It is at once evident, that rent is the effect of a monopoly; though the monopoly is a natural one, which may be regulated, which may even be held as a trust for the community generally, but which cannot be prevented from existing. The reason why landowners are able to require rent for their land, is that it is a commodity which many want, and which no one can obtain but from them. If all the land of the country belonged to one person, he could fix the rent at his pleasure. The whole people would be dependent on his will for the necessaries of life, and he might make what conditions he chose. This is the actual state of things in those Oriental kingdoms in which the land is considered the property of the state. Rent is then confounded with taxation4, and the despot may exact the utmost which the unfortunate cultivators have to give. Indeed, the exclusive possessor of the land of a country could not well be other than despot of it. The effect would be much the same if the land belonged to so few people, that they could, and did, act together as one man, and fix the rent by agreement among themselves. This case, however, is nowhere known to exist: and the only remaining supposition is that of free competition; the landowners being supposed to be, as in fact they are, too numerous to combine.
§2. A thing which is limited in quantity, even though its possessors do not act in concert, is still a monopolized5 article. But even when monopolized, a thing which is the gift of nature, and requires no labour or outlay6 as the condition of its existence, will, if there be competition among the holders7 of it, command a price, only if it exists in less quantity than the demand. If the whole land of a country were required for cultivation8, all of it might yield a rent. But in no country of any extent do the wants of the population require that all the land, which is capable of cultivation, should be cultivated. The food and other agricultural produce which the people need, and which they are willing and able to pay for at a price which remunerates the grower, may always be obtained without cultivating all the land; sometimes without cultivating more than a small part of it; the lands most easily cultivated being preferred in a very early stage of society; the most fertile, or those in the most convenient situations, in a more advanced state. There is always, therefore, some land which cannot, in existing circumstances, pay any rent; and no land ever pays rent, unless, in point of fertility or situation, it belongs to those superior kinds which exist in less quantity than the demand-which cannot be made to yield all the produce required for the community, unless on terms still less advantageous9 than the resort to less favoured soils.
There is land, such as the deserts of Arabia, which will yield nothing to any amount of labour; and there is land, like some of our hard sandy heaths, which would produce something, but, in the present state of the soil, not enough to defray the expenses of production. Such lands, unless by some application of chemistry to agriculture still remaining to be invented, cannot be cultivated for profit, unless some one actually creates a soil, by spreading new ingredients over the surface, or mixing them with the existing materials. If ingredients fitted for this purpose exist in the subsoil, or close at hand, the improvement even of the most unpromising spots may answer as a speculation10: but if those ingredients are costly11, and must be brought from a distance, it will seldom answer to do this for the sake of profit, though the “magic of property” will sometimes effect it. Land which cannot possibly yield a profit, is sometimes cultivated at a loss, the cultivators having their wants partially12 supplied from other sources; as in the case of paupers13, and some monasteries14 or charitable institutions, among which may be reckoned the Poor Colonies of Belgium. The worst land which can be cultivated as a means of subsistence, is that which will just replace the seed, and the food of the labourers employed on it, together with what Dr. Chalmers calls their secondaries; that is, the labourers required for supplying them with tools, and with the remaining necessaries of life. Whether any given land is capable of doing more than this, is not a question of political economy, but of physical fact. The supposition leaves nothing for profits, nor anything for the labourers except necessaries: the land, therefore, can only be cultivated by the labourers themselves, or else at a pecuniary15 loss: and a fortiori, cannot in any contingency16 afford a rent. The worst land which can be cultivated as an investment for capital, is that which, after replacing the seed, not only feeds the agricultural labourers and their secondaries, but affords them the current rate of wages, which may extend to much more than mere17 necessaries; and leaves for those who have advanced the wages of these two classes of labourers, a surplus equal to the profit they could have expected from any other employment of their capital. Whether any given land can do more than this, is not merely a physical question, but depends partly on the market value of agricultural produce. What the land can do for the labourers and for the capitalist, beyond feeding all whom it directly or indirectly18 employs, of course depends upon what the remainder of the produce can be sold for. The higher the market value of produce, the lower are the soils to which cultivation can descend19, consistently with affording to the capital employed, the ordinary rate of profit.
As, however, differences of fertility slide into one another by insensible gradations; and differences of accessibility, that is, of distance from markets, do the same; and since there is land so barren that it could not pay for its cultivation at any price; it is evident that, whatever the price may be, there must in any extensive region be some land which at that price will just pay the wages of the cultivators, and yield to the capital employed the ordinary profit, and no more. Until, therefore, the price rises higher, or until some improvement raises that particular land to a higher place in the scale of fertility, it cannot pay any rent. It is evident, however, that the community needs the produce of this quality of land; since if the lands more fertile or better situated20 than it, could have sufficed to supply the wants of society, the price would not have risen so high as to render its cultivation profitable. This land, therefore, will be cultivated; and we may lay it down as a principle that so long as any of the land of a country which is fit for cultivation, and not withheld21 from it by legal or other factitious obstacles, is not cultivated, the worst land in actual cultivation (in point of fertility and situation together) pays no rent.
§3. If, then, of the land in cultivation, the part which yields least return to the labour and capital employed on it gives only the ordinary profit of capital, without leaving anything for rent; a standard is afforded for estimating the amount of rent which will be yielded by all other land. Any land yields just as much more than the ordinary profits of stock, as it yields more than what is returned by the worst land in cultivation. The surplus is what the farmer can afford to pay as rent to the landlord; and since, if he did not so pay it, he would receive more than the ordinary rate of profit, the competition of other capitalists, that competition which equalizes the profits of different capitals, will enable the landlord to appropriate it. The rent, therefore, which any land will yield, is the excess of its produce, beyond what would be returned to the same capital if employed on the worst land in cultivation. This is not, and never was pretended to be, the limit of metayer rents, or of cottier rents; but it is the limit of farmers’ rents. No land rented to a capitalist farmer will permanently22 yield more than this; and when it yields less, it is because the landlord foregoes a part of what, if he chose, he could obtain.
This is the theory of rent, first propounded23 at the end of the last century by Dr. Anderson, and which, neglected at the time, was almost simultaneously24 rediscovered, twenty years later, by Sir Edward West, Mr. Malthus, and Mr. Ricardo. It is one of the cardinal25 doctrines26 of political economy; and until it was understood, no consistent explanation could be given of many of the more complicated industrial phenomena28. The evidence of its truth will be manifested with a great increase of clearness, when we come to trace the laws of the phenomena of Value and Price. Until that is done, it is not possible to free the doctrine27 from every difficulty which may present itself, nor perhaps to convey, to those previously29 unacquainted with the subject, more than a general apprehension30 of the reasoning by which the theorem is arrived at. Some, however, of the objections commonly made to it, admit of a complete answer even in the present stage of our inquiries31.
It has been denied that there can be any land in cultivation which pays no rent; because landlords (it is contended) would not allow their land to be occupied without payment. Those who lay any stress on this as an objection, must think that land of the quality which can but just pay for its cultivation, lies together in large masses, detached from any land of better quality. If an estate consisted wholly of this land, or of this and still worse, it is likely enough that the owner would not give the use of it for nothing; he would probably (if a rich man) prefer keeping it for other purposes, as for exercise, or ornament32, or perhaps as a game preserve. No farmer could afford to offer him anything for it, for purposes of culture; though something would probably be obtained for the use of its natural pasture, or other spontaneous produce. Even such land, however, would not necessarily remain uncultivated. It might be farmed by the proprietor2; no unfrequent case even in England. Portions of it might be granted as temporary allotments to labouring families, either from philanthropic motives33, or to save the poor-rate; or occupation might be allowed to squatters, free of rent, in the hope that their labour might give it value at some future period. Both these cases are of quite ordinary occurrence. So that even if an estate were wholly composed of the worst land capable of profitable cultivation, it would not necessarily lie uncultivated because it could pay no rent. Inferior land, however, does not usually occupy, without interruption, many square miles of ground; it is dispersed34 here and there, with patches of better land intermixed, and the same person who rents the better land, obtains along with it inferior soils which alternate with it. He pays a rent, nominally35 for the whole farm, but calculated on the produce of these parts alone (however small a portion of the whole) which are capable of returning more than the common rate of profit. It is thus scientifically true, that the remaining parts pay no rent.
§4. Let us, however, suppose that there were a validity in this objection, which can by no means be conceded to it; that when the demand of the community had forced up food to such a price as would remunerate the expense of producing it from a certain quantity of soil, it happened nevertheless that all the soil of that quality was withheld from cultivation, by the obstinacy37 of the owners in demanding a rent for it, not nominal36, nor trifling38, but sufficiently39 onerous40 to be a material item in the calculations of a farmer. What would then happen? Merely that the increase of produce, which the wants of society required, would for the time be obtained wholly (as it always is partially), not by an extension of cultivation, but by an increased application of labour and capital to land already cultivated.
Now we have already seen that this increased application of capital, other things being unaltered, is always attended with a smaller proportional return. We are not to suppose some new agricultural invention made precisely41 at this juncture42; nor a sudden extension of agricultural skill and knowledge, bringing into more general practice, just then, inventions already in partial use. We are to suppose no change, except a demand for more corn, and a consequent rise of its price. The rise of price enables measures to be taken for increasing the produce, which could not have been taken with profit at the previous price. The farmer uses more expensive manures; or manures land which he formerly43 left to nature; or procures44 lime or marl from a distance, as a dressing45 for the soil; or pulverizes46 or weeds it more thoroughly47; or drains, irrigates48, or subsoils portions of it, which at former prices would not have paid the cost of the operation; and so forth49. These things, or some of them, are done, when, more food being wanted, cultivation has no means of expanding itself upon new lands. And when the impulse is given to extract an increased amount of produce from the soil, the farmer or improver will only consider whether the outlay he makes for the purpose will be returned to him with the ordinary profit, and not whether any surplus will remain for rent. Even, therefore, if it were the fact, that there is never any land taken into cultivation, for which rent, and that too of an amount worth taking into consideration, was not paid; it would be true, nevertheless, that there is always some agricultural capital which pays no rent, because it returns nothing beyond the ordinary rate of profit: this capital being the portion of capital last applied50-that to which the last addition to the produce was due: or (to express the essentials of the case in one phrase), that which is applied in the least favourable51 circumstances. But the same amount of demand, and the same price, which enable this least productive portion of capital barely to replace itself with the ordinary profit, enable every other portion to yield a surplus proportioned to the advantage it possesses. And this surplus it is, which competition enables the landlord to appropriate. The rent of all land is measured by the excess of the return to the whole capital employed on it, above what is necessary to replace the capital with the ordinary rate of profit, or in other words, above what the same capital would yield if it were all employed in as disadvantageous circumstances as the least productive portion of it; whether that least productive portion of capital is rendered so by being employed on the worst soil, or by being expended52 in extorting54 more produce from land which already yielded as much as it could be made to part with on easier terms.
It is not pretended that the facts of any concrete case conform with absolute precision to this or any other scientific principle. We must never forget that the truths of political economy are truths only in the rough: they have the certainty, but not the precision, of exact science. It is not, for example, strictly55 true that a farmer will cultivate no land, and apply no capital, which returns less than the ordinary profit. He will expect the ordinary profit on the bulk of his capital. But when he has cast in his lot with his farm, and bartered56 his skill and exertions57, once for all, against what the farm will yield to him, he will probably be willing to expend53 capital on it (for an immediate58 return) in any manner which will afford him a surplus profit, however small, beyond the value of the risk, and the interest which he must pay for the capital if borrowed, or can get for it elsewhere if it is his own. But a new farmer, entering on the land, would make his calculations differently, and would not commence unless he could expect the full rate of ordinary profit on all the capital which he intended embarking59 in the enterprise. Again, prices may range higher or lower during the currency of a lease, than was expected when the contract was made, and the land, therefore, may be over or under-rented: and even when the lease expires, the landlord may be unwilling60 to grant a necessary diminution61 of rent, and the farmer, rather than relinquish62 his occupation, or seek a farm elsewhere when all are occupied, may consent to go on paying too high a rent. Irregularities like these we must always expect; it is impossible in political economy to obtain general theorems embracing the complications of circumstances which may affect the result in an individual case. When, too, the farmer class, having but little capital, cultivate for subsistence rather than for profit, and do not think of quitting their farm while they are able to live by it, their rents approximate to the character of cottier rents, and may be forced up by competition (if the number of competitors exceeds the number of farms) beyond the amount which will leave to the farmer the ordinary rate of profit. The laws which we are enabled to lay down respecting rents, profits, wages, prices, are only true in so far as the persons concerned are free from the influence of any other motives than those arising from the general circumstances of the case, and are guided, as to those, by the ordinary mercantile estimate of profit and loss. Applying this twofold supposition to the case of farmers and landlords, it will be true that the farmer requires the ordinary rate of profit on the whole of his capital; that whatever it returns to him beyond this he is obliged to pay to the landlord, but will not consent to pay more; that there is a portion of capital applied to agriculture in such circumstances of productiveness as to yield only the ordinary profits; and that the difference between the produce of this, and any other capital of similar amount, is the measure of the tribute which that other capital can and will pay, under the name of rent, to the landlord. This constitutes a law of rent, as near the truth as such a law can possibly be: though of course modified or disturbed in individual cases, by pending63 contracts, individual miscalculations, the influence of habit, and even the particular feelings and dispositions64 of the persons concerned.
§5. A remark is often made, which must not here be omitted, though, I think, more importance has been attached to it than it merits. Under the name of rent, many payments are commonly included, which are not a remuneration for the original powers of the land itself, but for capital expended on it. The additional rent which land yields in consequence of this outlay of capital, should, in the opinion of some writers, be regarded as profit, not rent. But before this can be admitted, a distinction must be made. The annual payment by a tenant65 almost always includes a consideration for the use of the buildings on the farm; not only barns, stables, and other outhouses, but a house to live in, not to speak of fences and the like. The landlord will ask, and the tenant give, for these, whatever is considered sufficient to yield the ordinary profit, or rather (risk and trouble being here out of the question) the ordinary interest, on the value of the buildings: that is, not on what it has cost to erect66 them, but on what it would now cost to erect others as good: the tenant being bound, in addition, to leave them in as good repair as he found them, for otherwise a much larger payment than simple interest would of course be required from him. These buildings are as distinct a thing from the farm as the stock or the timber on it; and what is paid for them can no more be called rent of land, than a payment for cattle would be, if it were the custom that the landlord should stock the farm for the tenant. The buildings, like the cattle, are not land, but capital, regularly consumed and reproduced; and all payments made in consideration for them are properly interest.
But with regard to capital actually sunk in improvements, and not requiring periodical renewal67, but spent once for all in giving the land a permanent increase of productiveness, it appears to me that the return made to such capital loses altogether the character of profits, and is governed by the principles of rent. It is true that a landlord will not expend capital in improving his estate, unless he expects from the improvement an increase of income surpassing the interest of his outlay. Prospectively68, this increase of income may be regarded as profit; but when the expense has been incurred69, and the improvement made, the rent of the improved land is governed by the same rules as that of the unimproved. Equally fertile land commands an equal rent, whether its fertility is natural or acquired; and I cannot think that the incomes of those who own the Bedford Level or the Lincolnshire Wolds ought to be called profit and not rent because those lands would have been worth next to nothing unless capital had been expended on them. The owners are not capitalists, but landlords; they have parted with their capital; it is consumed, destroyed; and neither is, nor is to be, returned to them, like the capital of a farmer or manufacturer, from what it produces. In lieu of it they now have land of a certain richness, which yields the same rent, and by the operation of the same causes, as if it had possessed70 from the beginning the degree of fertility which has been artificially given to it.
Some writers, in particular Mr. H.C. Carey, take away, still more completely than I have attempted to do, the distinction between these two sources of rent, by rejecting one of them altogether, and considering all rent as the effect of capital expended. In proof of this, Mr. Carey contends that the whole pecuniary value of all the land in any country, in England for instance, or in the United States, does not amount to anything approaching to the sum which has been laid out, or which it would even now be necessary to lay out, in order to bring the country to its present condition from a state of primaeval forest. This startling statement has been seized on by M. Bastiat and others, as a means of making out a stronger case than could otherwise be made in defence of property in land. Mr. Carey’s proposition, in its most obvious meaning, is equivalent to saying, that if there were suddenly added to the lands of England an unreclaimed territory of equal natural fertility, it would not be worth the while of the inhabitants of England to reclaim71 it: because the profits of the operation would not be equal to the ordinary interest on the capital expended. To which assertion if any answer could be supposed to be required, it would suffice to remark, that land not of equal but of greatly inferior quality to that previously cultivated, is continually reclaimed72 in England, at an expense which the subsequently accruing73 rent is sufficient to replace completely in a small number of years. The doctrine, moreover, is totally opposed to Mr. Carey’s own economical opinions. No one maintains more strenuously74 than Mr. Carey the undoubted truth, that as society advances in population, wealth, and combination of labour, land constantly rises in value and price. This, however, could not possibly be true, if the present value of land were less than the expense of clearing it and making it fit for cultivation; for it must have been worth this immediately after it was cleared; and according to Mr. Carey it has been rising in value ever since.
When, however, Mr. Carey asserts that the whole land of any country is not now worth the capital which has been expended on it, he does not mean that each particular estate is worth less than what has been laid out in improving it, and that, to the proprietors, the improvement of the land has been, in the final result, a miscalculation. He means, not that the land of Great Britain would not now sell for what has been laid out upon it, but that it would not sell for that amount plus the expense of making all the roads, canals, and railways. This is probably true, but is no more to the purpose, and no more important in political economy, than if the statement had been, that it would not sell for the sums laid out on it plus the national debt, or plus the cost of the French Revolutionary war, or any other expense incurred for a real or imaginary public advantage. The roads, railways, and canals were not constructed to give value to land: on the contrary, their natural effect was to lower its value, by rendering75 other and rival lands accessible: and the landholders of the southern counties actually petitioned Parliament against the turnpike roads on this very account.
The tendency of improved communications is to lower existing rents, by trenching on the monopoly of the land nearest to the places where large numbers of consumers are assembled. Roads and canals are not intended to raise the value of the land which already supplies the markets, but (among other purposes) to cheapen the supply, by letting in the produce of other and more distant lands; and the more effectually this purpose is attained76, the lower rent will be. If we could imagine that the railways and canals of the United States, instead of only cheapening communication, did their business so effectually as to annihilate77 cost of carriage altogether, and enable the produce of Michigan to reach the market of New York as quickly and as cheaply as the produce of Long Island-the whole value of all the land of the United States (except such as lies convenient for building) would be annihilated78; or rather, the best would only sell for the expense of clearing, and the government tax of a dollar and a quarter per acre; since land in Michigan, equal to the best in the United States, may be had in unlimited79 abundance by that amount of outlay. But it is strange that Mr. Carey should think this fact inconsistent with the Ricardo theory of rent. Admitting all that he asserts, it is still true that as long as there is land which yields no rent, the land which does yield rent, does so in consequence of some advantage which it enjoys, in fertility or vicinity to markets, over the other; and the measure of its advantage is also the measure of its rent. And the cause of its yielding rent, is that it possesses a natural monopoly; the quantity of land, as favourably80 circumstanced as itself, not being sufficient to supply the market. These propositions constitute the theory of rent, laid down by Ricardo; and if they are true, I cannot see that it signifies much whether the rent which the land yields at the present time, is greater or less than the interest of the capital which has been laid out to raise its value, together with the interest of the capital which has been laid out to lower its value.
Mr. Carey’s objection, however, has somewhat more of ingenuity81 than the arguments commonly met with against the theory of rent; a theorem which may he called the pons asinorum of political economy, for there are, I am inclined to think, few persons who have refused their assent82 to it except from not having thoroughly understood it. The loose and inaccurate83 way in which it is often apprehended84 by those who affect to refute it, is very remarkable85. Many, for instance, have imputed86 absurdity87 to Mr. Ricardo’s theory, because it is absurd to say that the cultivation of inferior land is the cause of rent on the superior. Mr. Ricardo does not say that it is the cultivation of inferior land, but the necessity of cultivating it, from the insufficiency of the superior land to feed a growing population: between which and the proposition imputed to him there is no less a difference than that between demand and supply. Others again allege88 as an objection against Ricardo, that if all land were of equal fertility, it might still yield a rent. But Ricardo says precisely the same. He says that if all lands were equally fertile, those which are nearer to their market than others, and are therefore less burthened with cost of carriage, would yield a rent equivalent to the advantage; and that the land yielding no rent would then be, not the least fertile, but the least advantageously situated, which the wants of the community required to be brought into cultivation. It is also distinctly a portion of Ricardo’s doctrine, that even apart from differences of situation, the land of a country supposed to be of uniform fertility would, all of it, on a certain supposition, pay rent: namely, if the demand of the community required that it should all be cultivated, and cultivated beyond the point at which a further application of capital begins to be attended with a smaller proportional return. It would be impossible to show that, except by forcible exaction89, the whole land of a country can yield a rent on any other supposition.
§6. After this view of the nature and causes of rent, let us turn back to the subject of profits, and bring up for reconsideration one of the propositions laid down in the last chapter. We there stated, that the advances of the capitalist, or in other words, the expenses of production, consist solely90 in wages of labour; that whatever portion of the outlay is not wages, is previous profit, and whatever is not previous profit, is wages. Rent, however, being an element which it is impossible to resolve into either profits or wages, we were obliged, for the moment, to assume that the capitalist is not required to pay rent-to give an equivalent for the use of an appropriated natural agent: and I undertook to show in the proper place, that this is an allowable supposition, and that rent does not really form any part of the expenses of production, or of the advances of the capitalist. The grounds on which this assertion was made are now apparent. It is true that all tenant farmers, and many other classes of producers, pay rent. But we have now seen, that whoever cultivates land, paying a rent for it, gets in return for his rent an instrument of superior power to other instruments of the same kind for which no rent is paid. The superiority of the instrument is in exact proportion to the rent paid for it. If a few persons had steam-engines of superior power to all others in existence, but limited by physical laws to a number short of the demand, the rent which a manufacturer would be willing to pay for one of these steam-engines could not he looked upon as an addition to his outlay, because by the use of it he would save in his other expenses the equivalent of what it cost him: without it he could not do the same quantity of work, unless at an additional expense equal to the rent. The same thing is true of land. The real expenses of production are those incurred on the worst land, or by the capital employed in the least favourable circumstances. This land or capital pays, as we have seen, no rent; but the expenses to which it is subject, cause all other land or agricultural capital to be subjected to an equivalent expense in the form of rent. Whoever does pay rent gets back its full value in extra advantages, and the rent which he pays does not place him in a worse position than, but only in the same position as, his fellow-producer who pays no rent, but whose instrument is one of inferior efficiency.
We have now completed the exposition of the laws which regulate the distribution of the produce of land, labour, and capital, as far as it is possible to discuss those laws independently of the instrumentality by which in a civilized91 society the distribution is effected; the machinery92 of Exchange and Price. The more complete elucidation93 and final confirmation94 of the laws which we have laid down, and the deduction95 of their most important consequences, must be preceded by an explanation of the nature and working of that machinery-a subject so extensive and complicated as to require a separate Book.
点击收听单词发音
1 requisites | |
n.必要的事物( requisite的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 proprietor | |
n.所有人;业主;经营者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 proprietors | |
n.所有人,业主( proprietor的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 taxation | |
n.征税,税收,税金 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 monopolized | |
v.垄断( monopolize的过去式和过去分词 );独占;专卖;专营 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 outlay | |
n.费用,经费,支出;v.花费 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 holders | |
支持物( holder的名词复数 ); 持有者; (支票等)持有人; 支托(或握持)…之物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 cultivation | |
n.耕作,培养,栽培(法),养成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 advantageous | |
adj.有利的;有帮助的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 speculation | |
n.思索,沉思;猜测;投机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 costly | |
adj.昂贵的,价值高的,豪华的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 partially | |
adv.部分地,从某些方面讲 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 paupers | |
n.穷人( pauper的名词复数 );贫民;贫穷 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 monasteries | |
修道院( monastery的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 pecuniary | |
adj.金钱的;金钱上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 contingency | |
n.意外事件,可能性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 indirectly | |
adv.间接地,不直接了当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 descend | |
vt./vi.传下来,下来,下降 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 situated | |
adj.坐落在...的,处于某种境地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 withheld | |
withhold过去式及过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 permanently | |
adv.永恒地,永久地,固定不变地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 propounded | |
v.提出(问题、计划等)供考虑[讨论],提议( propound的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 simultaneously | |
adv.同时发生地,同时进行地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 cardinal | |
n.(天主教的)红衣主教;adj.首要的,基本的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 doctrines | |
n.教条( doctrine的名词复数 );教义;学说;(政府政策的)正式声明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 apprehension | |
n.理解,领悟;逮捕,拘捕;忧虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 inquiries | |
n.调查( inquiry的名词复数 );疑问;探究;打听 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 ornament | |
v.装饰,美化;n.装饰,装饰物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 dispersed | |
adj. 被驱散的, 被分散的, 散布的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 nominally | |
在名义上,表面地; 应名儿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 nominal | |
adj.名义上的;(金额、租金)微不足道的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 obstinacy | |
n.顽固;(病痛等)难治 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 trifling | |
adj.微不足道的;没什么价值的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 sufficiently | |
adv.足够地,充分地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 onerous | |
adj.繁重的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 juncture | |
n.时刻,关键时刻,紧要关头 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 formerly | |
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 procures | |
v.(努力)取得, (设法)获得( procure的第三人称单数 );拉皮条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 dressing | |
n.(食物)调料;包扎伤口的用品,敷料 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 pulverizes | |
v.将…弄碎( pulverize的第三人称单数 );将…弄成粉末或尘埃;摧毁;粉碎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 thoroughly | |
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 irrigates | |
灌溉( irrigate的第三人称单数 ); 冲洗(伤口) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 favourable | |
adj.赞成的,称赞的,有利的,良好的,顺利的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 expended | |
v.花费( expend的过去式和过去分词 );使用(钱等)做某事;用光;耗尽 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 expend | |
vt.花费,消费,消耗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 extorting | |
v.敲诈( extort的现在分词 );曲解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 bartered | |
v.作物物交换,以货换货( barter的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 exertions | |
n.努力( exertion的名词复数 );费力;(能力、权力等的)运用;行使 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 embarking | |
乘船( embark的现在分词 ); 装载; 从事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 unwilling | |
adj.不情愿的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 diminution | |
n.减少;变小 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 relinquish | |
v.放弃,撤回,让与,放手 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 pending | |
prep.直到,等待…期间;adj.待定的;迫近的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 dispositions | |
安排( disposition的名词复数 ); 倾向; (财产、金钱的)处置; 气质 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 tenant | |
n.承租人;房客;佃户;v.租借,租用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 erect | |
n./v.树立,建立,使竖立;adj.直立的,垂直的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 renewal | |
adj.(契约)延期,续订,更新,复活,重来 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 prospectively | |
adv.预期; 前瞻性; 潜在; 可能 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 incurred | |
[医]招致的,遭受的; incur的过去式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 reclaim | |
v.要求归还,收回;开垦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 reclaimed | |
adj.再生的;翻造的;收复的;回收的v.开拓( reclaim的过去式和过去分词 );要求收回;从废料中回收(有用的材料);挽救 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 accruing | |
v.增加( accrue的现在分词 );(通过自然增长)产生;获得;(使钱款、债务)积累 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 strenuously | |
adv.奋发地,费力地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 rendering | |
n.表现,描写 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 annihilate | |
v.使无效;毁灭;取消 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 annihilated | |
v.(彻底)消灭( annihilate的过去式和过去分词 );使无效;废止;彻底击溃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 unlimited | |
adj.无限的,不受控制的,无条件的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 favourably | |
adv. 善意地,赞成地 =favorably | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 ingenuity | |
n.别出心裁;善于发明创造 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 assent | |
v.批准,认可;n.批准,认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 inaccurate | |
adj.错误的,不正确的,不准确的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 apprehended | |
逮捕,拘押( apprehend的过去式和过去分词 ); 理解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 remarkable | |
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 imputed | |
v.把(错误等)归咎于( impute的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 absurdity | |
n.荒谬,愚蠢;谬论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 allege | |
vt.宣称,申述,主张,断言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 exaction | |
n.强求,强征;杂税 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 civilized | |
a.有教养的,文雅的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 machinery | |
n.(总称)机械,机器;机构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 elucidation | |
n.说明,阐明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 confirmation | |
n.证实,确认,批准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 deduction | |
n.减除,扣除,减除额;推论,推理,演绎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |