Pierre-Joseph Proudhon was born July 15, 1809, in Besan?on, of humble7 parents. His father was a cooper, while his mother was a bright and vigorous country girl. He was of the people, the masses, and he spoke9 of it freely as an advantage. Proudhon professed10 that he always remained one of them and thus knew their life. It was early necessary that he should assist in his support, and this he did by agricultural labor11, in particular by guarding the cows as they pastured on the mountains of the Jura. Later he became a waiter in a restaurant. Time was, however, found for the school and the college, where he distinguished12 himself for unusual talents and carried off a large number of prizes and honors. The public library furnished him with reading-matter, so that he read a large number of books before he was fourteen. He used to call for as many as six books at a time. At the age of nineteen Proudhon was compelled to leave the college in order to assist his father, whose business had fallen into a sad condition. He learned the printer’s trade and soon became a corrector in a publishing house of some note, which became to him a school. The house published a large number of theological works, which he perused14 so carefully that it was afterwards supposed that he had studied at a theological[126] seminary. He learned Hebrew when they published a Bible with an interlinear translation. The result was that he was able to contribute a number of theological articles to the “Encyclopédie Catholique.”
The Académie de Besan?on having honors and prizes to distribute, proposed every year a subject for an essay. In 1839 the subject was “The Utility of the Celebration of Sunday.” Proudhon competed for the prize, but was not successful, although the book met with some praise, and passed through two editions in two years. He had, however, already been fortunate enough to secure a pension of 1500 francs, which had been founded to encourage literature and science, and placed in charge of the Académie. Besides his work demonstrating the utility of the observation of Sunday, Proudhon had written several essays of more or less merit on comparative philology15, and he was considered a very promising16 young man. But he was thinking all this time of means to elevate the laboring17 classes. When he solicited18 the votes of the Académie for the pension, he told them plainly that it was his intention to direct his studies towards the means of ameliorating the physical, moral, and intellectual condition of the most numerous and the poorest class. In a letter to Paul Ackermann, a distinguished man of letters, with whom he had formed a connection, he wrote as follows, concerning the congratulations he had received on being awarded the pension: “I have received the congratulations of more than two hundred people. Why do you think that people felicitate me? Because it is almost certain that I shall attain19 honors equal to those which the Jouffroys, the Pouillets have obtained, and perhaps, I am told, even greater honors. No one has come to me and said: ‘Proudhon,[127] you ought before everything else to devote yourself to the cause of the poor, to the enfranchisement20 of the little ones, to the instruction of the people. You will perhaps be an abomination to the rich and powerful; pursue your way as a reformer regardless of persecutions, of calumny21, of sorrow, and of death itself.’”[118]
About this time he founded a printing establishment in his native city, which appears never to have flourished greatly. He had already taken up the study of political economy, in addition to theology and philology, to both of which he hereafter devoted22 comparatively little attention. One of his first instructors23 in his new study was the able economist24, Pellegrino Rossi. His economic studies bore fruit in 1840, in his work on property, “Qu’est-ce que la Propriété?”[119]—“What is Property?” A startling answer to the question is given—viz., “Property is theft” and “Property-holders are thieves.”
The work marks a new epoch25 in the history of socialism, on several accounts. First, he attacks in it directly the chief support of individualism and the greatest obstacle to the realization26 of communism—private property. Others had proposed phalansteries, religious sects27, and social workshops, all presupposing the abolition28 of private property; but Proudhon was the first to attempt to prove directly and scientifically that private property per se was a monstrosity—was robbery. Again, he set an example of harsh and rude attacks on classes and institutions, which modern social democrats29 have not been slow to follow. He[128] could easily have expressed the thought which he wished to convey otherwise than by using the word “theft,” but he preferred the cruel, biting expression. Likewise, in condemning32 the God of the theologians, he cried out, “God is the evil!” (“Dieu c’est le mal!”) Very likely he simply meant to condemn31 certain ideas concerning God, but it was not at all necessary for him to use an expression sure to give offence and pain to many good people. In the same way he was not content to call property-holders thieves. He says elsewhere that the “proprietor33 is essentially34 a libidinous35 animal, without virtue36 and without shame.”
This reveals another side of Proudhon’s character. He felt for the poor, but he hated the rich as a class, if not individually. He tells us himself that he first experienced a feeling of shame on account of poverty, but finding existence intolerable while tormented37 by such a humiliating feeling, he succeeded in transforming it into hate and anger. Afterwards his hatred38 turned into contempt and he became calmer, though it is probable that he always retained a certain bitterness of feeling. He writes to the Académie de Besan?on: “When I sought to become your pensioner39, I was full of hate for that which exists and of projects of destruction. My hatred of privilege and of the authority of man was without measure. Perhaps I was sometimes wrong in confounding in my indignation persons and things; at present I only know how to despise and complain. In order to cease to hate, it was only necessary for me to understand.”[120]
In the third place, this book is remarkable40, because so many modern socialistic schools can be traced back[129] to it. The ideas of the anarchists41 of France at the present time are well presented in it. We also find in it a good presentation of that part of Marx’s doctrine43 of value which treats of labor-time as the measure of value, and the portion of the products which the capitalist takes under the name of profits as robbery. Marx developed it, and doubtless understood its import better than Proudhon, but nevertheless the germs of his most important theory are very plainly contained in this work on Property.[121]
Finally, the essay on Property is important because it led socialists44 and even political economists45 to a revision of their theories and a more careful observation of facts. Louis Blanc discouraged fantastical and supernatural schemes of reform; but the sharp, cutting criticism of Proudhon, directed now against the communists, now against the Saint-Simonians and Fourierists, now against the political economists, rendered them impossible. High-priests and revealers of visions could henceforth count on no favor on the part of the laborers46.
Proudhon disposed of his printing establishment in 1843, but at such a loss as to leave him in debt to the amount of 7000 francs, which, however, he was finally able to pay. His next business enterprise was the formation of a connection with a company which was engaged in transportation on the Saone and the Rhone. This occupation lasted five years, but he did not, in[130] the meantime, cease his literary labors48. In 1846 he published his “Système des Contradictions économiques ou Philosophie de la Misère.”[122] If the work, “Qu’est-ce que la Propriété?” ranks first in importance of all his works, this certainly occupies the second place. It contains a sharp criticism of socialistic and economic theories, which he opposes to one another, and shows that they are mutually destructive. Here, as elsewhere, no one has doubted the merit of his criticism. He adopted as the motto of the book “Destruam et ?dificabo”—“I will destroy and I will build up again.” He was powerful as a destroyer, but weak as a constructor. He could not keep the second part of his promise. He had become imperfectly acquainted with the Hegelian logic13 at second-hand49 through Carl Grün, who became his translator, and he sought to unite contradictories50, “thesis” and “antithesis51,” into a “synthesis.” But Hegel is not an author whom a Frenchman is likely to understand, and Proudhon did not succeed well in the use of his logical method.
Proudhon took no part in the Revolution of February, as he was not a politician, holding that all forms of government were equally vicious, and it was of little importance whether this or that party triumphed. He held himself aloof52 from any participation53 in the events which were transpiring54 until the political revolution was past, in order then to make his power more effectually felt in the settlement of social questions. In April he became editor of the Représentant du Peuple, and in June he was elected, by a large majority, to the Constituent55 Assembly as one of the representatives[131] of the Departement de la Seine. After he had seen the various social parties retire, defeated, from the scene, one after another, it became his turn to present positive measures of social reform. He had combated all socialistic sects, while maintaining persistently56 his position as a friend of the poor. What had he to offer, now that he had assisted to overthrow57 every plan of improvement which had been proposed? On the 31st of July he brought forward his scheme of organization of credit, which would guarantee labor to all in the only effectual way, as it would furnish every one with the instruments of labor. What this was we will consider presently. It is only necessary to state that it was rejected by the overwhelming majority of 691 to 2.[123] He attempted the execution of his plan without the aid of the state, by the erection of a bank, which failed about April 1, 1849, after an existence of a few weeks. Thus ended the attempt of the last great French socialist1 to carry out a scheme of social and economic regeneration. Proudhon’s paper was suppressed, but it reappeared twice under different names, before the arrest and sentence of its editor to three years’ imprisonment58 for breaking the press-laws terminated its existence. During his imprisonment he wrote his “La Révolution Sociale Démontrée par8 le Coup59 d’état du 2 Décembre”—“The Social Revolution Demonstrated by the Coup d’état of 2d December” (1851). This created a sensation, and six editions were sold in less than six months.[124] His imprisonment terminated on the 4th of June, 1852, and he retired60 to private life. He had[132] been married in 1850 to the daughter of a merchant, and it is said that his conduct as a husband and a father was exemplary. It is necessary to mention only one other work which he wrote—viz., “De la Justice dans la Révolution et dans l’église”—which appeared in 1858.[125] He shows in this book that outside of the Catholic Church and Christianity there is no God, no theology, no religion, and no faith. Has Proudhon become a Catholic and a conservative? By no means. He immediately proceeds to demonstrate that the Church is ever in conflict with justice. The book was seized eight days after its appearance, its author tried, and sentenced to a fine of 4000 francs and to three years’ imprisonment, which he escaped by flight to Belgium, where he remained until an amnesty in 1860 allowed him to return to France. He died in Passy in 1865.
It is necessary to dwell more at length on three points in Proudhon’s teachings—viz., his ideas concerning property, government, and positive reform.
“Property is theft,” says Proudhon. Every argument brought forward to sustain it destroys the institution. Some seek to justify61 it by the theory of occupation, in accordance with which theory that which belongs to no one becomes the property of him who takes possession of it.[126] But if this be admitted, then property depends upon the accidents of number of population and extent of territory. Those who are born too late will be property-less. However, if the soil originally belonged to no private[133] individual it must have belonged to all collectively, and all will not and cannot renounce62 their right to this common possession. If I fashion a plough it is mine, because I made it. Who made the earth? God. Well, let him then demand a rent for it—let him take his own. But this he will not do. His gifts are free. We see that the theory of occupation presupposes common property, and that cannot be surrendered any more than life or liberty.
The second theory of property is the labor theory. But this theory likewise destroys property. That only is mine which I produce. The earth is mine only so long as I cultivate it. The moment another labors on my farm it becomes his property. Again, labor presupposes the instruments of labor, and where is one to obtain these in a system of private, personal property, provided one does not already possess them? The theory of labor demands the abolition of property, in order that every one may have free access to the soil and to the other instruments of labor.
Property is robbery because it enables him who has not produced to consume the fruits of other people’s toil63. What I produce is worth what it costs—i.e., the time and economic goods which enter into it. If a capitalist or landlord takes away ten per cent., then the product costs me more than it is worth. I am robbed of this ten per cent. The proprietor is a thief.[127]
Shall we, then, return to the original state of society, to communism? By no means. Private property is unjust. It is robbery of the weak by the strong. Communism is the reverse injustice64. It is robbery of the strong by the weak. “Community is inequality,[134] but in an inverse65 sense from property. Property is exploitation of the weak by the strong. Community is an exploitation of the strong by the weak. In the system of property inequality of conditions results from force, under whatever name it may disguise itself—force, physical and intellectual; force of circumstances, hazard, fortune; force of acquired property, etc. In community inequality springs from mediocrity of talent and of labor, elevated to an equality with force; and this injurious equation is revolting to conscience and causes merit to murmur66.”[128]
We have now our thesis and our antithesis. The synthesis is found in possession. I may possess the instruments of labor of every kind in order to enable me to labor. It is labor which renders them mine—my own individual labor. So long as I cultivate myself a piece of land, it is mine and the product is mine. I may not rob another by charging for the use of the instruments of labor. It will be seen thus that what Proudhon really is fighting against is rent[129] and profits of capital. He allows inheritance—everything except individual ownership. Of course, when this is analyzed67, it becomes apparent that inheritance can amount to very little.
What is the ideal of government? Anarchy. We desire absolute liberty. Any control of man by man is oppression. “What form of government shall we prefer? Ah, how can you ask? replies one of my youngest readers.—You are a republican? Republican, yes; but this word defines nothing. Res publica—that is, the public thing; now, whoever wishes the[135] public thing, under any form of government, can call himself a republican. The kings also are republicans.—Ah, well, you are a democrat30? No.—What! are you a monarchist? No.—A constitutionalist? God forbid.—You are, then, an aristocrat68? Not at all.—Do you wish a mixed government? Still less.—What are you, then? I am an anarchist42.... Anarchy—the absence of master, of sovereign—such is the form of government which we approach every day, and our inveterate69 habit of taking man for a guide and his will for law makes us regard it as a heap of disorder70 and an expression of chaos71.... No one is king.... Every question of internal politics ought to be solved according to the data of the Department of Statistics; every question of international politics is a question of international statistics. The science of government belongs of right to one of the sections of the Academy of Sciences, of which the perpetual secretary necessarily becomes the first minister; and since every citizen may address a mémoire to the Academy, every citizen is a legislator; but as the opinion of no one counts except in so far as it is demonstrated to be true, no one can substitute his will for reason—no one is king.... Justice and legality are two things as independent of our consent as mathematical truth.... In order that truth should become law, it must be recognized. Now, what is it to recognize a law? It is to verify a mathematical or metaphysical operation. It is to repeat an experience, to observe a phenomenon, to prove a fact.”[130]
What positive measures of reform are proposed to bring about equality associated with anarchy? One[136] is a great national bank, in which product shall be exchanged against product without any intermediaries, so that money-mongers shall not be able to stop the circulation and thereby72 the production of goods. Paper money is to be given in exchange for whatever is brought to this place of deposit. This paper is a check, which indicates labor-time. It may be exchanged for anything else of the same value, which has cost the same labor. Products are exchanged for products, and what is received has the same value as what is given. Property must be abolished, and no landlord or capitalist may intervene and, by exacting73 toll74, make what I receive cost me more than it is worth.
What Proudhon proposed in the National Assembly was a bank which should effect exchanges of this sort. It was to be established by funds derived75 from a part of the proceeds of a tax of one third, or thirty-three and a third per cent. on revenues derived from property, and from a progressive tax on salaries of government officers. Branches were to be established in every part of France, and all were to be furnished with gratuitous77 credit. Interest has shown a tendency to decrease, which may be traced back for centuries.[131] Its normal rate is zero, and the national bank is to assist in bringing it down to this point. Everybody wants credit and everybody will be benefited by the measure.[132] All the world will give and receive credit. Rights and duties, privileges and obligations, are mutual6. We may call this scheme mutualism.[133]
But when interest becomes zero, it follows naturally[137] and inevitably78 that rents and profits become nil79. Credit enabling every one to obtain the instruments of labor without price, it is self-evident that no one will pay anything to landlord or capitalist for their use. The problem of abolishing the class of idlers is therefore solved. Henceforward property does not exist. The laborer47 receives all, and products cost no more than they are worth. This is the highest and the only true form of sociabilité. All men are associated on terms of equality; no one is subject to another.
Proudhon rejected communism. His ground of opposition80 was of a twofold nature. First, communism is based on property—not the property of an individual, but of the community. We have in it, consequently, the same kind of slavery as in our present society, save that we have many masters instead of one. “The members of a community, it is true, have nothing which is individual; but the community is proprietor, and proprietor not only of goods, but of persons and of wills. It is according to this principle of sovereign property that in every community labor, which ought to be for man only a condition imposed by nature, became a human command, and thereby odious81.”[134] Second, communism is unjust, because it is unequal. It is the robbery of the strong by the weak.
We have to ask, then, what is the equality which Proudhon desired? If he did not wish to place all on the same level as regards recompense, what did he wish? He tells us that “equality consists in the equality of conditions—that is, of means—not in the equality of well-being82, which with equal means ought[138] to be the work of the laborer.”[135] Was he not, then, a Saint-Simonian? did he not wish to proportion reward to services? He tells us distinctly, No.[136] He combats Saint-Simonism as unjust and impracticable. He also speaks of equality as the corner-stone of his system. The highest stage of society towards which we are moving he calls liberty—that is, the synthesis of the thesis, community, and the antithesis, property—but “liberty is equality, because liberty exists only in the social state, and outside of equality there is no society.” And he again and again condemns83 inequality of wages and recompense in his new society. Some writers, dwelling84 merely upon his condemnation85 of community, have said that he was not in favor of equality. This is a mistake. But how are we to reconcile his statements? They are contradictories. Where is the synthesis? It is found in the fact that all will hereafter produce alike. When possession takes the place of property, each one will labor equally, and the products, being measured by labor-time, will be equal in value. Equality of conditions becomes absolute equality. “On the one hand, the task of each laborer being easy and short, and the means of performing it successfully being equal, how could there, then, be great and small producers? On the other hand, the functions all being equal, either by the real equivalence of talents and capacities or by social co-operation, how can a functionary86, arguing from the excellence87 of his work, demand a proportional salary?” (i.e., a remuneration larger than the[139] remuneration of others, in proportion to the superiority of his work).
“But what do I say? In equality the salaries are always proportional to faculties88. But what is the salary or remuneration received? It is that which composes the reproductive consumption of the laborer. The act itself by which the laborer produces is then this consumption, equal to his production. When the astronomer89 produces observations, the poet verses, the savant experiences, they consume instruments, books, travels, etc.; now, if society provides for this consumption, what other proportionality of honors can the astronomer, the savant, and the poet demand? Let us conclude, then, that in equality, and in equality alone, the adage90 of Saint-Simon, ‘To each one according to his capacity, to each capacity according to its works,’ finds its full and complete application.”[137]
In intention, then, Proudhon was a communist in the sense of the definition given in this work. No man ever preached more plainly and unreservedly absolute equality as an ideal. He was not a communist in the sense of favoring communities such as we see in a few places at present, because they involve control and authority. He was, on the contrary, in favor of anarchic equality. The distinction might be made by saying that he was a communist, but not a communitarian.
I have, nevertheless, spoken of him several times as a socialist, because the entire tendency of every positive proposal which he made was socialistic, and not communistic. Equality has no logical connection with his projects. He proposed to transform property into[140] possession, which means simply limiting very materially the rights of property. Now, how could this change be so restricted without allowing inequalities to arise? Each one cultivates his land as he pleases and works as he will, all authority being banished91 from the face of the earth. Can any one, without resorting to some supernatural and unwarranted theory, suppose that all would derive76 the same products from the same instruments? Then let us take up the case of gratuitous credit. Will all avail themselves of it with equal profit in anarchy? What is to prevent my accumulating labor receipts if my production exceeds consumption? Or shall the state or some outside body prevent my taking more than I consume from the magazines or banks, whatever they are called? If so, do we not have all the interference and control of the hated community? It is thus seen that Proudhon is inconsistent as well as paradoxical, and is unable to effect his synthesis.
The following ten statements contain, in Proudhon’s own words, a résumé of the system which we have just examined:
“I. Individual possession is the condition of social life; ... Property is the suicide of society....
“II. The right of occupation being equal for all, possession varies according to the number of possessors....
“III. The effect of labor being the same for all, property is lost by its use on the part of others and by rent.
“IV. All human labor proceeding92 necessarily from a collective force, all property becomes, for the same reason, collective and indivisible; in terms more precise, labor destroys property.
“V. Every capacity for labor being, the same as every instrument of labor, an accumulated capital or collective property, inequality of remuneration and of fortune, under pretext93 of inequality of capacity, is injustice and theft.
“VI. Commerce has for its necessary conditions the liberty of contractors[141] and the equivalence of products exchanged; now, value having for its expression the sum of the time and of the expense which each product costs, and liberty being inviolable, the laborers necessarily remain equal in wages, as they are in duties and in rights.
“VII. Products are purchased only by products; now, the condition of every exchange being the equivalence of products, profits from exchange are impossible and unjust. Observe this principle of the most elementary economy, and pauperism94, luxury, oppression, vice2, crime, and hunger will disappear from among us.
“VIII. Men are associated by the physical and mathematical law of production; ...
“IX. Free association, liberty, which confines itself to the maintenance of equality in the means of production and equivalence in exchanges, is the only form of society possible, just, and true.
“X. Politics is the science of liberty; the government of man by man, under whatever name it may disguise itself, is oppression. The highest form of society is found in the union of order and anarchy.”[138]
Proudhon’s earnestness and sincerity95 can scarcely be doubted. We must give him credit for honesty, however strong our conviction that his schemes are utterly96 impracticable, and however severely97 we condemn the bitterness and injustice with which his views are presented. He closes his first mémoire on property with the following appeal to the Deity98 to hasten the coming emancipation99 and to witness his unselfish devotion: “O God of liberty! God of equality! Thou God, who hast placed in my heart the sentiment of justice before my reason comprehended it, hear my ardent100 prayer. Thou hast dictated101 that which I have written. Thou hast formed my thought, thou hast directed my studies, thou hast separated my spirit from curiosity and my heart from attachment102, in order that I should publish the truth before the master[142] and the slave. I have spoken as thou hast given me power and talent; it remains103 for thee to complete thy work. Thou knowest whether I have sought my interest or thy glory. O God of liberty! May my memory perish, if humanity may but be free; if I may but see in my obscurity the people finally instructed, if noble instructors but enlighten it, if disinterested104 hearts but guide it. Shorten, if it may be, our time of trial; smother105 inequality, pride, and avarice106; confound this idolatry of glory which retains us in abjection107; teach thy poor children that in the haven108 of liberty there are no more heroes nor grand men. Inspire the strong one, the wealthy one, whose name my lips shall never pronounce before thee, with horror on account of his robberies.... Then the great and the small, the rich and the poor, will unite in one ineffable109 fraternity; and all together, chanting a new hymn110, will re-erect thy altar, O God of liberty and of equality!”
点击收听单词发音
1 socialist | |
n.社会主义者;adj.社会主义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 explicitly | |
ad.明确地,显然地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 contrived | |
adj.不自然的,做作的;虚构的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 anarchy | |
n.无政府状态;社会秩序混乱,无秩序 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 mutual | |
adj.相互的,彼此的;共同的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 humble | |
adj.谦卑的,恭顺的;地位低下的;v.降低,贬低 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 par | |
n.标准,票面价值,平均数量;adj.票面的,平常的,标准的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 spoke | |
n.(车轮的)辐条;轮辐;破坏某人的计划;阻挠某人的行动 v.讲,谈(speak的过去式);说;演说;从某种观点来说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 professed | |
公开声称的,伪称的,已立誓信教的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 labor | |
n.劳动,努力,工作,劳工;分娩;vi.劳动,努力,苦干;vt.详细分析;麻烦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 logic | |
n.逻辑(学);逻辑性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 perused | |
v.读(某篇文字)( peruse的过去式和过去分词 );(尤指)细阅;审阅;匆匆读或心不在焉地浏览(某篇文字) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 philology | |
n.语言学;语文学 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 promising | |
adj.有希望的,有前途的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 laboring | |
n.劳动,操劳v.努力争取(for)( labor的现在分词 );苦干;详细分析;(指引擎)缓慢而困难地运转 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 solicited | |
v.恳求( solicit的过去式和过去分词 );(指娼妇)拉客;索求;征求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 attain | |
vt.达到,获得,完成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 enfranchisement | |
选举权 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 calumny | |
n.诽谤,污蔑,中伤 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 devoted | |
adj.忠诚的,忠实的,热心的,献身于...的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 instructors | |
指导者,教师( instructor的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 economist | |
n.经济学家,经济专家,节俭的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 epoch | |
n.(新)时代;历元 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 realization | |
n.实现;认识到,深刻了解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 sects | |
n.宗派,教派( sect的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 abolition | |
n.废除,取消 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 democrats | |
n.民主主义者,民主人士( democrat的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 democrat | |
n.民主主义者,民主人士;民主党党员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 condemn | |
vt.谴责,指责;宣判(罪犯),判刑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 condemning | |
v.(通常因道义上的原因而)谴责( condemn的现在分词 );宣判;宣布…不能使用;迫使…陷于不幸的境地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 proprietor | |
n.所有人;业主;经营者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 essentially | |
adv.本质上,实质上,基本上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 libidinous | |
adj.淫荡的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 tormented | |
饱受折磨的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 hatred | |
n.憎恶,憎恨,仇恨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 pensioner | |
n.领养老金的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 remarkable | |
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 anarchists | |
无政府主义者( anarchist的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 anarchist | |
n.无政府主义者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 doctrine | |
n.教义;主义;学说 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 socialists | |
社会主义者( socialist的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 economists | |
n.经济学家,经济专家( economist的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 laborers | |
n.体力劳动者,工人( laborer的名词复数 );(熟练工人的)辅助工 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 laborer | |
n.劳动者,劳工 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 labors | |
v.努力争取(for)( labor的第三人称单数 );苦干;详细分析;(指引擎)缓慢而困难地运转 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 second-hand | |
adj.用过的,旧的,二手的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 contradictories | |
n.矛盾的,抵触的( contradictory的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 antithesis | |
n.对立;相对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 aloof | |
adj.远离的;冷淡的,漠不关心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 participation | |
n.参与,参加,分享 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 transpiring | |
(事实,秘密等)被人知道( transpire的现在分词 ); 泄露; 显露; 发生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 constituent | |
n.选民;成分,组分;adj.组成的,构成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 persistently | |
ad.坚持地;固执地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 overthrow | |
v.推翻,打倒,颠覆;n.推翻,瓦解,颠覆 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 imprisonment | |
n.关押,监禁,坐牢 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 coup | |
n.政变;突然而成功的行动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 retired | |
adj.隐退的,退休的,退役的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 justify | |
vt.证明…正当(或有理),为…辩护 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 renounce | |
v.放弃;拒绝承认,宣布与…断绝关系 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 toil | |
vi.辛劳工作,艰难地行动;n.苦工,难事 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 injustice | |
n.非正义,不公正,不公平,侵犯(别人的)权利 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 inverse | |
adj.相反的,倒转的,反转的;n.相反之物;v.倒转 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 murmur | |
n.低语,低声的怨言;v.低语,低声而言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 analyzed | |
v.分析( analyze的过去式和过去分词 );分解;解释;对…进行心理分析 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 aristocrat | |
n.贵族,有贵族气派的人,上层人物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 inveterate | |
adj.积习已深的,根深蒂固的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 disorder | |
n.紊乱,混乱;骚动,骚乱;疾病,失调 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 chaos | |
n.混乱,无秩序 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 exacting | |
adj.苛求的,要求严格的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 toll | |
n.过路(桥)费;损失,伤亡人数;v.敲(钟) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 derive | |
v.取得;导出;引申;来自;源自;出自 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 gratuitous | |
adj.无偿的,免费的;无缘无故的,不必要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 inevitably | |
adv.不可避免地;必然发生地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 nil | |
n.无,全无,零 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 odious | |
adj.可憎的,讨厌的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 well-being | |
n.安康,安乐,幸福 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 condemns | |
v.(通常因道义上的原因而)谴责( condemn的第三人称单数 );宣判;宣布…不能使用;迫使…陷于不幸的境地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 dwelling | |
n.住宅,住所,寓所 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 condemnation | |
n.谴责; 定罪 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 functionary | |
n.官员;公职人员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 excellence | |
n.优秀,杰出,(pl.)优点,美德 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 faculties | |
n.能力( faculty的名词复数 );全体教职员;技巧;院 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 astronomer | |
n.天文学家 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 adage | |
n.格言,古训 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 banished | |
v.放逐,驱逐( banish的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 proceeding | |
n.行动,进行,(pl.)会议录,学报 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 pretext | |
n.借口,托词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 pauperism | |
n.有被救济的资格,贫困 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 sincerity | |
n.真诚,诚意;真实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 utterly | |
adv.完全地,绝对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 severely | |
adv.严格地;严厉地;非常恶劣地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 deity | |
n.神,神性;被奉若神明的人(或物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 emancipation | |
n.(从束缚、支配下)解放 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 ardent | |
adj.热情的,热烈的,强烈的,烈性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 dictated | |
v.大声讲或读( dictate的过去式和过去分词 );口授;支配;摆布 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 attachment | |
n.附属物,附件;依恋;依附 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 disinterested | |
adj.不关心的,不感兴趣的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 smother | |
vt./vi.使窒息;抑制;闷死;n.浓烟;窒息 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 avarice | |
n.贪婪;贪心 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 abjection | |
n. 卑鄙, 落魄 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 haven | |
n.安全的地方,避难所,庇护所 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 ineffable | |
adj.无法表达的,不可言喻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 hymn | |
n.赞美诗,圣歌,颂歌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |