而困难地运转 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 destitute | |
adj.缺乏的;穷困的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 persecuted | |
(尤指宗教或政治信仰的)迫害(~sb. for sth.)( persecute的过去式和过去分词 ); 烦扰,困扰或骚扰某人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 voluptuous | |
adj.肉欲的,骄奢淫逸的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 tyrant | |
n.暴君,专制的君主,残暴的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 insolent | |
adj.傲慢的,无理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 persecutor | |
n. 迫害者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 caressing | |
爱抚的,表现爱情的,亲切的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 sage | |
n.圣人,哲人;adj.贤明的,明智的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 persecuting | |
(尤指宗教或政治信仰的)迫害(~sb. for sth.)( persecute的现在分词 ); 烦扰,困扰或骚扰某人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 profligate | |
adj.行为不检的;n.放荡的人,浪子,肆意挥霍者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 detest | |
vt.痛恨,憎恶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 charlatan | |
n.骗子;江湖医生;假内行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |