Of the “Tim?us” of Plato and Some Other Things.
The fathers of the Church, of the first four centuries, were all Greeks and Platonists: you find not one Roman who wrote for Christianity, or who had the slightest tincture of philosophy. I will here observe, by the way, that it is strange enough, the great Church of Rome, which contributed in nothing to this establishment, has alone reaped all the advantage. It has been with this revolution, as with all those produced by civil wars: the first who trouble a state, always unknowingly labor2 for others rather than for themselves.
The school of Alexandria, founded by one named Mark, to whom succeeded Athenagoras, Clement3, and Origen, was the centre of the Christian1 philosophy. Plato was regarded by all the Greeks of Alexandria as the master of wisdom, the interpreter of the divinity. If the first Christians4 had not embraced the dogmas of Plato, they would never have had any philosophers, any man of mind in their party. I set aside inspiration and grace which are above all philosophy, and speak only of the ordinary course of human events.
It is said that it was principally in the “Tim?us” of Plato that the Greek fathers were instructed. This “Tim?us” passes for the most sublime5 work of all ancient philosophy. It is almost the only one which Dacier has not translated, and I think the reason is, because he did not understand it, and that he feared to discover to clear-sighted readers the face of this Greek divinity, who is only adored because he is veiled.
Plato, in this fine dialogue, commences by introducing an Egyptian priest, who teaches Solon the ancient history of the city of Athens, which was preserved faithfully for nine thousand years in the archives of Egypt.
Athens, says the priest, was once the finest city of Greece, and the most renowned6 in the world for the arts of war and peace. She alone resisted the warriors7 of the famous island Atlantis, who came in innumerable vessels8 to subjugate9 a great part of Europe and Asia. Athens had the glory of freeing so many vanquished10 people, and of preserving Egypt from the servitude which menaced us. But after this illustrious victory and service rendered to mankind, a frightful11 earthquake in twenty-four hours swallowed the territory of Athens, and all the great island of Atlantis. This island is now only a vast sea, which the ruins of this ancient world and the slime mixed with its waters rendered unnavigable.
This is what the priest relates to Solon: and such is the manner in which Plato prepares to explain to us subsequently, the formation of the soul, the operations of the “Word,” and his trinity. It is not physically12 impossible that there might be an island Atlantis, which had not existed for nine thousand years, and which perished by an earthquake, like Herculaneum and so many other cities; but our priest, in adding that the sea which washes Mount Atlas13 is inaccessible14 to vessels, renders the history a little suspicious.
It may be, after all, that since Solon — that is to say, in the course of three thousand years — vessels have dispersed15 the slime of the ancient island Atlantis and rendered the sea navigable; but it is still surprising that he should prepare by this island to speak of the “Word.”
Perhaps in telling this priest’s or old woman’s story, Plato wished to insinuate16 something contrary to the vicissitudes17 which have so often changed the face of the globe. Perhaps he would merely say what Pythagoras and Tim?us of Locris have said so long before him, and what our eyes tell us every day — that everything in nature perishes and is renewed. The history of Deucalion and Pyrrha, the fall of Ph?thon, are fables18: but inundations and conflagrations19 are truths.
Plato departs from his imaginary island, to speak of things which the best of philosophers of our days would not disavow. “That which is produced has necessarily a cause, an author. It is difficult to discover the author of this world; and when he is found it is dangerous to speak of him to the people.”
Nothing is more true, even now, than that if a sage20, in passing by our Lady of Loretto, said to another sage, his friend, that our Lady of Loretto, with her little black face, governs not the entire universe, and a good woman overheard these words, and related them to other good women of the march of Ancona, the sage would be stoned like Orpheus. This is precisely21 the situation in which the first Christians were believed to be, who spoke22 not well of Cybele and Diana, which alone should attach them to Plato. The unintelligible23 things which he afterwards treats of, ought not to disgust us with him.
I will not reproach Plato with saying, in his “Tim?us,” that the world is an animal; for he no doubt understands that the elements in motion animate25 the world; and he means not, by animal, a dog or a man, who walks, feels, eats, sleeps, and engenders26. An author should always be explained in the most favorable sense; and it is not while we accuse people, or when we denounce their books, that it is right to interpret malignantly27 and poison all their words; nor is it thus that I shall treat Plato.
According to him there is a kind of trinity which is the soul of matter. These are his words: “From the indivisible substance, always similar to itself, and the divisible substance, a third substance is composed, which partakes of the same and of others.”
Afterwards came the Pythagorean number, which renders the thing still more unintelligible, and consequently more respectable. What ammunition28 for people commencing a paper war! Friend reader, a little patience and attention, if you please: “When God had formed the soul of the world of these three substances, the soul shot itself into the midst of the universe, to the extremities29 of being; spreading itself everywhere, and reacting upon itself, it formed at all times a divine origin of eternal wisdom.”
And some lines afterwards: “Thus the nature of the immense animal which we call the world, is eternal.” Plato, following the example of his predecessors30, then introduces the Supreme31 Being, the Creator of the world, forming this world before time; so that God could not exist without the world, nor the world without God; as the sun cannot exist without shedding light into space, nor this light steal into space without the sun.
I pass in silence many Greek, or rather Oriental ideas; as for example — that there are four sorts of animals — celestial32 gods, birds of the air, fishes, and terrestrial animals, to which last we have the honor to belong.
I hasten to arrive at a second trinity: “the being engendered33, the being who engenders, and the being which resembles the engendered and the engenderer.” This trinity is formal enough, and the fathers have found their account in it.
This trinity is followed by a rather singular theory of the four elements. The earth is founded on an equilateral triangle, water on a right-angled triangle, air on a scalene, and fire on an isosceles triangle. After which he demonstratively proves that there can be but five worlds, because there are but five regular solid bodies, and yet that there is but one world which is round.
I confess that no philosopher in Bedlam34 has ever reasoned so powerfully. Rouse yourself, friend reader, to hear me speak of the other famous trinity of Plato, which his commentators35 have so much vaunted: it is the Eternal Being, the Eternal Creator of the world; His word, intelligence, or idea; and the good which results from it. I assure you that I have sought for it diligently36 in this “Tim?us,” and I have never found it there; it may be there totidem literis, but it is not totidem verbis, or I am much mistaken.
After reading all Plato with great reluctance37, I perceived some shadow of the trinity for which he is so much honored. It is in the sixth book of his “Chimerical Republic,” in which he says: “Let us speak of the Son, the wonderful production of good, and His perfect image.” But unfortunately he discovers this perfect image of God to be the sun. It was therefore the physical sun, which with the Word and the Father composed the platonic38 trinity. In the “Epinomis” of Plato there are very curious absurdities39, one of which I translate as reasonably as I can, for the convenience of the reader:
“Know that there are eight virtues40 in heaven: I have observed them, which is easy to all the world. The sun is one of its virtues, the moon another; the third is the assemblage of stars; and the five planets, with these three virtues, make the number eight. Be careful of thinking that these virtues, or those which they contain, and which animate them, either move of themselves or are carried in vehicles; be careful, I say, of believing that some may be gods and others not; that some may be adorable, and others such as we should neither adore or invoke41. They are all brothers; each has his share; we owe them all the same honors; they fill all the situations which the Word assigned to them, when it formed the visible universe.”
Here is the Word already found: we must now find the three persons. They are in the second letter from Plato to Dionysius, which letters assuredly are not forged; the style is the same as that of his dialogues. He often says to Dionysius and Dion things very difficult to comprehend, and which we might believe to be written in numbers, but he also tells us very clear ones, which have been found true a long time after him. For example, he expresses himself thus in his seventh letter to Dion:
“I have been convinced that all states are very badly governed; there is scarcely any good institution or administration. We see, as it were, day after day, that all follow the path of fortune rather than that of wisdom.” After this short digression on temporal affairs, let us return to spiritual ones, to the Trinity. Plato says to Dionysius:
“The King of the universe is surrounded by His works: all is the effect of His grace. The finest of things have their first cause in Him; the second in perfection have in Him their second cause, and He is further the third cause of works of the third degree.”
The Trinity, such as we acknowledge, could not be recognized in this letter; but it was a great point to have in a Greek author a guaranty of the dogmas of the dawning Church. Every Greek church was therefore Platonic, as every Latin church was peripatetic42, from the commencement of the third century. Thus two Greeks whom we have never understood, were the masters of our opinions until the time in which men at the end of two thousand years were obliged to think for themselves.
§ II.
Questions on Plato and Some Other Trifles.
Plato, in saying to the Greeks what so many philosophers of other nations have said before him, in assuring them that there is a Supreme Intelligence which arranged the universe — did he think that this Supreme Intelligence resided in a single place, like a king of the East in his seraglio? Or rather did he believe that this Powerful Intelligence spread itself everywhere like light, or a being still more delicate, prompt, active, and penetrating43 than light? The God of Plato, in a word, is he in matter, or is he separated from it? Oh, you who have read Plato attentively44, that is to say, seven or eight fantastical dreams hidden in some garret in Europe, if ever these questions reach you, I implore45 you to answer them.
The barbarous island of Cassiterides, in which men lived in the woods in the time of Plato, has finally produced philosophers who are as much beyond him as Plato was beyond those of his contemporaries who reasoned not at all. Among these philosophers, Clarke is perhaps altogether the clearest, the most profound, the most methodical, and the strongest of all those who have spoken of the Supreme Being.
When he gave his excellent book to the public he found a young gentleman of the county of Gloucester who candidly46 advanced objections as strong as his demonstrations47. We can see them at the end of the first volume of Clarke; it was not on the necessary existence of the Supreme Being that he reasoned; it was on His infinity48 and immensity.
It appears not indeed, that Clarke has proved that there is a being who penetrates50 intimately all which exists, and that this being whose properties we cannot conceive has the property of extending Himself to the greatest imaginable distance.
The great Newton has demonstrated that there is a void in nature; but what philosopher could demonstrate to me that God is in this void; that He touches it; that He fills it? How, bounded as we are, can we attain51 to the knowledge of these mysteries? Does it not suffice, that it proves to us that a Supreme Master exists? It is not given to us to know what He is nor how He is.
It seems as if Locke and Clarke had the keys of the intelligible24 world. Locke has opened all the apartments which can be entered; but has not Clarke wished to penetrate49 a little above the edifice52? How could a philosopher like Samuel Clarke, after so admirable a work on the existence of God, write so pitiable a one on matters of fact?
How could Benedict Spinoza, who had as much profundity53 of mind as Samuel Clarke, after raising himself to the most sublime metaphysics, how could he not perceive that a Supreme Intelligence presides over works visibly arranged with a supreme intelligence — if it is true after all that such is the system of Spinoza?
How could Newton, the greatest of men, comment upon the Apocalypse, as we have already remarked? How could Locke, after having so well developed the human understanding, degrade his own in another work? I fancy I see eagles, who after darting54 into a cloud go to rest on a dunghill.
点击收听单词发音
1 Christian | |
adj.基督教徒的;n.基督教徒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 labor | |
n.劳动,努力,工作,劳工;分娩;vi.劳动,努力,苦干;vt.详细分析;麻烦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 clement | |
adj.仁慈的;温和的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 Christians | |
n.基督教徒( Christian的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 sublime | |
adj.崇高的,伟大的;极度的,不顾后果的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 renowned | |
adj.著名的,有名望的,声誉鹊起的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 warriors | |
武士,勇士,战士( warrior的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 vessels | |
n.血管( vessel的名词复数 );船;容器;(具有特殊品质或接受特殊品质的)人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 subjugate | |
v.征服;抑制 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 vanquished | |
v.征服( vanquish的过去式和过去分词 );战胜;克服;抑制 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 frightful | |
adj.可怕的;讨厌的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 physically | |
adj.物质上,体格上,身体上,按自然规律 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 atlas | |
n.地图册,图表集 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 inaccessible | |
adj.达不到的,难接近的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 dispersed | |
adj. 被驱散的, 被分散的, 散布的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 insinuate | |
vt.含沙射影地说,暗示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 vicissitudes | |
n.变迁,世事变化;变迁兴衰( vicissitude的名词复数 );盛衰兴废 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 fables | |
n.寓言( fable的名词复数 );神话,传说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 conflagrations | |
n.大火(灾)( conflagration的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 sage | |
n.圣人,哲人;adj.贤明的,明智的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 spoke | |
n.(车轮的)辐条;轮辐;破坏某人的计划;阻挠某人的行动 v.讲,谈(speak的过去式);说;演说;从某种观点来说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 unintelligible | |
adj.无法了解的,难解的,莫明其妙的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 intelligible | |
adj.可理解的,明白易懂的,清楚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 animate | |
v.赋于生命,鼓励;adj.有生命的,有生气的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 engenders | |
v.产生(某形势或状况),造成,引起( engender的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 malignantly | |
怀恶意地; 恶毒地; 有害地; 恶性地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 ammunition | |
n.军火,弹药 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 extremities | |
n.端点( extremity的名词复数 );尽头;手和足;极窘迫的境地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 predecessors | |
n.前任( predecessor的名词复数 );前辈;(被取代的)原有事物;前身 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 celestial | |
adj.天体的;天上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 engendered | |
v.产生(某形势或状况),造成,引起( engender的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 bedlam | |
n.混乱,骚乱;疯人院 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 commentators | |
n.评论员( commentator的名词复数 );时事评论员;注释者;实况广播员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 diligently | |
ad.industriously;carefully | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 reluctance | |
n.厌恶,讨厌,勉强,不情愿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 platonic | |
adj.精神的;柏拉图(哲学)的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 absurdities | |
n.极端无理性( absurdity的名词复数 );荒谬;谬论;荒谬的行为 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 virtues | |
美德( virtue的名词复数 ); 德行; 优点; 长处 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 invoke | |
v.求助于(神、法律);恳求,乞求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 peripatetic | |
adj.漫游的,逍遥派的,巡回的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 penetrating | |
adj.(声音)响亮的,尖锐的adj.(气味)刺激的adj.(思想)敏锐的,有洞察力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 attentively | |
adv.聚精会神地;周到地;谛;凝神 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 implore | |
vt.乞求,恳求,哀求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 candidly | |
adv.坦率地,直率而诚恳地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 demonstrations | |
证明( demonstration的名词复数 ); 表明; 表达; 游行示威 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 infinity | |
n.无限,无穷,大量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 penetrate | |
v.透(渗)入;刺入,刺穿;洞察,了解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 penetrates | |
v.穿过( penetrate的第三人称单数 );刺入;了解;渗透 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 edifice | |
n.宏伟的建筑物(如宫殿,教室) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 profundity | |
n.渊博;深奥,深刻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 darting | |
v.投掷,投射( dart的现在分词 );向前冲,飞奔 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |