Moreover, the knowledge which the human mind acquires at first is only very imperfectly real; for theological philosophy furnishes the mind with its first conceptions. Man begins by supposing everywhere wills like his own, and the world which surrounds him is peopled with gods or fetishes. Nevertheless, from this first period, the rudiments8 of a more positive knowledge already appear. In every order of phenomena9 some are very simple and of such striking regularity10, that evidently no arbitrary will intervenes in their working. Man must very quickly have had a “real” idea of these phenomena. In all the other cases instead of observing the phenomena he61 imagined the mode of their production; but here he observed the sequences and concomitances which he could not resist; and he regulated his conduct upon this observation. From this humble11 beginning science came into being.
In this way, far from opposing scientific thought to common thought, as most of the philosophers do, Comte, without disregarding the special character of one and of the other shows that both spring from the same source, and that they do not present any essential point of difference. However abstract and however elevated science may become, it always remains12, according to him, a “simple special prolongation” of good sense, of common sense and of “universal wisdom.” The character of “positivity,” by which scientific knowledge is distinguished13 from theological and metaphysical conceptions, belongs also to popular wisdom. Like this wisdom, which the practical necessities of life have formed, science abstains14 from searching after the causes, the ends, the substances, and whatever is beyond the reach of verification by experience. Its efforts bear exclusively upon the laws of coexistence and of succession which govern the phenomena. And again it is from this wisdom that it has borrowed the spirit of its positive method, which consists in observing facts and in systematising observations to rise to the concept of laws.
It follows from this that science contains within itself neither its starting-point nor its terminus. Both are given it by “common sense” whence it springs. The starting-point is the spontaneous observation of constant relations between the most simple phenomena. The terminus is the knowledge of these same relations among all given phenomena, as complete and as precise as our requirements demand. Indeed the common sense, or the popular wisdom, is soon baffled by the complexity15 of phenomena. If we had no other guide we should know very little, and in nearly all cases we should62 be reduced to a kind of empirical divination16. The function of science is to substitute a real knowledge of laws to this divination.
This function would never have been fulfilled if the human mind had not possessed17 the property of being able to separate theory from practice. Undoubtedly the former proceeds from the latter. As has been said, every science is born from a corresponding art, and from the desire to perfect it. But this perfecting would not have gone very far, if the human mind had never lost sight of it. Happily, man is capable of temporarily forgetting his immediate18 interests in the pursuit of knowledge. By degrees, from the complexity of concrete cases, he has learnt to disengage the elements common to a whole class of phenomena. He has thus formed the idea of law, or the invariable relation between given phenomena. Beyond the intellectual satisfaction which this knowledge gave him, he found in time applications of it which he would never have imagined beforehand. To quote an example from a civilisation19 already very advanced, when the Greek geometers patiently applied20 themselves to the study of conic sections, did they suspect that their labours would one day serve in calculating certain astronomical21 determinations upon which the safety of mariners22 would depend?
In this way, science, utilitarian23 in its origin, since it sprang from the practical needs of man, utilitarian in its end, since it aims at providing for those needs, has nevertheless been unable to develop itself and will be unable still to do so in the future, except by neglecting this very utility. Better to fulfil its destiny, it must provisionally forget it; and it will be the more useful, in the long run, in proportion as it will have been the more disinterested24. We never know, a priori, if a discovery which finds no application to-day, combined later with another one, will not be of capital interest for63 mankind. Therefore it is of the highest importance that theoretical order should remain clearly distinct from the practical order.
That is why Comte regarded the appearance of a sacerdotal class, specially25 occupied with speculative26 research, as a decisive moment in history of humanity. It matters little that these researches should have remained chimerical27 and absurd during long centuries. The essential point was that the human mind should form and keep the habit of disinterested speculation28, that it should not rest content with immediately applicable knowledge, and that it should exert itself towards a theoretical conception of nature, however simple at first that conception was bound to be.
Thus, science has, properly speaking, two roots, the one practical, the other theoretical. If it originated in the primitive arts, it is no less closely allied29 with primitive philosophy. It still bears features which enable us to discern this twofold filiation. On the one hand, it has remained speculative as was the theological philosophy which first dominated over the human mind. Only this speculation has gradually abandoned everything except the laws of phenomena, and it has ended by undermining the theological conceptions from which it came. On the other hand, science has remained real, like the popular wisdom which gave it birth. But, while dealing30 with given phenomena in experience, it has developed in the direction of theory. Instead of only considering scenes of concrete objects, it has resolved them into their elements. A more and more powerful analysis has raised it to the consideration of laws more and more general and abstract. Thus, while the popular wisdom is limited to empirical generalisations, a science such as, for instance, astronomy discovers the law which governs the whole of an immense order of phenomena.
From this general idea of science the following consequences at once follow:
64
1. Science is the collective work of humanity. It bears upon an object common to all: Reality. It employs the method common to all: the positive method. All intellects work in the same manner on a common ground. It is what Comte calls “the profound mental identity of learned men with the crowd whose destiny fulfils itself in active work.31” The progress of the scientific mind is a methodical extension of popular common sense to all subjects accessible to human reason. But here method does almost everything. “The whole superiority of the philosophical31 mind over the popular common sense results from a special and continuous application to common speculations32, in starting prudently33 from the initial step, after having brought them back to a normal state of judicious34 abstraction, for the purpose of generalising and coordinating35. For, what ordinary intellects chiefly lack, is less the precision and penetration36 appropriate for discerning partial approximations, than the aptitude37 for generalising abstract relations, and for establishing a perfect logical coherence38 among our various notions.”32
The germ of the highest scientific conceptions is often to be found in common reason. Comte delights in giving as an example one of the discoveries which he most admires, Descartes’ invention of analytical39 Geometry. To determine at every moment the position of a point in space by its distance from fixed40 axes: is not that what geographers42 have been doing for so long in order to determine the longitude43 and latitude44 of a place upon the terrestrial sphere? And has not this proceeding45 itself been suggested to the geographer41 by simple common sense? For he instinctively46 seeks to mark the inaccessible47 points which interest him, by means of their distance from given points or lines. From this the idea of the Cartesian co-ordinates only differs by a superior degree of abstraction and of generality.
65
Thus all men must be regarded as collaborating48 in the discovery of truth as much as in making use of it. Speaking generally, if the great philosophers and scientific men of genius seem to be the intellectual guides of humanity, it is because they are the first to be affected49 by each mental revolution. They are the first to pass from a traditional to a new attitude and their example is decisive. But, says Comte, “the changes relating to the method of thinking with originality50 only become manifest when they are almost accomplished51.” The great men whose names are justly authors attached to are, however, more the heralds52 than the of these changes.
2. Science is the work of all: it must therefore be accessible to all. It is a patrimony53 common to the whole of mankind; and the inheritance must be taken from no one. As a consequence, the State owes scientific instruction to those who are not in a position to procure54 it for themselves. Not that all men, all the people ought to acquire a deep knowledge of the several fundamental sciences, like those who make it the particular occupation of their lives. The impossibility of such a thing is too evident for several reasons. Neither is it a question of popularising the great scientific theories, for the use of badly prepared minds. Comte condemns55 severely56 this way of “simplifying” science. For instance, he will not allow Newton’s laws to be separated from their demonstrations57. It will always be the duty of the greater number of men to adopt the majority of scientific truths on the testimony58 of those who will have discovered, criticised and verified them. But, what it will be the duty of common education to give to every mind, is the habit of conceiving all phenomena, from the most simple to the most complex, as equally governed by invariable laws, and, consequently, of understanding the whole of nature as an order which the positive method alone allows us to discover and to66 modify. And as this method cannot be studied apart from the sciences in which it is used, it will be necessary for every man to be made acquainted with a summary of each fundamental science, from mathematics to sociology. There is nothing impracticable in this scheme. Comte has drawn59 out, in the positive Polity, a plan of education conceived on this principle. On this condition alone will philosophy, founded upon positive science, succeed in realising the harmony of minds, and in “reorganising the beliefs.”
II.
Auguste Comte often says that the positive spirit consists in keeping oneself equally distant from two dangers, mysticism and empiricism.33 By mysticism he understands the recourse to non-verifiable explanations and to transcendent, hypotheses. Men’s imagination finds pleasure in these things, but we must be able to bring all “real” knowledge back to a general or particular fact. Positive science therefore abstains from searching after substances, ends, and even causes. It only bears upon phenomena and their relations.
Empiricism, in its turn, is no less than mysticism contrary to the spirit of science, Empiricism signifies for Comte the knowledge which does not go beyond the pure and simple ascertainment60 of a fact. Now, an accumulation of even precisely61 noted62 facts has no theoretical interest. It may, at most, be erudition, but it is not science. To think that by thus gathering63 facts together one is labouring at the work of science, is “to take a quarry64 for an edifice65.”34 In a word, “science is made up of laws, and not of facts.”35
Strictly66 speaking, no scientific observation is even possible without a previous theory, that is to say, without a presupposed67 law, whose verification is in question. Undoubtedly in science when it has become positive, the imagination no longer constructs “causes” or “essences.” It must submit to reason, that is to say, to the methodical investigation67 of phenomena. Nevertheless, this investigation cannot take place without guiding hypotheses, and thus the imagination plays a part in science, subordinate it is true, but indispensable. Comte here separates himself from Bacon. According to the English philosopher, in the knowledge of nature, the mind must make itself as receptive as possible. In introducing anything of itself it would falsify science, and its whole effort must be to hold itself up to phenomena as a perfectly7 plain and unspotted mirror, so as to reflect them as they are. Now this is precisely the idea of science which Comte rejects under the name of empiricism. Without the hypotheses or the theories suggested by the very activity of the mind science would never be constituted, according to him. There would never even be an apprehension68 of fact, at least an apprehension such that it could be of service to science. In a word “absolute empiricism is impossible.” In the simple observation of a phenomenon by the human mind, the entire mind is interested, and in it the subjective69 conditions of science are already virtually given.
This being granted, science may be defined as a methodical processus of the connection and extension of our knowledge. It consists, in every department “in the exact relations established between observed facts, so as to deduce from the least possible number of fundamental data, the most extensive series of secondary phenomena, in renouncing70 absolutely the vain search after causes and essences.” So long as men seek to “explain” phenomena the theological and metaphysical spirit has not yet disappeared. Positive science abstains from all explanations of this kind. Thus, Newton has placed in the same category universal gravitation and the attraction of68 bodies. We cannot know what this mutual71 action of the stars and the attraction of terrestrial bodies are in themselves. But we know with full certainty, the existence and the law of these two orders of phenomena and moreover we know that they are identical. For the geometer weight is explained when he conceives it as a particular case of general gravitation. On the contrary it is weight which makes the physicist72 proper understand celestial73 gravitation. We can never go beyond such juxtapositions74 “of ideas.”36
But while science brings together similar phenomena, its chief function is to connect them, that is to say to determine them one by another according to the relations which exist between them. All science, says Comte, consists in the co-ordination of facts; and if the several observations remained isolated75 there would be no science. We may even say generally that science is destined76, as far as the various phenomena permit, to dispense77 with direct observation, in allowing us to deduce the greatest possible number of results from the smallest number of acquired data. If a constant relation is found to subsist78 between two phenomena, it becomes useless to observe them both; for from the observation of one the variations of the other will be deduced. But the first may in its turn be the function of a third, and so on; until at last we conceive a constant connection between all the phenomena of a given order, which may allow us to deduce them all from a single law. Such for Comte would be the perfect form of science: how near it is to the Cartesian ideal! “The positive spirit,” he says, “without failing to recognize the preponderance of reality directly ascertained79, tends to enlarge the rational at the expense of the experimental domain80, by substituting the prevision of phenomena to their immediate observation.” Scientific progress consists in diminishing the number of69 distinct and independent laws, by continually multiplying their respective connections.37
“Prevision” thus becomes the essential characteristic of scientific knowledge, and that independently of any utilitarian mental reservation. For the eventual81 applications of science do not determine its theoretical advance. The prevision with which we are here concerned consists solely82 in the possibility of knowing with certainty without observing. It is knowledge a priori in the Aristotelian sense of the word, of which mathematics present the most perfect model. A rectilinear triangle being given, I do not need experience to know with certainty that the sum of the angles in it is equal to two right angles. Thus understood prevision applies to the present, and even to the past, as well as to the future. When Comte writes “All science has prevision for its aim,”38 we must understand: “All science tends to substitute deduction83 to experience, rational to empirical knowledge.” This prevision, a necessary consequence of the constant relations discovered between phenomena, will allow men never to mistake real science for fruitless erudition, which accumulates facts without deducing them one from another.
Thus the formula cited above enlarges itself: “Science is composed of laws and not of facts.” The more deduction is substituted to experience, the better is the extension and connection of our knowledge realised. Consequently, the more also does science draw near to that unity84 which is imperatively85 claimed by our understanding, and which is for it the criterion of truth. “Real science,” says Comte, “regarded from the highest point of view, has no other general object but to establish or to fortify86 unceasingly the intellectual order, which is the basis of all other order.”39 The mind70 which applies itself to the contemplation of the world requires, before everything, to find it intelligible87. “Real” science satisfies it, not in imagining wills and causes, as did theology and metaphysics, but in discovering order in the constant relations between phenomena. When this order is harmonious88, that is to say, when the several classes of phenomena are conceived as homogenous89, and as similarly governed by laws, “the spontaneous unity of our understanding is consolidated90.” It matters little that the various orders of phenomena are given to us as irreducible to one another. The highest object of science is to determine the point of view from which all phenomena appear intelligible, and this point of view is one as the understanding itself is one.
III.
Perhaps it would have been easy to pass from this conception of positive science to a theory of knowledge, and to a metaphysical view of nature, both idealistic. But Comte neither could nor would push his theory in this direction. In this respect nothing is more significant than his way of understanding the relativity of science.
This relativity is usually presented as the conclusion of a criticism of our understanding, of its nature, of its bearings, and of its relations to its objects. But, according to Comte, an inquiry91 pursued on these lines, has no chance of reaching a conclusion. The only theory of knowledge which is positive and “real,” is drawn from the history of the human mind. The laws of the mind are only revealed in the examination of the successive products of its activity, that is to say in its beliefs and in its science. The relativity of science can therefore only be stated at first, as a fact, leaving it for subsequent inquiry to determine the reason of that fact. The law of the three States suffices for this, for it shows that man began by71 seeking for absolute knowledge. The philosophy to which he first turns is, at the same time, the most na?ve and the most ambitious. But a necessary evolution causes him to abandon the pursuit of the absolute, first in its theological form and then in the metaphysical form. Having reached the positive state, man knows that his science, necessarily relative, is limited to “the systematic92 co-ordination of phenomena,” and the knowledge of their laws.
The condemnation93 which thus strikes researches bearing on the absolute is itself, moreover, only relative in character. It prejudges nothing respecting the ultimate solution of questions. Positive philosophy in no way takes sides in respect to these problems. It simply states that science has more and more cut them off from the number of those which it studies. Indeed it is impossible to apply the positive method to questions which concern the absolute. Now, this method being the only one which our mind can henceforth follow, at least if it wishes to maintain the logical unity which is its supreme95 requirement, it follows that these problems are in fact abandoned. Nothing more and nothing less. “Sound philosophy,” says Comte, “sets aside, it is true, insoluble questions”; but “in stating the motive96 of their rejection97, it avoids denying anything respecting them, which would be contradictory98 to that systematic disuse by which alone uncontrovertible opinions must die out.” (Comte means: opinions which do not come within the range of positive discussion.) The problems relating to the essence of the soul or to the “substantia prima” will melt away, as the majority of the metaphysical problems which the scholastics put to themselves have already disappeared.
Even to positive science, we must be careful not to attribute an absolute character—that is to say, in a sense slightly different from the preceding one, but very frequently with Comte—a definite and immutable99 character. The laws which we can72 determine are never true except under certain conditions. We have no right to consider them as true absolutely. Newton’s law is demonstrated for our solar system: but do we know that it is verified in all the systems throughout space? Do not let us confound the world, which we can study with the united resources of observation and calculation with the universe, of which we know scarcely anything, and which outranges all our powers. In spite of the famous principle of the sufficient reason the absence of motives100 for negation101 does not constitute the right of affirmation, without any direct proof. Absolute notions, says Comte, seem to me so impossible that I would not even dare, whatever probability I may see in it, to warrant the necessary and unalterable perpetuity of the theory of gravitation restricted to the interior of our world, if one day, (which is moreover very difficult to admit) the precision of our present observations came to be perfected as much as we have done in comparison to Hipparchus.40
In the same way, must not attraction have seemed to be an absolute quality (that is to say an immutable one) of bodies, since neither change of shape, nor the passage from one physical constitution to another, nor any chemical metamorphosis, nor even the difference between the state of life and death could modify this quality, so long as the integrity of the substance was maintained? The Newtonian conception came and destroyed entirely102 at a signal stroke this character which must have appeared so indestructible, by showing that the weight of a body is a phenomenon purely103 relative to the position of this body in the world, or, more precisely, to its distance from the centre of the earth.41
In order that our positive science of any part of nature should be absolute, that is to say, final, it would have to be complete. But, as all things are caused or causing, helped or73 helping104, according to Pascal’s expression, all the phenomena in a reciprocal universal action, all the laws relative one to another, our science will never be complete on any point. It only furnishes more or less imperfect approximations.42 The discovery of new facts and new laws is always possible.
How many times does not positive science find itself obliged to modify and to readjust a system of long acquired notions, in order to make a place for new elements? This is a work often very laborious105, but from which science never dreams of shrinking, knowing that it is made liable to it, so to speak, by definition, that is to say, that it is relative. Examples of this abound106, not only in the history of physical and natural science, but even in that of so-called exact sciences. Do we not hear M. Poincaré declaring in accordance with Hertz, that given the system of Galileo and of Newton in mechanics it is impossible to give a satisfactory idea of mass and of force?43
Thus the definitions, and even the laws, established by the positive sciences, are at every period approximations corresponding to the knowledge we have of facts. And as this knowledge can always be enriched the approximation may also become stricter, without ever reaching its confines. Leibnitz already said that the analysis of anything real reaches to infinity107. This thought is with him, closely allied to the whole of his metaphysics. We find in Comte an expression in some way equivalent, although positive. He says, although the progress of the science of nature consists in substituting as much as possible the rational method to the experimental method, the limit can never be attained108, we can never affirm that experience will not bring new elements which will oblige us to modify the edifice of science. The relativity of science thus serves to maintain an equal balance between the need of unity which comes from74 the understanding, and the inexhaustible diversity of the world of reality which this understanding studies.
As a fact, then, positive science is always relative. Rightly, it cannot be otherwise, and this for two essential reasons. It depends necessarily upon “our organisation109” and “our situation”44 or, in other words, it is relative “both to the individual and to the species in its advance.”
It is relative in the first place to our organisation. Here Comte takes up again an idea which was dear to the philosophers of the XVIII. century and in particular to Diderot. If our organisation were different, the data which our science elaborates would be other that they are. With more organs we might perhaps grasp kinds of problems of which we have no idea. If we suppose our species to be blind, astronomy would not exist for it. And further, a natural law requires that the more complex and the higher phenomena in regard to their conditions of existence, should be subordinated to the more general and the more common phenomena. The intellectual phenomena thus depend, first, upon the biological phenomena, and then upon all those to which the biological phenomena are subordinated. In this sense, therefore, science is relative to our organisation, which is itself relative in respect to the milieu110 in which we live. But, reciprocally, the representation of this milieu and of this organisation rests upon intellectual laws which impart to science a need of unity and harmony special to the mind.
Comte concludes, therefore, that to endeavour to apportion111 what belongs to the object and what to the subject in scientific knowledge is a hopeless attempt. We simply know that science is not the exclusive product either of the subject or the object. Giving too much to the object leads us to “empiricism.” Falling to the opposite extreme leads to75 “mysticism.” The efforts of philosophers to construct an abstract theory of knowledge have only ended in miserable112 results. We have not gone beyond Aristotle’s “axiom as corrected by Leibnitz.” Nihil est in intellectu quod non prius fuerit in sensu, nisi ipse intellectus. We are only certain of one thing: our science, necessarily conditioned by our organisation, is also necessarily relative.
But this is not the most decisive consideration for it only makes us see that our science would be different, if our organisation were to change. Now, as a matter of fact, our organisation does not change. Human nature, according to Comte, remains similar to itself in the whole course of its evolution. It is this evolution which itself becomes a cause, and a decisive one, of relativity for science. For, if our organisation does not vary, the system of our conceptions and of our science necessarily varies, according to our “situation,” that is to say, according to the position which we occupy in this evolution, which accomplishes itself according to laws.
Our conceptions, our religions, our philosophies, are not only individual phenomena; they are also and chiefly social phenomena, moments in a collective and continuous life, of which all the phases are interdependent. We only know in a given order of knowledge, what is compatible at that moment with the generally admitted philosophy, with the knowledge already acquired in this and in the other orders of phenomena, with the great hypotheses considered as true, with the methods in force, etc. As soon as the human mind has become conscious of the evolution to which it is subject, as soon as it has grasped its most general law (the law of the three states), in a word, as soon as sociology is founded, science can no longer be conceived as other than relative. For from that moment the various sciences appear as so many great social facts, which vary as so many functions of the rest of civilisation.
76
Our speculations, “depending on the totality of social progression,” can therefore never admit of that absolute fixity which metaphysicians have supposed. The continuous movement of history modifies, in the long run, the beliefs which appear to be the most immutable. Our theories tend to represent more and more faithfully the objects of our investigations113, that is to say the laws of phenomena. We are thus brought back to the idea of limit, which is never attained, towards which we are advancing by means of approximations ever more exact.
The time is not yet far distant, when a doctrine114 of this kind could not have been advanced without at once being rejected as sceptical. The human mind is scarcely beginning to understand that truth cannot be immutable.45 Men believed that truth must always be identical with itself, always identical for all minds at all times and at all places. It seems that in losing this character, it must cease to be truth. That is why philosophy has been so persistent115 in the pursuit of the absolute. It was believed that no truth could be certain, unless it rested, ultimately, upon an immutable foundation.
Science was therefore made to hang on metaphysics. And the defeats, a thousand times repeated, of metaphysics would not have discouraged the human mind had not positive philosophy at last shown that the truth of which we are capable, because it is relative does not cease to be truth. We are not condemned116 to choose between the pursuit of an inaccessible absolute and the crumbling117 down of all science. It suffices to understand that human science evolves and that this evolution is subject to laws. It is never ended: it always “becomes.” It is not a “state:” it is a “progress.”
There are therefore provisional, and, if one may so speak, temporary truths. Does science ever establish any others?77 The ideas which Hipparchus and the Greek astronomers118 had of the heavens was not false in all respects. It was the astronomical truth compatible with the conditions of the society in which they lived. After the labours of the observers of the Middle Ages, utilised by Copernicus, this idea faded before another one which became more perfect with Newton and Laplace. Perhaps this one will be modified in its turn, in consequence of new discoveries! Similarly it was thought that the earth was a flat surface, then a round disc. Then it was represented as a sphere and finally as an ellipsoid. To-day we know that this ellipsoid is irregular.
Truth is then at each period “the perfect logical coherence,” or the correspondence between our conceptions and our observations. The history of human thought is composed of a progressive series of alternating periods. At a certain moment the mind has placed what it conceives in accordance with what it knows. But, by degrees, new facts are observed, known facts are better interpreted, discoveries burst forth94. The harmony between the conceptions and the observations then becomes precarious119. Minds find a greater and greater difficulty in fitting all the acquired knowledge into the traditional frame. At last the frame gives way. Then the harmony is re-established in a more comprehensive form, which in its turn is destined to become insufficient120. Here positive philosophy recognises a sociological law. It gives up the vain dream of immutable truth. It no longer regards the truth of to-day as absolutely true, nor the truth of yesterday as absolutely false. It ceases to be critical in regard to the past.”
To conclude, the theory of science can therefore only be accomplished from the sociological point of view. It remains imperfect so long as “we” has not been substituted to “I,” the universal subject which is humanity to the individual subject, and a philosophical history of the sciences to mere121 reflective analysis.78 To the logical conditions of science, to define it completely, its biological and social conditions must be joined. Then, but then only, it will be understood, that, at each period, science is at the same time true and relative, without its relativity placing its truth in danger.
点击收听单词发音
1 inclination | |
n.倾斜;点头;弯腰;斜坡;倾度;倾向;爱好 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 imperative | |
n.命令,需要;规则;祈使语气;adj.强制的;紧急的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 repugnance | |
n.嫌恶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 torpor | |
n.迟钝;麻木;(动物的)冬眠 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 undoubtedly | |
adv.确实地,无疑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 rudiments | |
n.基础知识,入门 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 regularity | |
n.规律性,规则性;匀称,整齐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 humble | |
adj.谦卑的,恭顺的;地位低下的;v.降低,贬低 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 abstains | |
戒(尤指酒),戒除( abstain的第三人称单数 ); 弃权(不投票) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 complexity | |
n.复杂(性),复杂的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 divination | |
n.占卜,预测 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 civilisation | |
n.文明,文化,开化,教化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 astronomical | |
adj.天文学的,(数字)极大的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 mariners | |
海员,水手(mariner的复数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 utilitarian | |
adj.实用的,功利的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 disinterested | |
adj.不关心的,不感兴趣的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 specially | |
adv.特定地;特殊地;明确地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 speculative | |
adj.思索性的,暝想性的,推理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 chimerical | |
adj.荒诞不经的,梦幻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 speculation | |
n.思索,沉思;猜测;投机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 allied | |
adj.协约国的;同盟国的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 dealing | |
n.经商方法,待人态度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 philosophical | |
adj.哲学家的,哲学上的,达观的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 speculations | |
n.投机买卖( speculation的名词复数 );思考;投机活动;推断 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 prudently | |
adv. 谨慎地,慎重地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 judicious | |
adj.明智的,明断的,能作出明智决定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 coordinating | |
v.使协调,使调和( coordinate的现在分词 );协调;协同;成为同等 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 penetration | |
n.穿透,穿人,渗透 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 aptitude | |
n.(学习方面的)才能,资质,天资 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 coherence | |
n.紧凑;连贯;一致性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 analytical | |
adj.分析的;用分析法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 geographer | |
n.地理学者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 geographers | |
地理学家( geographer的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 longitude | |
n.经线,经度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 latitude | |
n.纬度,行动或言论的自由(范围),(pl.)地区 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 proceeding | |
n.行动,进行,(pl.)会议录,学报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 instinctively | |
adv.本能地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 inaccessible | |
adj.达不到的,难接近的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 collaborating | |
合作( collaborate的现在分词 ); 勾结叛国 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 affected | |
adj.不自然的,假装的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 originality | |
n.创造力,独创性;新颖 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 accomplished | |
adj.有才艺的;有造诣的;达到了的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 heralds | |
n.使者( herald的名词复数 );预报者;预兆;传令官v.预示( herald的第三人称单数 );宣布(好或重要) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 patrimony | |
n.世袭财产,继承物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 procure | |
vt.获得,取得,促成;vi.拉皮条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 condemns | |
v.(通常因道义上的原因而)谴责( condemn的第三人称单数 );宣判;宣布…不能使用;迫使…陷于不幸的境地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 severely | |
adv.严格地;严厉地;非常恶劣地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 demonstrations | |
证明( demonstration的名词复数 ); 表明; 表达; 游行示威 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 testimony | |
n.证词;见证,证明 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 ascertainment | |
n.探查,发现,确认 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 noted | |
adj.著名的,知名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 gathering | |
n.集会,聚会,聚集 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 quarry | |
n.采石场;v.采石;费力地找 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 edifice | |
n.宏伟的建筑物(如宫殿,教室) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 investigation | |
n.调查,调查研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 apprehension | |
n.理解,领悟;逮捕,拘捕;忧虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 subjective | |
a.主观(上)的,个人的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 renouncing | |
v.声明放弃( renounce的现在分词 );宣布放弃;宣布与…决裂;宣布摒弃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 mutual | |
adj.相互的,彼此的;共同的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 physicist | |
n.物理学家,研究物理学的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 celestial | |
adj.天体的;天上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 juxtapositions | |
n.并置,并列( juxtaposition的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 isolated | |
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 dispense | |
vt.分配,分发;配(药),发(药);实施 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 subsist | |
vi.生存,存在,供养 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 ascertained | |
v.弄清,确定,查明( ascertain的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 domain | |
n.(活动等)领域,范围;领地,势力范围 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 eventual | |
adj.最后的,结局的,最终的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 solely | |
adv.仅仅,唯一地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 deduction | |
n.减除,扣除,减除额;推论,推理,演绎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 unity | |
n.团结,联合,统一;和睦,协调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 imperatively | |
adv.命令式地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 fortify | |
v.强化防御,为…设防;加强,强化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 intelligible | |
adj.可理解的,明白易懂的,清楚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 harmonious | |
adj.和睦的,调和的,和谐的,协调的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 homogenous | |
adj.同类的,同质的,纯系的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 consolidated | |
a.联合的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 inquiry | |
n.打听,询问,调查,查问 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 systematic | |
adj.有系统的,有计划的,有方法的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 condemnation | |
n.谴责; 定罪 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 rejection | |
n.拒绝,被拒,抛弃,被弃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 contradictory | |
adj.反驳的,反对的,抗辩的;n.正反对,矛盾对立 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 immutable | |
adj.不可改变的,永恒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 negation | |
n.否定;否认 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 purely | |
adv.纯粹地,完全地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 helping | |
n.食物的一份&adj.帮助人的,辅助的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 laborious | |
adj.吃力的,努力的,不流畅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 abound | |
vi.大量存在;(in,with)充满,富于 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 infinity | |
n.无限,无穷,大量 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 organisation | |
n.组织,安排,团体,有机休 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 milieu | |
n.环境;出身背景;(个人所处的)社会环境 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 apportion | |
vt.(按比例或计划)分配 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 miserable | |
adj.悲惨的,痛苦的;可怜的,糟糕的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 investigations | |
(正式的)调查( investigation的名词复数 ); 侦查; 科学研究; 学术研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 persistent | |
adj.坚持不懈的,执意的;持续的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 condemned | |
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 crumbling | |
adj.摇摇欲坠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 astronomers | |
n.天文学者,天文学家( astronomer的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 precarious | |
adj.不安定的,靠不住的;根据不足的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 insufficient | |
adj.(for,of)不足的,不够的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |