This rule of historical method, which Comte likes to recall, applies very well to his own system. In order to reach as complete an understanding as possible of his doctrine1, to appreciate exactly its general orientation6, to understand the importance which the author attaches in it to this or that part, the study of the text will not suffice. We must2 further take into account the historical circumstances in which the doctrine found its birth, the general movement of contemporary ideas, and the manifold influences which have reacted upon the mind of the philosopher.
Now one great fact, above all others, dominates the period in which the positive philosophy appeared. It is the French Revolution, as Comte expressly states: without it, neither the theory of progress, nor consequently social science, nor consequently again positive philosophy would have been possible. Was it not, moreover, inevitable7 that this extraordinary social upheaval8 should by reflex action have determined9 a vast and prolonged movement in philosophical10 and political speculation11? The effects of this reflex action varied12 according to the value and the originality13 of the minds which experienced them. But in the greatest as in the most mediocre14 we recognise infallibly certain common features. For instance, men and women, in the rising generation at the beginning of the XIX. century, never fail to put the same question to themselves: “What social institutions should be established after the Revolution?” and by this all understand not only the political form of government, but the very principles of social order: a problem which appeared as urgent from the practical point of view, as it was supreme15 from the theoretical point of view. It is this problem in various forms which preoccupies16 Chateaubriand as well as Fourier and Saint-Simon, and Joseph de Maistre as well as Cousin and Comte.
All agree upon the first point. We must “reconstruct.” An “organic” period must succeed the “critical” period which has just come to an end. According to Saint Simon’s striking expression, humanity is not made to inhabit ruins. The revolutionary storm had been so formidable, the din5 so deafening17, the social back-wash so violent, that no one exactly measured the effect which had been produced. Many institu3tions which had only been shaken seemed to be overthrown18. A good part of the old régime had even gone through the crisis without being too greatly damaged, and had survived. But this fact, which was very well appreciated by the men of 1850, could not yet be discovered by the first generation of the century. It conscientiously19 believed that the old régime had crumbled20 altogether, and that the task either of restoring it, or of again laying down the very bases of society belonged to it. In this the first generation remained faithful to the spirit of the Revolution, which had considered itself as an effort to institute an entirely21 new social and political system, a thought in which the civilised world had shared. Now, in spite of the labours of the revolutionary assemblies, in spite of the power and of the great talent which the Convention had at its command, this ambitious hope had not been realised. The question remained open after the Directoire and after the Empire. When the old régime was supposed to have been destroyed, how was society to be “reorganised”?
Thus, at the opening of the XIX. century, philosophical speculation was at first to be directed towards the religious and social problems. Undoubtedly22 the influence of the uninterrupted advance of the positive sciences was also felt at the same time. A study of Auguste Comte’s system could hardly fail to recognise the fact. But, even with Comte, scientific interest, however active it may be, is subordinated to the social interest. What he asks of philosophy is the rational settlement of the bases of modern society. Thus, he means to discover the elements of a religion which can be substituted to Catholicism, whose mission he considers as at an end.
“The XIX. century,” Ranke has said, “is especially a century of restoration.” A deep saying, which exactly expresses one of the leading features in the historical physiognomy of this century. It is precisely23 thus that it was4 conceived by those who inaugurated it. Such indeed is the main tendency of the greater number of philosophical doctrines which have expressed its most intimate characteristics. Only, as is generally the case, this restoration absorbs and consolidates24 a large part of the results acquired during the crisis. At the same time new problems, raised especially by the development of industry in its larger aspects, made clear-sighted men feel that the revolutionary period, however desirable it might be to bring it to a close, was really only beginning.
点击收听单词发音
1 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 doctrines | |
n.教条( doctrine的名词复数 );教义;学说;(政府政策的)正式声明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 milieu | |
n.环境;出身背景;(个人所处的)社会环境 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 din | |
n.喧闹声,嘈杂声 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 orientation | |
n.方向,目标;熟悉,适应,情况介绍 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 inevitable | |
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 upheaval | |
n.胀起,(地壳)的隆起;剧变,动乱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 speculation | |
n.思索,沉思;猜测;投机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 varied | |
adj.多样的,多变化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 originality | |
n.创造力,独创性;新颖 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 mediocre | |
adj.平常的,普通的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 preoccupies | |
v.占据(某人)思想,使对…全神贯注,使专心于( preoccupy的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 deafening | |
adj. 振耳欲聋的, 极喧闹的 动词deafen的现在分词形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 overthrown | |
adj. 打翻的,推倒的,倾覆的 动词overthrow的过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 conscientiously | |
adv.凭良心地;认真地,负责尽职地;老老实实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 crumbled | |
(把…)弄碎, (使)碎成细屑( crumble的过去式和过去分词 ); 衰落; 坍塌; 损坏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 undoubtedly | |
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 consolidates | |
巩固 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |