In controversies relating to progress it is asked whether the work of man be fertile or sterile4, whether it be lost or preserved, whether history have an end, and if so of what sort, whether this end be attainable6 in time or only in the infinite, whether history be progress or regress, or an interchange between progress and regress, greatness and decadence7, whether good or evil prevail in it, and the like. When these questions have been considered with a little attention we shall see that they resolve themselves substantially into three points: the conception of development, that of end, and that of value. That is to say, they are concerned with the whole of reality, and with history only when it is[Pg 84] precisely8 the whole of reality. For this reason they do not belong to supposed particular sciences, to the philosophy of history, or to sociology, but to philosophy and to history in so far as it is philosophy. When the ordinary current terminology9 has been translated into philosophical10 terms it calls forth11 immediately the thesis, antithesis12, and synthesis by means of which those problems have been thought and solved during the course of philosophy, to which the reader desirous of instruction must be referred. We can only mention here that the conception of reality as development is nothing but the synthesis of the two one-sided opposites, consisting of permanency without change and of change without permanency, of an identity without diversity and of a diversity without identity, for development is a perpetual surpassing, which is at the same time a perpetual conservation. From this point of view one of the conceptions that has had the greatest vogue13 in historical books, that of historical circles, is revealed as an equivocal attempt to issue forth from a double one-sidedness and a falling back into it, owing to an equivocation14. Because either the series of circles is conceived as composed of identicals and we have only permanency, or it is conceived as of things diverse and we have only change. But if, on the contrary, we conceive it as circularity that is perpetually identical and at the same time perpetually diverse, in this sense it coincides with the conception of development itself.
In like manner, the opposite theses, as to the attainment15 or the impossibility of attainment of the end of history, reveal their common defect of positing16 the end as extrinsic17 to history, conceiving of it either as that which can be reached in time (progressus ad finitum),[Pg 85] or as that which can never be attained18, but only infinitely19 approximated (progressus ad infinitum). But where the end has been correctly conceived as internal—that is to say, all one with development itself—we must conclude that it is attained at every instant, and at the same time not attained, because every attainment is the formation of a new prospect20, whence we have at every moment the satisfaction of possession, and arising from this the dissatisfaction which drives us to seek a new possession.[1]
Finally, the conceptions of history as a passage from evil to good (progress), or from good to evil (decadence, regression), take their origin from the same error of entifying and making extrinsic good and evil, joy and sorrow (which are the dialectical construction of reality itself). To unite them in the eclectic conception of an alternation of good and evil, of progress and regress, is incorrect. The true solution is that of progress understood not as a passage from evil to good, as though from one state to another, but as the passage from the good to the better, in which the evil is the good itself seen in the light of the better.
These are all philosophical solutions which are at variance21 with the superficial theses of controversialists (dictated to them by sentimental22 motives23 or imaginative combinations, really mythological25 or resulting in mythologies26), to the same extent that they are in accordance with profound human convictions and with the tireless toil27, the trust, the courage, which constitute their ethical28 manifestations29.
By drawing the consequences of the dialectical[Pg 86] conception of progress something more immediately effective can be achieved in respect to the practice and history of historiography. For we find in that conception the origin of a historical maxim30, in the mouth of every one, yet frequently misunderstood and frequently violated—that is to say, that to history pertains31 not to judge, but to explain, and that it should be not subjective32 but objective.
Misunderstood, because the judging in question is often taken in the sense of logical judgment33, of that judgment which is thinking itself, and the subjectivity34, which would thus be excluded, would be neither more nor less than the subjectivity of thought. In consequence of this misunderstanding we hear historians being advised to purge35 themselves of theories, to refrain from the disputes arising from them, to restrict themselves to facts, collecting, arranging, and squeezing out the sap (even by the statistical36 method). It is impossible to follow such advice as this, as may easily be seen, for such 'abstention from thought' reveals itself as really abstention from 'seriousness of thought,' as a surreptitious attaching of value to the most vulgar and contradictory38 thoughts, transmitted by tradition, wandering about idly in the mind, or flashing out as the result of momentary39 caprice. The maxim is altogether false, understood or misunderstood in this way, and it must be taken by its opposite—namely, that history must always judge strictly40, and that it must always be energetically subjective without allowing itself to be confused by the conflicts in which thought engages or by the risks that it runs. For it is thought itself, and thought alone, which gets over its own difficulties and dangers, without falling even here into that frivolous41 eclecticism42 which tries to find a middle term between[Pg 87] our judgment and that of others, and suggests various neutral and insipid43 forms of judgment.
But the true and legitimate44 meaning, the original motive24 for that 'judging,' that 'subjectivity,' which it condemns46, is that history should not apply to the deeds and the personages that are its material the qualifications of good and evil, as though there really were good and evil facts in the world, people who are good and people who are evil. And it is certainly not to be denied that innumerable historiographers, or those who claim to be historiographers, have really striven and still strive along those lines, in the vain and presumptuous47 attempt to reward the good and punish the evil, to qualify historical epochs as representing progress or decadence—in a word, to settle what is good and what is evil, as though it were a question of separating one element from another in a compound, hydrogen from, oxygen.
Whoever desires to observe intrinsically the above maxim, and by doing so to set himself in accordance with the dialectic conception of progress, must in truth look upon every trace or vestige49 of propositions affirming evil, regression, or decadence as real facts, as a sign of imperfection—in a word, he must condemn45 every trace or vestige of negative judgments50. If the course of history is not the passage from evil to good, or alternative good and evil, but the passage from the good to the better, if history should explain and not condemn, it will pronounce only positive judgments, and will forge chains of good, so solid and so closely linked that it will not be possible to introduce into them even a little link of evil or to interpose empty spaces, which in so far as they are empty would not represent good but evil. A fact that seems to be only evil, an epoch48 that appears[Pg 88] to be one of complete decadence, can be nothing but a non-historical fact—that is to say, one which has not been historically treated, not penetrated51 by thought, and which has remained the prey52 of sentiment and imagination.
Whence comes the phenomenology of good and evil, of sin and repentance53, of decadence and resurrection, save from the consciousness of the agent, from the act which is in labour to produce a new form of life?[2] And in that act the adversary54 who opposed us is in the wrong; the state from which we wish to escape, and from which we are escaping, is unhappy; the new one toward which we are tending becomes symbolized55 as a dreamed-of felicity to be attained, or as a past condition to restore, which is therefore most beautiful in recollection (which here is not recollection, but imagination). Every one knows how these things present them-selves to us in the course of history, manifesting themselves in poetry, in Utopias, in stories with a moral, in detractions, in apologies, in myths of love, of hate, and the like. To the heretics of the Middle Ages and to the Protestant reformers the condition of the primitive56 Christians57 seemed to be most lovely and most holy, that of papal Christians most evil and debased. The Sparta of Lycurgus and the Rome of Cincinnatus seemed to the Jacobins to be as admirable as France under the Carlovingians and the Capetians was detestable. The humanists looked upon the lives of the ancient poets and sages59 as luminous60 and the life of the Middle Ages as dense61 darkness. Even in times near our own has been witnessed the glorification62 of the Lombard communes and the depreciation63 of the Holy Roman Empire, and the very opposite of this, according as the facts relating to these[Pg 89] historical events were reflected in the consciousness of an Italian longing64 for the independence of Italy or of a German upholding the holy German empire of Prussian hegemony. And this will always happen, because such is the phenomenology of the practical consciousness, and these practical valuations will always be present to some extent in the works of historians. As works, these are not and cannot ever be pure history, quintessential history; if in no other way, then in their phrasing and use of metaphors65 they will reflect the repercussion66 of practical needs and efforts directed toward the future. But the historical consciousness, as such, is logical and not practical consciousness, and indeed makes the other its object; history once lived has become in it thought, and the antitheses67 of will and feeling that formerly68 offered resistance have no longer a place in thought.
For if there are no good and evil facts, but facts that are always good when understood in their intimate being and concreteness, there are not opposite sides, but that wider side that embraces both the adversaries69 and which happens just to be historical consideration. Historical consideration, therefore, recognizes as of equal right the Church of the catacombs and that of Gregory VII, the tribunes of the Roman people and the feudal70 barons71, the Lombard League and the Emperor Barbarossa. History never metes72 out justice, but always justifies73; she could not carry out the former act without making herself unjust—that is to say, confounding thought with life, taking the attractions and repulsions of sentiment for the judgments of thought.
Poetry is satisfied with the expression of sentiment, and it is worthy74 of note that a considerable historian, Schlosser, wishing to reserve for himself the right and duty of[Pg 90] judging historical facts with Kantian austerity and abstraction, kept his eyes fixed75 on the Divine Comedy—that is to say, a poetical76 work—as his model of treatment. And since there are poetical elements in all myths, we understand why the conception of history known as dualistic—that is to say, of history as composed of two currents, which mix but never resolve in one another their waters of good and evil, truth and error, rationality and irrationality—should have formed a conspicuous77 part, not only of the Christian58 religion, but also of the mythologies (for they really are such) of humanism and of illuminism. But the detection of this problem of the duality of values and its solution in the superior unity78 of the conception of development is the work of the nineteenth century, which on this account and on account of other solutions of the same kind (certainly not on account of its philological79 and arch?ological richness, which was relatively80 common to the four preceding centuries) has been well called 'the century of history.'
Not only, therefore, is history unable to discriminate81 between facts that are good and facts that are evil, and between epochs that are progressive and those that are regressive, but it does not begin until the psychological conditions which rendered possible such antitheses have been superseded82 and substituted by an act of the spirit, which seeks to ascertain83 what function the fact or the epoch previously84 condemned85 has fulfilled—that is to say, what it has produced of its own in the course of development, and therefore what it has produced. And since all facts and epochs are productive in their own way, not only is not one of them to be condemned in the light of history, but all are to be praised and venerated86. A condemned fact, a fact that is repugnant, is not yet a historical proposition, it is hardly even the[Pg 91] premiss of a historical problem to be formulated87. A negative history is a non-history so long as its negative process substitutes itself for thought, which is affirmative, and does not maintain itself within its practical and moral bounds and limit itself to poetical expressions and empirical modes of representation, in respect of all of which we can certainly speak (speak and not think), as we do speak at every moment, of bad men and periods of decadence and regression.
If the vice37 of negative history arises from the separation, the solidification88, and the opposition89 of the dialectical antitheses of good and evil and the transformation90 of the ideal moments of development into entities91, that other deviation92 of history which may be known as elegiac history arises from the misunderstanding of another necessity of that conception—that is to say, the perpetual constancy, the perpetual conservation of what has been acquired. But this is also false by definition. What is preserved and enriched in the course of history is history itself, spirituality. The past does not live otherwise than in the present, as the force of the present, resolved and transformed in the present. Every particular form, individual, action, institution, work, thought, is destined93 to perish: even art, which is called eternal (and is so in a certain sense), perishes, for it does not live, save to the extent that it is reproduced, and therefore transfigured and surrounded with new light, in the spirit of posterity94. Finally, truth itself perishes, particular and determined95 truth, because it is not rethinkable, save when included in the system of a vaster truth, and therefore at the same time transformed. But those who do not rise to the conception of pure historical consideration, those who attach themselves with their whole soul to an individual, a work, a belief, an[Pg 92] institution, and attach themselves so strongly that they cannot separate themselves from it in order to objectify it before themselves and think it, are prone96 to attribute the immortality97 which belongs to the spirit in universal to the spirit in one of its particular and determined forms; and since that form, notwithstanding their efforts, dies, and dies in their arms, the universe darkens before their gaze, and the only history that they can relate is the sad one of the agony and death of beautiful things. This too is poetry, and very lofty poetry. Who can do otherwise than weep at the loss of a beloved one, at separation from something dear to him, cannot see the sun extinguished and the earth tremble and the birds cease their flight and fall to earth, like Dante, on the loss of his beloved "who was so beautiful"? But history is never history of death, but history of life, and all know that the proper commemoration of the dead is the knowledge of what they did in life, of what they produced that is working in us, the history of their life and not of their death, which it behoves a gentle soul to veil, a soul barbarous and perverse98 to exhibit in its miserable99 nakedness and to contemplate100 with unhealthy persistence101. For this reason all histories which narrate102 the death and not the life of peoples, of states, of institutions, of customs, of literary and artistic103 ideals, of religious conceptions, are to be considered false, or, we repeat, simply poetry, where they attain5 to the level of poetry. People grow sad and suffer and lament104 because that which was is no longer. This would resolve itself into a mere105 tautology106 (because if it was, it is evident that it is no longer), were it not conjoined to the neglect of recognizing what of that past has not perished—that is to say, that past in so far as it is not past but present, the eternal life of the past. It is in this neglect,[Pg 93] in the incorrect view arising out of it, that the falsity of such histories resides.
It sometimes happens that historians, intent upon narrating107 those scenes of anguish108 in a lugubrious109 manner and upon celebrating the funerals which it pleases them to call histories, remain partly astounded110 and partly scandalized when they hear a peal111 of laughter, a cry of joy, a sigh of satisfaction, or find an enthusiastic impulse springing up from the documents that they are searching. How, they ask, could men live, make love, reproduce their species, sing, paint, discuss, when the trumps112 were sounding east and west to announce the end of the world? But they do not see that such an end of the world exists only in their own imaginations, rich in elegiac motives, but poor in understanding. They do not perceive that such importunate113 trumpet-calls have never in reality existed. These are very useful, on the other hand, for reminding those who may have forgotten it that history always pursues her indefatigable114 work, and that her apparent agonies are the travail115 of a new birth, and that what are believed to be her expiring sighs are moans that announce the birth of a new world. History differs from the individual who dies because, in the words of Alcm?on of Crete, he is not able τ?ν ?ρχ?ν τ? τ?λει προσ?ψαι, to join his beginning to his end: history never dies, because she always joins her beginning to her end.
[1] For the complete development of these conceptions, see my study of The Conception of Becoming, in the Saggio sullo Hegel seguito da altri scritti di storia della filosofia, pp. 149-175 (Bari, 1913). (English translation of the work on Hegel by Douglas Ainslie. Macmillan, London.)
[2] For what relates to this section, see my treatment of Judgments of Value, in the work before cited.
点击收听单词发音
1 controversies | |
争论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 flaunt | |
vt.夸耀,夸饰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 treatises | |
n.专题著作,专题论文,专著( treatise的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 sterile | |
adj.不毛的,不孕的,无菌的,枯燥的,贫瘠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 attainable | |
a.可达到的,可获得的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 decadence | |
n.衰落,颓废 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 terminology | |
n.术语;专有名词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 antithesis | |
n.对立;相对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 Vogue | |
n.时髦,时尚;adj.流行的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 equivocation | |
n.模棱两可的话,含糊话 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 attainment | |
n.达到,到达;[常pl.]成就,造诣 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 positing | |
v.假定,设想,假设( posit的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 extrinsic | |
adj.外部的;不紧要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 infinitely | |
adv.无限地,无穷地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 prospect | |
n.前景,前途;景色,视野 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 variance | |
n.矛盾,不同 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 sentimental | |
adj.多愁善感的,感伤的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 mythological | |
adj.神话的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 mythologies | |
神话学( mythology的名词复数 ); 神话(总称); 虚构的事实; 错误的观点 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 toil | |
vi.辛劳工作,艰难地行动;n.苦工,难事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 ethical | |
adj.伦理的,道德的,合乎道德的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 manifestations | |
n.表示,显示(manifestation的复数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 maxim | |
n.格言,箴言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 pertains | |
关于( pertain的第三人称单数 ); 有关; 存在; 适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 subjective | |
a.主观(上)的,个人的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 judgment | |
n.审判;判断力,识别力,看法,意见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 subjectivity | |
n.主观性(主观主义) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 purge | |
n.整肃,清除,泻药,净化;vt.净化,清除,摆脱;vi.清除,通便,腹泻,变得清洁 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 statistical | |
adj.统计的,统计学的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 contradictory | |
adj.反驳的,反对的,抗辩的;n.正反对,矛盾对立 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 momentary | |
adj.片刻的,瞬息的;短暂的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 frivolous | |
adj.轻薄的;轻率的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 eclecticism | |
n.折衷主义 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 insipid | |
adj.无味的,枯燥乏味的,单调的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 legitimate | |
adj.合法的,合理的,合乎逻辑的;v.使合法 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 condemn | |
vt.谴责,指责;宣判(罪犯),判刑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 condemns | |
v.(通常因道义上的原因而)谴责( condemn的第三人称单数 );宣判;宣布…不能使用;迫使…陷于不幸的境地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 presumptuous | |
adj.胆大妄为的,放肆的,冒昧的,冒失的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 epoch | |
n.(新)时代;历元 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 vestige | |
n.痕迹,遗迹,残余 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 judgments | |
判断( judgment的名词复数 ); 鉴定; 评价; 审判 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 penetrated | |
adj. 击穿的,鞭辟入里的 动词penetrate的过去式和过去分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 prey | |
n.被掠食者,牺牲者,掠食;v.捕食,掠夺,折磨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 repentance | |
n.懊悔 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 adversary | |
adj.敌手,对手 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 symbolized | |
v.象征,作为…的象征( symbolize的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 Christians | |
n.基督教徒( Christian的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 Christian | |
adj.基督教徒的;n.基督教徒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 sages | |
n.圣人( sage的名词复数 );智者;哲人;鼠尾草(可用作调料) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 luminous | |
adj.发光的,发亮的;光明的;明白易懂的;有启发的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 dense | |
a.密集的,稠密的,浓密的;密度大的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 glorification | |
n.赞颂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 depreciation | |
n.价值低落,贬值,蔑视,贬低 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 longing | |
n.(for)渴望 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 metaphors | |
隐喻( metaphor的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 repercussion | |
n.[常pl.](不良的)影响,反响,后果 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 antitheses | |
n.对照,对立的,对比法;对立( antithesis的名词复数 );对立面;对照;对偶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 formerly | |
adv.从前,以前 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 adversaries | |
n.对手,敌手( adversary的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 feudal | |
adj.封建的,封地的,领地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 barons | |
男爵( baron的名词复数 ); 巨头; 大王; 大亨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 metes | |
v.(对某人)施以,给予(处罚等)( mete的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 justifies | |
证明…有理( justify的第三人称单数 ); 为…辩护; 对…作出解释; 为…辩解(或辩护) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 worthy | |
adj.(of)值得的,配得上的;有价值的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 poetical | |
adj.似诗人的;诗一般的;韵文的;富有诗意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 conspicuous | |
adj.明眼的,惹人注目的;炫耀的,摆阔气的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 unity | |
n.团结,联合,统一;和睦,协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 philological | |
adj.语言学的,文献学的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 relatively | |
adv.比较...地,相对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 discriminate | |
v.区别,辨别,区分;有区别地对待 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 superseded | |
[医]被代替的,废弃的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 ascertain | |
vt.发现,确定,查明,弄清 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 previously | |
adv.以前,先前(地) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 condemned | |
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 venerated | |
敬重(某人或某事物),崇敬( venerate的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 formulated | |
v.构想出( formulate的过去式和过去分词 );规划;确切地阐述;用公式表示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 solidification | |
凝固 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 transformation | |
n.变化;改造;转变 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 entities | |
实体对像; 实体,独立存在体,实际存在物( entity的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 deviation | |
n.背离,偏离;偏差,偏向;离题 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 posterity | |
n.后裔,子孙,后代 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 prone | |
adj.(to)易于…的,很可能…的;俯卧的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 immortality | |
n.不死,不朽 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 perverse | |
adj.刚愎的;坚持错误的,行为反常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 miserable | |
adj.悲惨的,痛苦的;可怜的,糟糕的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 contemplate | |
vt.盘算,计议;周密考虑;注视,凝视 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 persistence | |
n.坚持,持续,存留 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 narrate | |
v.讲,叙述 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 artistic | |
adj.艺术(家)的,美术(家)的;善于艺术创作的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 lament | |
n.悲叹,悔恨,恸哭;v.哀悼,悔恨,悲叹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 tautology | |
n.无谓的重复;恒真命题 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 narrating | |
v.故事( narrate的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 anguish | |
n.(尤指心灵上的)极度痛苦,烦恼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 lugubrious | |
adj.悲哀的,忧郁的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 astounded | |
v.使震惊(astound的过去式和过去分词);愕然;愕;惊讶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 peal | |
n.钟声;v.鸣响 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 trumps | |
abbr.trumpets 喇叭;小号;喇叭形状的东西;喇叭筒v.(牌戏)出王牌赢(一牌或一墩)( trump的过去式 );吹号公告,吹号庆祝;吹喇叭;捏造 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 importunate | |
adj.强求的;纠缠不休的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 indefatigable | |
adj.不知疲倦的,不屈不挠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 travail | |
n.阵痛;努力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |