Under the selective surveillance of the law of conspicuous waste there grows up a code of accredited12 canons of consumption, the effect of which is to hold the consumer up to a standard of expensiveness and wastefulness14 in his consumption of goods and in his employment of time and effort. This growth of prescriptive usage has an immediate15 effect upon economic life, but it has also an indirect and remoter effect upon conduct in other respects as well. Habits of thought with respect to the expression of life in any given direction unavoidably affect the habitual16 view of what is good and right in life in other directions also. In the organic complex of habits of thought which make up the substance of an individual's conscious life the economic interest does not lie isolated17 and distinct from all other interests. Something, for instance, has already been said of its relation to the canons of reputability.
The principle of conspicuous waste guides the formation of habits of thought as to what is honest and reputable in life and in commodities. In so doing, this principle will traverse other norms of conduct which do not primarily have to do with the code of pecuniary18 honor, but which have, directly or incidentally, an economic significance of some magnitude. So the canon of honorific waste may, immediately or remotely, influence the sense of duty, the sense of beauty, the sense of utility, the sense of devotional or ritualistic fitness, and the scientific sense of truth.
It is scarcely necessary to go into a discussion here of the particular points at which, or the particular manner in which, the canon of honorific expenditure19 habitually20 traverses the canons of moral conduct. The matter is one which has received large attention and illustration at the hands of those whose office it is to watch and admonish21 with respect to any departures from the accepted code of morals. In modern communities, where the dominant22 economic and legal feature of the community's life is the institution of private property, one of the salient features of the code of morals is the sacredness of property. There needs no insistence23 or illustration to gain assent24 to the proposition that the habit of holding private property inviolate25 is traversed by the other habit of seeking wealth for the sake of the good repute to be gained through its conspicuous consumption. Most offenses26 against property, especially offenses of an appreciable magnitude, come under this head. It is also a matter of common notoriety and byword that in offenses which result in a large accession of property to the offender28 he does not ordinarily incur29 the extreme penalty or the extreme obloquy30 with which his offenses would be visited on the ground of the naive31 moral code alone. The thief or swindler who has gained great wealth by his delinquency has a better chance than the small thief of escaping the rigorous penalty of the law and some good repute accrues32 to him from his increased wealth and from his spending the irregularly acquired possessions in a seemly manner. A well-bred expenditure of his booty especially appeals with great effect to persons of a cultivated sense of the proprieties34, and goes far to mitigate35 the sense of moral turpitude36 with which his dereliction is viewed by them. It may be noted37 also—and it is more immediately to the point—that we are all inclined to condone38 an offense27 against property in the case of a man whose motive is the worthy39 one of providing the means of a "decent" manner of life for his wife and children. If it is added that the wife has been "nurtured40 in the lap of luxury," that is accepted as an additional extenuating41 circumstance. That is to say, we are prone42 to condone such an offense where its aim is the honorific one of enabling the offender's wife to perform for him such an amount of vicarious consumption of time and substance as is demanded by the standard of pecuniary decency. In such a case the habit of approving the accustomed degree of conspicuous waste traverses the habit of deprecating violations43 of ownership, to the extent even of sometimes leaving the award of praise or blame uncertain. This is peculiarly true where the dereliction involves an appreciable predatory or piratical element.
This topic need scarcely be pursued further here; but the remark may not be out of place that all that considerable body of morals that clusters about the concept of an inviolable ownership is itself a psychological precipitate46 of the traditional meritoriousness48 of wealth. And it should be added that this wealth which is held sacred is valued primarily for the sake of the good repute to be got through its conspicuous consumption. The bearing of pecuniary decency upon the scientific spirit or the quest of knowledge will be taken up in some detail in a separate chapter. Also as regards the sense of devout49 or ritual merit and adequacy in this connection, little need be said in this place. That topic will also come up incidentally in a later chapter. Still, this usage of honorific expenditure has much to say in shaping popular tastes as to what is right and meritorious47 in sacred matters, and the bearing of the principle of conspicuous waste upon some of the commonplace devout observances and conceits50 may therefore be pointed51 out.
Obviously, the canon of conspicuous waste is accountable for a great portion of what may be called devout consumption; as, e.g., the consumption of sacred edifices52, vestments, and other goods of the same class. Even in those modern cults53 to whose divinities is imputed55 a predilection56 for temples not built with hands, the sacred buildings and the other properties of the cult33 are constructed and decorated with some view to a reputable degree of wasteful13 expenditure. And it needs but little either of observation or introspection—and either will serve the turn—to assure us that the expensive splendor57 of the house of worship has an appreciable uplifting and mellowing58 effect upon the worshipper's frame of mind. It will serve to enforce the same fact if we reflect upon the sense of abject59 shamefulness60 with which any evidence of indigence61 or squalor about the sacred place affects all beholders. The accessories of any devout observance should be pecuniarily63 above reproach. This requirement is imperative64, whatever latitude65 may be allowed with regard to these accessories in point of aesthetic66 or other serviceability. It may also be in place to notice that in all communities, especially in neighborhoods where the standard of pecuniary decency for dwellings68 is not high, the local sanctuary69 is more ornate, more conspicuously70 wasteful in its architecture and decoration, than the dwelling67 houses of the congregation. This is true of nearly all denominations71 and cults, whether Christian72 or Pagan, but it is true in a peculiar45 degree of the older and maturer cults. At the same time the sanctuary commonly contributes little if anything to the physical comfort of the members. Indeed, the sacred structure not only serves the physical well-being73 of the members to but a slight extent, as compared with their humbler dwelling-houses; but it is felt by all men that a right and enlightened sense of the true, the beautiful, and the good demands that in all expenditure on the sanctuary anything that might serve the comfort of the worshipper should be conspicuously absent. If any element of comfort is admitted in the fittings of the sanctuary, it should be at least scrupulously74 screened and masked under an ostensible75 austerity. In the most reputable latter-day houses of worship, where no expense is spared, the principle of austerity is carried to the length of making the fittings of the place a means of mortifying76 the flesh, especially in appearance. There are few persons of delicate tastes, in the matter of devout consumption to whom this austerely78 wasteful discomfort79 does not appeal as intrinsically right and good. Devout consumption is of the nature of vicarious consumption. This canon of devout austerity is based on the pecuniary reputability of conspicuously wasteful consumption, backed by the principle that vicarious consumption should conspicuously not conduce to the comfort of the vicarious consumer.
The sanctuary and its fittings have something of this austerity in all the cults in which the saint or divinity to whom the sanctuary pertains80 is not conceived to be present and make personal use of the property for the gratification of luxurious81 tastes imputed to him. The character of the sacred paraphernalia82 is somewhat different in this respect in those cults where the habits of life imputed to the divinity more nearly approach those of an earthly patriarchal potentate—where he is conceived to make use of these consumable goods in person. In the latter case the sanctuary and its fittings take on more of the fashion given to goods destined83 for the conspicuous consumption of a temporal master or owner. On the other hand, where the sacred apparatus is simply employed in the divinity's service, that is to say, where it is consumed vicariously on his account by his servants, there the sacred properties take the character suited to goods that are destined for vicarious consumption only.
In the latter case the sanctuary and the sacred apparatus are so contrived84 as not to enhance the comfort or fullness of life of the vicarious consumer, or at any rate not to convey the impression that the end of their consumption is the consumer's comfort. For the end of vicarious consumption is to enhance, not the fullness of life of the consumer, but the pecuniary repute of the master for whose behoof the consumption takes place. Therefore priestly vestments are notoriously expensive, ornate, and inconvenient85; and in the cults where the priestly servitor of the divinity is not conceived to serve him in the capacity of consort86, they are of an austere77, comfortless fashion. And such it is felt that they should be.
It is not only in establishing a devout standard of decent expensiveness that the principle of waste invades the domain87 of the canons of ritual serviceability. It touches the ways as well as the means, and draws on vicarious leisure as well as on vicarious consumption. Priestly demeanor88 at its best is aloof89, leisurely90, perfunctory, and uncontaminated with suggestions of sensuous91 pleasure. This holds true, in different degrees of course, for the different cults and denominations; but in the priestly life of all anthropomorphic cults the marks of a vicarious consumption of time are visible.
The same pervading92 canon of vicarious leisure is also visibly present in the exterior93 details of devout observances and need only be pointed out in order to become obvious to all beholders. All ritual has a notable tendency to reduce itself to a rehearsal94 of formulas. This development of formula is most noticeable in the maturer cults, which have at the same time a more austere, ornate, and severe priestly life and garb95; but it is perceptible also in the forms and methods of worship of the newer and fresher sects96, whose tastes in respect of priests, vestments, and sanctuaries97 are less exacting98. The rehearsal of the service (the term "service" carries a suggestion significant for the point in question) grows more perfunctory as the cult gains in age and consistency99, and this perfunctoriness of the rehearsal is very pleasing to the correct devout taste. And with a good reason, for the fact of its being perfunctory goes to say pointedly100 that the master for whom it is performed is exalted101 above the vulgar need of actually proficuous service on the part of his servants. They are unprofitable servants, and there is an honorific implication for their master in their remaining unprofitable. It is needless to point out the close analogy at this point between the priestly office and the office of the footman. It is pleasing to our sense of what is fitting in these matters, in either case, to recognize in the obvious perfunctoriness of the service that it is a pro11 forma execution only. There should be no show of agility102 or of dexterous103 manipulation in the execution of the priestly office, such as might suggest a capacity for turning off the work.
In all this there is of course an obvious implication as to the temperament104, tastes, propensities105, and habits of life imputed to the divinity by worshippers who live under the tradition of these pecuniary canons of reputability. Through its pervading men's habits of thought, the principle of conspicuous waste has colored the worshippers' notions of the divinity and of the relation in which the human subject stands to him. It is of course in the more naive cults that this suffusion106 of pecuniary beauty is most patent, but it is visible throughout. All peoples, at whatever stage of culture or degree of enlightenment, are fain to eke107 out a sensibly scant108 degree of authentic109 formation regarding the personality and habitual surroundings of their divinities. In so calling in the aid of fancy to enrich and fill in their picture of the divinity's presence and manner of life they habitually impute54 to him such traits as go to make up their ideal of a worthy man. And in seeking communion with the divinity the ways and means of approach are assimilated as nearly as may be to the divine ideal that is in men's minds at the time. It is felt that the divine presence is entered with the best grace, and with the best effect, according to certain accepted methods and with the accompaniment of certain material circumstances which in popular apprehension110 are peculiarly consonant111 with the divine nature. This popularly accepted ideal of the bearing and paraphernalia adequate to such occasions of communion is, of course, to a good extent shaped by the popular apprehension of what is intrinsically worthy and beautiful in human carriage and surroundings on all occasions of dignified112 intercourse113. It would on this account be misleading to attempt an analysis of devout demeanor by referring all evidences of the presence of a pecuniary standard of reputability back directly and baldly to the underlying114 norm of pecuniary emulation115. So it would also be misleading to ascribe to the divinity, as popularly conceived, a jealous regard for his pecuniary standing116 and a habit of avoiding and condemning117 squalid situations and surroundings simply because they are under grade in the pecuniary respect.
And still, after all allowance has been made, it appears that the canons of pecuniary reputability do, directly or indirectly118, materially affect our notions of the attributes of divinity, as well as our notions of what are the fit and adequate manner and circumstances of divine communion. It is felt that the divinity must be of a peculiarly serene119 and leisurely habit of life. And whenever his local habitation is pictured in poetic120 imagery, for edification or in appeal to the devout fancy, the devout word-painter, as a matter of course, brings out before his auditors121' imagination a throne with a profusion122 of the insignia of opulence123 and power, and surrounded by a great number of servitors. In the common run of such presentations of the celestial124 abodes125, the office of this corps126 of servants is a vicarious leisure, their time and efforts being in great measure taken up with an industrially unproductive rehearsal of the meritorious characteristics and exploits of the divinity; while the background of the presentation is filled with the shimmer127 of the precious metals and of the more expensive varieties of precious stones. It is only in the crasser128 expressions of devout fancy that this intrusion of pecuniary canons into the devout ideals reaches such an extreme. An extreme case occurs in the devout imagery of the Negro population of the South. Their word-painters are unable to descend129 to anything cheaper than gold; so that in this case the insistence on pecuniary beauty gives a startling effect in yellow—such as would be unbearable130 to a soberer taste. Still, there is probably no cult in which ideals of pecuniary merit have not been called in to supplement the ideals of ceremonial adequacy that guide men's conception of what is right in the matter of sacred apparatus.
Similarly it is felt—and the sentiment is acted upon—that the priestly servitors of the divinity should not engage in industrially productive work; that work of any kind—any employment which is of tangible131 human use—must not be carried on in the divine presence, or within the precincts of the sanctuary; that whoever comes into the presence should come cleansed132 of all profane133 industrial features in his apparel or person, and should come clad in garments of more than everyday expensiveness; that on holidays set apart in honor of or for communion with the divinity no work that is of human use should be performed by any one. Even the remoter, lay dependents should render a vicarious leisure to the extent of one day in seven. In all these deliverances of men's uninstructed sense of what is fit and proper in devout observance and in the relations of the divinity, the effectual presence of the canons of pecuniary reputability is obvious enough, whether these canons have had their effect on the devout judgment134 in this respect immediately or at the second remove.
These canons of reputability have had a similar, but more far-reaching and more specifically determinable, effect upon the popular sense of beauty or serviceability in consumable goods. The requirements of pecuniary decency have, to a very appreciable extent, influenced the sense of beauty and of utility in articles of use or beauty. Articles are to an extent preferred for use on account of their being conspicuously wasteful; they are felt to be serviceable somewhat in proportion as they are wasteful and ill adapted to their ostensible use.
The utility of articles valued for their beauty depends closely upon the expensiveness of the articles. A homely135 illustration will bring out this dependence136. A hand-wrought137 silver spoon, of a commercial value of some ten to twenty dollars, is not ordinarily more serviceable—in the first sense of the word—than a machine-made spoon of the same material. It may not even be more serviceable than a machine-made spoon of some "base" metal, such as aluminum138, the value of which may be no more than some ten to twenty cents. The former of the two utensils is, in fact, commonly a less effective contrivance for its ostensible purpose than the latter. The objection is of course ready to hand that, in taking this view of the matter, one of the chief uses, if not the chief use, of the costlier139 spoon is ignored; the hand-wrought spoon gratifies our taste, our sense of the beautiful, while that made by machinery140 out of the base metal has no useful office beyond a brute141 efficiency. The facts are no doubt as the objection states them, but it will be evident on rejection142 that the objection is after all more plausible143 than conclusive144. It appears (1) that while the different materials of which the two spoons are made each possesses beauty and serviceability for the purpose for which it is used, the material of the hand-wrought spoon is some one hundred times more valuable than the baser metal, without very greatly excelling the latter in intrinsic beauty of grain or color, and without being in any appreciable degree superior in point of mechanical serviceability; (2) if a close inspection145 should show that the supposed hand-wrought spoon were in reality only a very clever citation146 of hand-wrought goods, but an imitation so cleverly wrought as to give the same impression of line and surface to any but a minute examination by a trained eye, the utility of the article, including the gratification which the user derives147 from its contemplation as an object of beauty, would immediately decline by some eighty or ninety per cent, or even more; (3) if the two spoons are, to a fairly close observer, so nearly identical in appearance that the lighter148 weight of the spurious article alone betrays it, this identity of form and color will scarcely add to the value of the machine-made spoon, nor appreciably149 enhance the gratification of the user's "sense of beauty" in contemplating150 it, so long as the cheaper spoon is not a novelty, ad so long as it can be procured151 at a nominal152 cost. The case of the spoons is typical. The superior gratification derived153 from the use and contemplation of costly154 and supposedly beautiful products is, commonly, in great measure a gratification of our sense of costliness155 masquerading under the name of beauty. Our higher appreciation156 of the superior article is an appreciation of its superior honorific character, much more frequently than it is an unsophisticated appreciation of its beauty. The requirement of conspicuous wastefulness is not commonly present, consciously, in our canons of taste, but it is none the less present as a constraining norm selectively shaping and sustaining our sense of what is beautiful, and guiding our discrimination with respect to what may legitimately157 be approved as beautiful and what may not.
It is at this point, where the beautiful and the honorific meet and blend, that a discrimination between serviceability and wastefulness is most difficult in any concrete case. It frequently happens that an article which serves the honorific purpose of conspicuous waste is at the same time a beautiful object; and the same application of labor158 to which it owes its utility for the former purpose may, and often does, give beauty of form and color to the article. The question is further complicated by the fact that many objects, as, for instance, the precious stones and the metals and some other materials used for adornment159 and decoration, owe their utility as items of conspicuous waste to an antecedent utility as objects of beauty. Gold, for instance, has a high degree of sensuous beauty very many if not most of the highly prized works of art are intrinsically beautiful, though often with material qualification; the like is true of some stuffs used for clothing, of some landscapes, and of many other things in less degree. Except for this intrinsic beauty which they possess, these objects would scarcely have been coveted160 as they are, or have become monopolized161 objects of pride to their possessors and users. But the utility of these things to the possessor is commonly due less to their intrinsic beauty than to the honor which their possession and consumption confers, or to the obloquy which it wards162 off.
Apart from their serviceability in other respects, these objects are beautiful and have a utility as such; they are valuable on this account if they can be appropriated or monopolized; they are, therefore, coveted as valuable possessions, and their exclusive enjoyment163 gratifies the possessor's sense of pecuniary superiority at the same time that their contemplation gratifies his sense of beauty. But their beauty, in the naive sense of the word, is the occasion rather than the ground of their monopolization164 or of their commercial value. "Great as is the sensuous beauty of gems165, their rarity and price adds an expression of distinction to them, which they would never have if they were cheap." There is, indeed, in the common run of cases under this head, relatively166 little incentive167 to the exclusive possession and use of these beautiful things, except on the ground of their honorific character as items of conspicuous waste. Most objects of this general class, with the partial exception of articles of personal adornment, would serve all other purposes than the honorific one equally well, whether owned by the person viewing them or not; and even as regards personal ornaments169 it is to be added that their chief purpose is to lend éclat to the person of their wearer (or owner) by comparison with other persons who are compelled to do without. The aesthetic serviceability of objects of beauty is not greatly nor universally heightened by possession.
The generalization170 for which the discussion so far affords ground is that any valuable object in order to appeal to our sense of beauty must conform to the requirements of beauty and of expensiveness both. But this is not all. Beyond this the canon of expensiveness also affects our tastes in such a way as to inextricably blend the marks of expensiveness, in our appreciation, with the beautiful features of the object, and to subsume the resultant effect under the head of an appreciation of beauty simply. The marks of expensiveness come to be accepted as beautiful features of the expensive articles. They are pleasing as being marks of honorific costliness, and the pleasure which they afford on this score blends with that afforded by the beautiful form and color of the object; so that we often declare that an article of apparel, for instance, is "perfectly171 lovely," when pretty much all that an analysis of the aesthetic value of the article would leave ground for is the declaration that it is pecuniarily honorific.
This blending and confusion of the elements of expensiveness and of beauty is, perhaps, best exemplified in articles of dress and of household furniture. The code of reputability in matters of dress decides what shapes, colors, materials, and general effects in human apparel are for the time to be accepted as suitable; and departures from the code are offensive to our taste, supposedly as being departures from aesthetic truth. The approval with which we look upon fashionable attire172 is by no means to be accounted pure make-believe. We readily, and for the most part with utter sincerity173, find those things pleasing that are in vogue174. Shaggy dress-stuffs and pronounced color effects, for instance, offend us at times when the vogue is goods of a high, glossy176 finish and neutral colors. A fancy bonnet177 of this year's model unquestionably appeals to our sensibilities today much more forcibly than an equally fancy bonnet of the model of last year; although when viewed in the perspective of a quarter of a century, it would, I apprehend178, be a matter of the utmost difficulty to award the palm for intrinsic beauty to the one rather than to the other of these structures. So, again, it may be remarked that, considered simply in their physical juxtaposition179 with the human form, the high gloss175 of a gentleman's hat or of a patent-leather shoe has no more of intrinsic beauty than a similarly high gloss on a threadbare sleeve; and yet there is no question but that all well-bred people (in the Occidental civilized180 communities) instinctively181 and unaffectedly cleave183 to the one as a phenomenon of great beauty, and eschew184 the other as offensive to every sense to which it can appeal. It is extremely doubtful if any one could be induced to wear such a contrivance as the high hat of civilized society, except for some urgent reason based on other than aesthetic grounds.
By further habituation to an appreciative185 perception of the marks of expensiveness in goods, and by habitually identifying beauty with reputability, it comes about that a beautiful article which is not expensive is accounted not beautiful. In this way it has happened, for instance, that some beautiful flowers pass conventionally for offensive weeds; others that can be cultivated with relative ease are accepted and admired by the lower middle class, who can afford no more expensive luxuries of this kind; but these varieties are rejected as vulgar by those people who are better able to pay for expensive flowers and who are educated to a higher schedule of pecuniary beauty in the florist's products; while still other flowers, of no greater intrinsic beauty than these, are cultivated at great cost and call out much admiration187 from flower-lovers whose tastes have been matured under the critical guidance of a polite environment.
The same variation in matters of taste, from one class of society to another, is visible also as regards many other kinds of consumable goods, as, for example, is the case with furniture, houses, parks, and gardens. This diversity of views as to what is beautiful in these various classes of goods is not a diversity of the norm according to which the unsophisticated sense of the beautiful works. It is not a constitutional difference of endowments in the aesthetic respect, but rather a difference in the code of reputability which specifies188 what objects properly lie within the scope of honorific consumption for the class to which the critic belongs. It is a difference in the traditions of propriety189 with respect to the kinds of things which may, without derogation to the consumer, be consumed under the head of objects of taste and art. With a certain allowance for variations to be accounted for on other grounds, these traditions are determined190, more or less rigidly191, by the pecuniary plane of life of the class.
Everyday life affords many curious illustrations of the way in which the code of pecuniary beauty in articles of use varies from class to class, as well as of the way in which the conventional sense of beauty departs in its deliverances from the sense untutored by the requirements of pecuniary repute. Such a fact is the lawn, or the close-cropped yard or park, which appeals so unaffectedly to the taste of the Western peoples. It appears especially to appeal to the tastes of the well-to-do classes in those communities in which the dolicho-blond element predominates in an appreciable degree. The lawn unquestionably has an element of sensuous beauty, simply as an object of apperception, and as such no doubt it appeals pretty directly to the eye of nearly all races and all classes; but it is, perhaps, more unquestionably beautiful to the eye of the dolicho-blond than to most other varieties of men. This higher appreciation of a stretch of greensward in this ethnic192 element than in the other elements of the population, goes along with certain other features of the dolicho-blond temperament that indicate that this racial element had once been for a long time a pastoral people inhabiting a region with a humid climate. The close-cropped lawn is beautiful in the eyes of a people whose inherited bent193 it is to readily find pleasure in contemplating a well-preserved pasture or grazing land.
For the aesthetic purpose the lawn is a cow pasture; and in some cases today—where the expensiveness of the attendant circumstances bars out any imputation194 of thrift195—the idyl of the dolicho-blond is rehabilitated196 in the introduction of a cow into a lawn or private ground. In such cases the cow made use of is commonly of an expensive breed. The vulgar suggestion of thrift, which is nearly inseparable from the cow, is a standing objection to the decorative197 use of this animal. So that in all cases, except where luxurious surroundings negate198 this suggestion, the use of the cow as an object of taste must be avoided. Where the predilection for some grazing animal to fill out the suggestion of the pasture is too strong to be suppressed, the cow's place is often given to some more or less inadequate199 substitute, such as deer, antelopes200, or some such exotic beast. These substitutes, although less beautiful to the pastoral eye of Western man than the cow, are in such cases preferred because of their superior expensiveness or futility201, and their consequent repute. They are not vulgarly lucrative202 either in fact or in suggestion.
Public parks of course fall in the same category with the lawn; they too, at their best, are imitations of the pasture. Such a park is of course best kept by grazing, and the cattle on the grass are themselves no mean addition to the beauty of the thing, as need scarcely be insisted on with anyone who has once seen a well-kept pasture. But it is worth noting, as an expression of the pecuniary element in popular taste, that such a method of keeping public grounds is seldom resorted to. The best that is done by skilled workmen under the supervision203 of a trained keeper is a more or less close imitation of a pasture, but the result invariably falls somewhat short of the artistic204 effect of grazing. But to the average popular apprehension a herd205 of cattle so pointedly suggests thrift and usefulness that their presence in the public pleasure ground would be intolerably cheap. This method of keeping grounds is comparatively inexpensive, therefore it is indecorous.
Of the same general bearing is another feature of public grounds. There is a studious exhibition of expensiveness coupled with a make-believe of simplicity206 and crude serviceability. Private grounds also show the same physiognomy wherever they are in the management or ownership of persons whose tastes have been formed under middle-class habits of life or under the upper-class traditions of no later a date than the childhood of the generation that is now passing. Grounds which conform to the instructed tastes of the latter-day upper class do not show these features in so marked a degree. The reason for this difference in tastes between the past and the incoming generation of the well-bred lies in the changing economic situation. A similar difference is perceptible in other respects, as well as in the accepted ideals of pleasure grounds. In this country as in most others, until the last half century but a very small proportion of the population were possessed207 of such wealth as would exempt208 them from thrift. Owing to imperfect means of communication, this small fraction were scattered209 and out of effective touch with one another. There was therefore no basis for a growth of taste in disregard of expensiveness. The revolt of the well-bred taste against vulgar thrift was unchecked. Wherever the unsophisticated sense of beauty might show itself sporadically210 in an approval of inexpensive or thrifty212 surroundings, it would lack the "social confirmation213" which nothing but a considerable body of like-minded people can give. There was, therefore, no effective upper-class opinion that would overlook evidences of possible inexpensiveness in the management of grounds; and there was consequently no appreciable divergence214 between the leisure-class and the lower middle-class ideal in the physiognomy of pleasure grounds. Both classes equally constructed their ideals with the fear of pecuniary disrepute before their eyes.
Today a divergence in ideals is beginning to be apparent. The portion of the leisure class that has been consistently exempt from work and from pecuniary cares for a generation or more is now large enough to form and sustain opinion in matters of taste. Increased mobility216 of the members has also added to the facility with which a "social confirmation" can be attained217 within the class. Within this select class the exemption218 from thrift is a matter so commonplace as to have lost much of its utility as a basis of pecuniary decency. Therefore the latter-day upper-class canons of taste do not so consistently insist on an unremitting demonstration219 of expensiveness and a strict exclusion220 of the appearance of thrift. So, a predilection for the rustic221 and the "natural" in parks and grounds makes its appearance on these higher social and intellectual levels. This predilection is in large part an outcropping of the instinct of workmanship; and it works out its results with varying degrees of consistency. It is seldom altogether unaffected, and at times it shades off into something not widely different from that make-believe of rusticity222 which has been referred to above.
A weakness for crudely serviceable contrivances that pointedly suggest immediate and wasteless use is present even in the middle-class tastes; but it is there kept well in hand under the unbroken dominance of the canon of reputable futility. Consequently it works out in a variety of ways and means for shamming223 serviceability—in such contrivances as rustic fences, bridges, bowers224, pavilions, and the like decorative features. An expression of this affectation of serviceability, at what is perhaps its widest divergence from the first promptings of the sense of economic beauty, is afforded by the cast-iron rustic fence and trellis or by a circuitous225 drive laid across level ground.
The select leisure class has outgrown226 the use of these pseudo-serviceable variants228 of pecuniary beauty, at least at some points. But the taste of the more recent accessions to the leisure class proper and of the middle and lower classes still requires a pecuniary beauty to supplement the aesthetic beauty, even in those objects which are primarily admired for the beauty that belongs to them as natural growths.
The popular taste in these matters is to be seen in the prevalent high appreciation of topiary work and of the conventional flower-beds of public grounds. Perhaps as happy an illustration as may be had of this dominance of pecuniary beauty over aesthetic beauty in middle-class tastes is seen in the reconstruction229 of the grounds lately occupied by the Columbian Exposition. The evidence goes to show that the requirement of reputable expensiveness is still present in good vigor230 even where all ostensibly lavish231 display is avoided. The artistic effects actually wrought in this work of reconstruction diverge215 somewhat widely from the effect to which the same ground would have lent itself in hands not guided by pecuniary canons of taste. And even the better class of the city's population view the progress of the work with an unreserved approval which suggests that there is in this case little if any discrepancy232 between the tastes of the upper and the lower or middle classes of the city. The sense of beauty in the population of this representative city of the advanced pecuniary culture is very chary233 of any departure from its great cultural principle of conspicuous waste.
The love of nature, perhaps itself borrowed from a higher-class code of taste, sometimes expresses itself in unexpected ways under the guidance of this canon of pecuniary beauty, and leads to results that may seem incongruous to an unreflecting beholder62. The well-accepted practice of planting trees in the treeless areas of this country, for instance, has been carried over as an item of honorific expenditure into the heavily wooded areas; so that it is by no means unusual for a village or a farmer in the wooded country to clear the land of its native trees and immediately replant saplings of certain introduced varieties about the farmyard or along the streets. In this way a forest growth of oak, elm, beech234, butternut, hemlock235, basswood, and birch is cleared off to give room for saplings of soft maple236, cottonwood, and brittle237 willow238. It is felt that the inexpensiveness of leaving the forest trees standing would derogate239 from the dignity that should invest an article which is intended to serve a decorative and honorific end.
The like pervading guidance of taste by pecuniary repute is traceable in the prevalent standards of beauty in animals. The part played by this canon of taste in assigning her place in the popular aesthetic scale to the cow has already been spokes240 of. Something to the same effect is true of the other domestic animals, so far as they are in an appreciable degree industrially useful to the community—as, for instance, barnyard fowl241, hogs242, cattle, sheep, goats, draught-horses. They are of the nature of productive goods, and serve a useful, often a lucrative end; therefore beauty is not readily imputed to them. The case is different with those domestic animals which ordinarily serve no industrial end; such as pigeons, parrots and other cage-birds, cats, dogs, and fast horses. These commonly are items of conspicuous consumption, and are therefore honorific in their nature and may legitimately be accounted beautiful. This class of animals are conventionally admired by the body of the upper classes, while the pecuniarily lower classes—and that select minority of the leisure class among whom the rigorous canon that abjures243 thrift is in a measure obsolescent—find beauty in one class of animals as in another, without drawing a hard and fast line of pecuniary demarcation between the beautiful and the ugly. In the case of those domestic animals which are honorific and are reputed beautiful, there is a subsidiary basis of merit that should be spokes of. Apart from the birds which belong in the honorific class of domestic animals, and which owe their place in this class to their non-lucrative character alone, the animals which merit particular attention are cats, dogs, and fast horses. The cat is less reputable than the other two just named, because she is less wasteful; she may even serve a useful end. At the same time the cat's temperament does not fit her for the honorific purpose. She lives with man on terms of equality, knows nothing of that relation of status which is the ancient basis of all distinctions of worth, honor, and repute, and she does not lend herself with facility to an invidious comparison between her owner and his neighbors. The exception to this last rule occurs in the case of such scarce and fanciful products as the Angora cat, which have some slight honorific value on the ground of expensiveness, and have, therefore, some special claim to beauty on pecuniary grounds.
The dog has advantages in the way of uselessness as well as in special gifts of temperament. He is often spoken of, in an eminent244 sense, as the friend of man, and his intelligence and fidelity245 are praised. The meaning of this is that the dog is man's servant and that he has the gift of an unquestioning subservience246 and a slave's quickness in guessing his master's mood. Coupled with these traits, which fit him well for the relation of status—and which must for the present purpose be set down as serviceable traits—the dog has some characteristics which are of a more equivocal aesthetic value. He is the filthiest247 of the domestic animals in his person and the nastiest in his habits. For this he makes up is a servile, fawning248 attitude towards his master, and a readiness to inflict249 damage and discomfort on all else. The dog, then, commends himself to our favor by affording play to our propensity250 for mastery, and as he is also an item of expense, and commonly serves no industrial purpose, he holds a well-assured place in men's regard as a thing of good repute. The dog is at the same time associated in our imagination with the chase—a meritorious employment and an expression of the honorable predatory impulse. Standing on this vantage ground, whatever beauty of form and motion and whatever commendable251 mental traits he may possess are conventionally acknowledged and magnified. And even those varieties of the dog which have been bred into grotesque252 deformity by the dog-fancier are in good faith accounted beautiful by many. These varieties of dogs—and the like is true of other fancy-bred animals—are rated and graded in aesthetic value somewhat in proportion to the degree of grotesqueness253 and instability of the particular fashion which the deformity takes in the given case. For the purpose in hand, this differential utility on the ground of grotesqueness and instability of structure is reducible to terms of a greater scarcity254 and consequent expense. The commercial value of canine255 monstrosities, such as the prevailing256 styles of pet dogs both for men's and women's use, rests on their high cost of production, and their value to their owners lies chiefly in their utility as items of conspicuous consumption. Indirectly, through reflection upon their honorific expensiveness, a social worth is imputed to them; and so, by an easy substitution of words and ideas, they come to be admired and reputed beautiful. Since any attention bestowed257 upon these animals is in no sense gainful or useful, it is also reputable; and since the habit of giving them attention is consequently not deprecated, it may grow into an habitual attachment258 of great tenacity259 and of a most benevolent260 character. So that in the affection bestowed on pet animals the canon of expensiveness is present more or less remotely as a norm which guides and shapes the sentiment and the selection of its object. The like is true, as will be noticed presently, with respect to affection for persons also; although the manner in which the norm acts in that case is somewhat different.
The case of the fast horse is much like that of the dog. He is on the whole expensive, or wasteful and useless—for the industrial purpose. What productive use he may possess, in the way of enhancing the well-being of the community or making the way of life easier for men, takes the form of exhibitions of force and facility of motion that gratify the popular aesthetic sense. This is of course a substantial serviceability. The horse is not endowed with the spiritual aptitude261 for servile dependence in the same measure as the dog; but he ministers effectually to his master's impulse to convert the "animate262" forces of the environment to his own use and discretion263 and so express his own dominating individuality through them. The fast horse is at least potentially a race-horse, of high or low degree; and it is as such that he is peculiarly serviceable to his owner. The utility of the fast horse lies largely in his efficiency as a means of emulation; it gratifies the owner's sense of aggression264 and dominance to have his own horse outstrip265 his neighbor's. This use being not lucrative, but on the whole pretty consistently wasteful, and quite conspicuously so, it is honorific, and therefore gives the fast horse a strong presumptive position of reputability. Beyond this, the race-horse proper has also a similarly non-industrial but honorific use as a gambling266 instrument.
The fast horse, then, is aesthetically267 fortunate, in that the canon of pecuniary good repute legitimates268 a free appreciation of whatever beauty or serviceability he may possess. His pretensions269 have the countenance270 of the principle of conspicuous waste and the backing of the predatory aptitude for dominance and emulation. The horse is, moreover, a beautiful animal, although the race-horse is so in no peculiar degree to the uninstructed taste of those persons who belong neither in the class of race-horse fanciers nor in the class whose sense of beauty is held in abeyance271 by the moral constraint272 of the horse fancier's award. To this untutored taste the most beautiful horse seems to be a form which has suffered less radical211 alteration273 than the race-horse under the breeder's selective development of the animal. Still, when a writer or speaker—especially of those whose eloquence274 is most consistently commonplace wants an illustration of animal grace and serviceability, for rhetorical use, he habitually turns to the horse; and he commonly makes it plain before he is done that what he has in mind is the race-horse.
It should be noted that in the graduated appreciation of varieties of horses and of dogs, such as one meets with among people of even moderately cultivated tastes in these matters, there is also discernible another and more direct line of influence of the leisure-class canons of reputability. In this country, for instance, leisure-class tastes are to some extent shaped on usages and habits which prevail, or which are apprehended275 to prevail, among the leisure class of Great Britain. In dogs this is true to a less extent than in horses. In horses, more particularly in saddle horses—which at their best serve the purpose of wasteful display simply—it will hold true in a general way that a horse is more beautiful in proportion as he is more English; the English leisure class being, for purposes of reputable usage, the upper leisure class of this country, and so the exemplar for the lower grades. This mimicry276 in the methods of the apperception of beauty and in the forming of judgments277 of taste need not result in a spurious, or at any rate not a hypocritical or affected182, predilection. The predilection is as serious and as substantial an award of taste when it rests on this basis as when it rests on any other, the difference is that this taste is and as substantial an award of taste when it rests on this basis as when it rests on any other; the difference is that this taste is a taste for the reputably correct, not for the aesthetically true.
The mimicry, it should be said, extends further than to the sense of beauty in horseflesh simply. It includes trappings and horsemanship as well, so that the correct or reputably beautiful seat or posture278 is also decided279 by English usage, as well as the equestrian280 gait. To show how fortuitous may sometimes be the circumstances which decide what shall be becoming and what not under the pecuniary canon of beauty, it may be noted that this English seat, and the peculiarly distressing281 gait which has made an awkward seat necessary, are a survival from the time when the English roads were so bad with mire186 and mud as to be virtually impassable for a horse travelling at a more comfortable gait; so that a person of decorous tastes in horsemanship today rides a punch with docked tail, in an uncomfortable posture and at a distressing gait, because the English roads during a great part of the last century were impassable for a horse travelling at a more horse-like gait, or for an animal built for moving with ease over the firm and open country to which the horse is indigenous283. It is not only with respect to consumable goods—including domestic animals—that the canons of taste have been colored by the canons of pecuniary reputability. Something to the like effect is to be said for beauty in persons. In order to avoid whatever may be matter of controversy284, no weight will be given in this connection to such popular predilection as there may be for the dignified (leisurely) bearing and poly presence that are by vulgar tradition associated with opulence in mature men. These traits are in some measure accepted as elements of personal beauty. But there are certain elements of feminine beauty, on the other hand, which come in under this head, and which are of so concrete and specific a character as to admit of itemized appreciation. It is more or less a rule that in communities which are at the stage of economic development at which women are valued by the upper class for their service, the ideal of female beauty is a robust285, large-limbed woman. The ground of appreciation is the physique, while the conformation of the face is of secondary weight only. A well-known instance of this ideal of the early predatory culture is that of the maidens286 of the Homeric poems.
This ideal suffers a change in the succeeding development, when, in the conventional scheme, the office of the high-class wife comes to be a vicarious leisure simply. The ideal then includes the characteristics which are supposed to result from or to go with a life of leisure consistently enforced. The ideal accepted under these circumstances may be gathered from descriptions of beautiful women by poets and writers of the chivalric287 times. In the conventional scheme of those days ladies of high degree were conceived to be in perpetual tutelage, and to be scrupulously exempt from all useful work. The resulting chivalric or romantic ideal of beauty takes cognizance chiefly of the face, and dwells on its delicacy288, and on the delicacy of the hands and feet, the slender figure, and especially the slender waist. In the pictured representations of the women of that time, and in modern romantic imitators of the chivalric thought and feeling, the waist is attenuated289 to a degree that implies extreme debility. The same ideal is still extant among a considerable portion of the population of modern industrial communities; but it is to be said that it has retained its hold most tenaciously290 in those modern communities which are least advanced in point of economic and civil development, and which show the most considerable survivals of status and of predatory institutions. That is to say, the chivalric ideal is best preserved in those existing communities which are substantially least modern. Survivals of this lackadaisical291 or romantic ideal occur freely in the tastes of the well-to-do classes of Continental292 countries. In modern communities which have reached the higher levels of industrial development, the upper leisure class has accumulated so great a mass of wealth as to place its women above all imputation of vulgarly productive labor. Here the status of women as vicarious consumers is beginning to lose its place in the sections of the body of the people; and as a consequence the ideal of feminine beauty is beginning to change back again from the infirmly delicate, translucent293, and hazardously294 slender, to a woman of the archaic295 type that does not disown her hands and feet, nor, indeed, the other gross material facts of her person. In the course of economic development the ideal of beauty among the peoples of the Western culture has shifted from the woman of physical presence to the lady, and it is beginning to shift back again to the woman; and all in obedience296 to the changing conditions of pecuniary emulation. The exigencies297 of emulation at one time required lusty slaves; at another time they required a conspicuous performance of vicarious leisure and consequently an obvious disability; but the situation is now beginning to outgrow227 this last requirement, since, under the higher efficiency of modern industry, leisure in women is possible so far down the scale of reputability that it will no longer serve as a definitive298 mark of the highest pecuniary grade.
Apart from this general control exercised by the norm of conspicuous waste over the ideal of feminine beauty, there are one or two details which merit specific mention as showing how it may exercise an extreme constraint in detail over men's sense of beauty in women. It has already been noticed that at the stages of economic evolution at which conspicuous leisure is much regarded as a means of good repute, the ideal requires delicate and diminutive299 hands and feet and a slender waist. These features, together with the other, related faults of structure that commonly go with them, go to show that the person so affected is incapable300 of useful effort and must therefore be supported in idleness by her owner. She is useless and expensive, and she is consequently valuable as evidence of pecuniary strength. It results that at this cultural stage women take thought to alter their persons, so as to conform more nearly to the requirements of the instructed taste of the time; and under the guidance of the canon of pecuniary decency, the men find the resulting artificially induced pathological features attractive. So, for instance, the constricted301 waist which has had so wide and persistent302 a vogue in the communities of the Western culture, and so also the deformed303 foot of the Chinese. Both of these are mutilations of unquestioned repulsiveness304 to the untrained sense. It requires habituation to become reconciled to them. Yet there is no room to question their attractiveness to men into whose scheme of life they fit as honorific items sanctioned by the requirements of pecuniary reputability. They are items of pecuniary and cultural beauty which have come to do duty as elements of the ideal of womanliness.
The connection here indicated between the aesthetic value and the invidious pecuniary value of things is of course not present in the consciousness of the valuer. So far as a person, in forming a judgment of taste, takes thought and reflects that the object of beauty under consideration is wasteful and reputable, and therefore may legitimately be accounted beautiful; so far the judgment is not a bona fide judgment of taste and does not come up for consideration in this connection. The connection which is here insisted on between the reputability and the apprehended beauty of objects lies through the effect which the fact of reputability has upon the valuer's habits of thought. He is in the habit of forming judgments of value of various kinds-economic, moral, aesthetic, or reputable concerning the objects with which he has to do, and his attitude of commendation towards a given object on any other ground will affect the degree of his appreciation of the object when he comes to value it for the aesthetic purpose. This is more particularly true as regards valuation on grounds so closely related to the aesthetic ground as that of reputability. The valuation for the aesthetic purpose and for the purpose of repute are not held apart as distinctly as might be. Confusion is especially apt to arise between these two kinds of valuation, because the value of objects for repute is not habitually distinguished305 in speech by the use of a special descriptive term. The result is that the terms in familiar use to designate categories or elements of beauty are applied306 to cover this unnamed element of pecuniary merit, and the corresponding confusion of ideas follows by easy consequence. The demands of reputability in this way coalesce307 in the popular apprehension with the demands of the sense of beauty, and beauty which is not accompanied by the accredited marks of good repute is not accepted. But the requirements of pecuniary reputability and those of beauty in the naive sense do not in any appreciable degree coincide. The elimination308 from our surroundings of the pecuniarily unfit, therefore, results in a more or less thorough elimination of that considerable range of elements of beauty which do not happen to conform to the pecuniary requirement. The underlying norms of taste are of very ancient growth, probably far antedating309 the advent310 of the pecuniary institutions that are here under discussion. Consequently, by force of the past selective adaptation of men's habits of thought, it happens that the requirements of beauty, simply, are for the most part best satisfied by inexpensive contrivances and structures which in a straightforward311 manner suggest both the office which they are to perform and the method of serving their end. It may be in place to recall the modern psychological position. Beauty of form seems to be a question of facility of apperception. The proposition could perhaps safely be made broader than this. If abstraction is made from association, suggestion, and "expression," classed as elements of beauty, then beauty in any perceived object means that the mind readily unfolds its apperceptive activity in the directions which the object in question affords. But the directions in which activity readily unfolds or expresses itself are the directions to which long and close habituation has made the mind prone. So far as concerns the essential elements of beauty, this habituation is an habituation so close and long as to have induced not only a proclivity312 to the apperceptive form in question, but an adaptation of physiological313 structure and function as well. So far as the economic interest enters into the constitution of beauty, it enters as a suggestion or expression of adequacy to a purpose, a manifest and readily inferable subservience to the life process. This expression of economic facility or economic serviceability in any object—what may be called the economic beauty of the object-is best served by neat and unambiguous suggestion of its office and its efficiency for the material ends of life.
On this ground, among objects of use the simple and unadorned article is aesthetically the best. But since the pecuniary canon of reputability rejects the inexpensive in articles appropriated to individual consumption, the satisfaction of our craving314 for beautiful things must be sought by way of compromise. The canons of beauty must be circumvented315 by some contrivance which will give evidence of a reputably wasteful expenditure, at the same time that it meets the demands of our critical sense of the useful and the beautiful, or at least meets the demand of some habit which has come to do duty in place of that sense. Such an auxiliary316 sense of taste is the sense of novelty; and this latter is helped out in its surrogateship by the curiosity with which men view ingenious and puzzling contrivances. Hence it comes that most objects alleged317 to be beautiful, and doing duty as such, show considerable ingenuity318 of design and are calculated to puzzle the beholder—to bewilder him with irrelevant319 suggestions and hints of the improbable—at the same time that they give evidence of an expenditure of labor in excess of what would give them their fullest efficency for their ostensible economic end.
This may be shown by an illustration taken from outside the range of our everyday habits and everyday contact, and so outside the range of our bias320. Such are the remarkable321 feather mantles322 of Hawaii, or the well-known cawed handles of the ceremonial adzes of several Polynesian islands. These are undeniably beautiful, both in the sense that they offer a pleasing composition of form, lines, and color, and in the sense that they evince great skill and ingenuity in design and construction. At the same time the articles are manifestly ill fitted to serve any other economic purpose. But it is not always that the evolution of ingenious and puzzling contrivances under the guidance of the canon of wasted effort works out so happy a result. The result is quite as often a virtually complete suppression of all elements that would bear scrutiny as expressions of beauty, or of serviceability, and the substitution of evidences of misspent ingenuity and labor, backed by a conspicuous ineptitude323; until many of the objects with which we surround ourselves in everyday life, and even many articles of everyday dress and ornament168, are such as would not be tolerated except under the stress of prescriptive tradition. Illustrations of this substitution of ingenuity and expense in place of beauty and serviceability are to be seen, for instance, in domestic architecture, in domestic art or fancy work, in various articles of apparel, especially of feminine and priestly apparel.
The canon of beauty requires expression of the generic324. The "novelty" due to the demands of conspicuous waste traverses this canon of beauty, in that it results in making the physiognomy of our objects of taste a congeries of idiosyncrasies; and the idiosyncrasies are, moreover, under the selective surveillance of the canon of expensiveness.
This process of selective adaptation of designs to the end of conspicuous waste, and the substitution of pecuniary beauty for aesthetic beauty, has been especially effective in the development of architecture. It would be extremely difficult to find a modern civilized residence or public building which can claim anything better than relative inoffensiveness in the eyes of anyone who will dissociate the elements of beauty from those of honorific waste. The endless variety of fronts presented by the better class of tenements325 and apartment houses in our cities is an endless variety of architectural distress282 and of suggestions of expensive discomfort. Considered as objects of beauty, the dead walls of the sides and back of these structures, left untouched by the hands of the artist, are commonly the best feature of the building.
What has been said of the influence of the law of conspicuous waste upon the canons of taste will hold true, with but a slight change of terms, of its influence upon our notions of the serviceability of goods for other ends than the aesthetic one. Goods are produced and consumed as a means to the fuller unfolding of human life; and their utility consists, in the first instance, in their efficiency as means to this end. The end is, in the first instance, the fullness of life of the individual, taken in absolute terms. But the human proclivity to emulation has seized upon the consumption of goods as a means to an invidious comparison, and has thereby326 invested consumable goods with a secondary utility as evidence of relative ability to pay. This indirect or secondary use of consumable goods lends an honorific character to consumption and presently also to the goods which best serve the emulative327 end of consumption. The consumption of expensive goods is meritorious, and the goods which contain an appreciable element of cost in excess of what goes to give them serviceability for their ostensible mechanical purpose are honorific. The marks of superfluous328 costliness in the goods are therefore marks of worth—of high efficency for the indirect, invidious end to be served by their consumption; and conversely, goods are humilific, and therefore unattractive, if they show too thrifty an adaptation to the mechanical end sought and do not include a margin329 of expensiveness on which to rest a complacent330 invidious comparison. This indirect utility gives much of their value to the "better" grades of goods. In order to appeal to the cultivated sense of utility, an article must contain a modicum331 of this indirect utility.
While men may have set out with disapproving332 an inexpensive manner of living because it indicated inability to spend much, and so indicated a lack of pecuniary success, they end by falling into the habit of disapproving cheap things as being intrinsically dishonorable or unworthy because they are cheap. As time has gone on, each succeeding generation has received this tradition of meritorious expenditure from the generation before it, and has in its turn further elaborated and fortified333 the traditional canon of pecuniary reputability in goods consumed; until we have finally reached such a degree of conviction as to the unworthiness of all inexpensive things, that we have no longer any misgivings335 in formulating336 the maxim337, "Cheap and nasty." So thoroughly338 has the habit of approving the expensive and disapproving the inexpensive been ingrained into our thinking that we instinctively insist upon at least some measure of wasteful expensiveness in all our consumption, even in the case of goods which are consumed in strict privacy and without the slightest thought of display. We all feel, sincerely and without misgiving334, that we are the more lifted up in spirit for having, even in the privacy of our own household, eaten our daily meal by the help of hand-wrought silver utensils, from hand-painted china (often of dubious339 artistic value) laid on high-priced table linen340. Any retrogression from the standard of living which we are accustomed to regard as worthy in this respect is felt to be a grievous violation44 of our human dignity. So, also, for the last dozen years candles have been a more pleasing source of light at dinner than any other. Candlelight is now softer, less distressing to well-bred eyes, than oil, gas, or electric light. The same could not have been said thirty years ago, when candles were, or recently had been, the cheapest available light for domestic use. Nor are candles even now found to give an acceptable or effective light for any other than a ceremonial illumination.
A political sage3 still living has summed up the conclusion of this whole matter in the dictum: "A cheap coat makes a cheap man," and there is probably no one who does not feel the convincing force of the maxim.
The habit of looking for the marks of superfluous expensiveness in goods, and of requiring that all goods should afford some utility of the indirect or invidious sort, leads to a change in the standards by which the utility of goods is gauged341. The honorific element and the element of brute efficiency are not held apart in the consumer's appreciation of commodities, and the two together go to make up the unanalyzed aggregate342 serviceability of the goods. Under the resulting standard of serviceability, no article will pass muster343 on the strength of material sufficiency alone. In order to completeness and full acceptability to the consumer it must also show the honorific element. It results that the producers of articles of consumption direct their efforts to the production of goods that shall meet this demand for the honorific element. They will do this with all the more alacrity344 and effect, since they are themselves under the dominance of the same standard of worth in goods, and would be sincerely grieved at the sight of goods which lack the proper honorific finish. Hence it has come about that there are today no goods supplied in any trade which do not contain the honorific element in greater or less degree. Any consumer who might, Diogenes-like, insist on the elimination of all honorific or wasteful elements from his consumption, would be unable to supply his most trivial wants in the modern market. Indeed, even if he resorted to supplying his wants directly by his own efforts, he would find it difficult if not impossible to divest345 himself of the current habits of thought on this head; so that he could scarcely compass a supply of the necessaries of life for a day's consumption without instinctively and by oversight346 incorporating in his home-made product something of this honorific, quasi-decorative element of wasted labor.
It is notorious that in their selection of serviceable goods in the retail347 market purchasers are guided more by the finish and workmanship of the goods than by any marks of substantial serviceability. Goods, in order to sell, must have some appreciable amount of labor spent in giving them the marks of decent expensiveness, in addition to what goes to give them efficiency for the material use which they are to serve. This habit of making obvious costliness a canon of serviceability of course acts to enhance the aggregate cost of articles of consumption. It puts us on our guard against cheapness by identifying merit in some degree with cost. There is ordinarily a consistent effort on the part of the consumer to obtain goods of the required serviceability at as advantageous348 a bargain as may be; but the conventional requirement of obvious costliness, as a voucher349 and a constituent350 of the serviceability of the goods, leads him to reject as under grade such goods as do not contain a large element of conspicuous waste.
It is to be added that a large share of those features of consumable goods which figure in popular apprehension as marks of serviceability, and to which reference is here had as elements of conspicuous waste, commend themselves to the consumer also on other grounds than that of expensiveness alone. They usually give evidence of skill and effective workmanship, even if they do not contribute to the substantial serviceability of the goods; and it is no doubt largely on some such ground that any particular mark of honorific serviceability first comes into vogue and afterward351 maintains its footing as a normal constituent element of the worth of an article. A display of efficient workmanship is pleasing simply as such, even where its remoter, for the time unconsidered, outcome is futile352. There is a gratification of the artistic sense in the contemplation of skillful work. But it is also to be added that no such evidence of skillful workmanship, or of ingenious and effective adaptation of means to an end, will, in the long run, enjoy the approbation353 of the modern civilized consumer unless it has the sanction of the Canon of conspicuous waste.
The position here taken is enforced in a felicitous354 manner by the place assigned in the economy of consumption to machine products. The point of material difference between machine-made goods and the hand-wrought goods which serve the same purposes is, ordinarily, that the former serve their primary purpose more adequately. They are a more perfect product—show a more perfect adaptation of means to end. This does not save them from disesteem and deprecation, for they fall short under the test of honorific waste. Hand labor is a more wasteful method of production; hence the goods turned out by this method are more serviceable for the purpose of pecuniary reputability; hence the marks of hand labor come to be honorific, and the goods which exhibit these marks take rank as of higher grade than the corresponding machine product. Commonly, if not invariably, the honorific marks of hand labor are certain imperfections and irregularities in the lines of the hand-wrought article, showing where the workman has fallen short in the execution of the design. The ground of the superiority of hand-wrought goods, therefore, is a certain margin of crudeness. This margin must never be so wide as to show bungling355 workmanship, since that would be evidence of low cost, nor so narrow as to suggest the ideal precision attained only by the machine, for that would be evidence of low cost.
The appreciation of those evidences of honorific crudeness to which hand-wrought goods owe their superior worth and charm in the eyes of well-bred people is a matter of nice discrimination. It requires training and the formation of right habits of thought with respect to what may be called the physiognomy of goods. Machine-made goods of daily use are often admired and preferred precisely356 on account of their excessive perfection by the vulgar and the underbred who have not given due thought to the punctilios of elegant consumption. The ceremonial inferiority of machine products goes to show that the perfection of skill and workmanship embodied357 in any costly innovations in the finish of goods is not sufficient of itself to secure them acceptance and permanent favor. The innovation must have the support of the canon of conspicuous waste. Any feature in the physiognomy of goods, however pleasing in itself, and however well it may approve itself to the taste for effective work, will not be tolerated if it proves obnoxious358 to this norm of pecuniary reputability.
The ceremonial inferiority or uncleanness in consumable goods due to "commonness," or in other words to their slight cost of production, has been taken very seriously by many persons. The objection to machine products is often formulated359 as an objection to the commonness of such goods. What is common is within the (pecuniary) reach of many people. Its consumption is therefore not honorific, since it does not serve the purpose of a favorable invidious comparison with other consumers. Hence the consumption, or even the sight of such goods, is inseparable from an odious360 suggestion of the lower levels of human life, and one comes away from their contemplation with a pervading sense of meanness that is extremely distasteful and depressing to a person of sensibility. In persons whose tastes assert themselves imperiously, and who have not the gift, habit, or incentive to discriminate361 between the grounds of their various judgments of taste, the deliverances of the sense of the honorific coalesce with those of the sense of beauty and of the sense of serviceability—in the manner already spoken of; the resulting composite valuation serves as a judgment of the object's beauty or its serviceability, according as the valuer's bias or interest inclines him to apprehend the object in the one or the other of these aspects. It follows not infrequently that the marks of cheapness or commonness are accepted as definitive marks of artistic unfitness, and a code or schedule of aesthetic proprieties on the one hand, and of aesthetic abominations on the other, is constructed on this basis for guidance in questions of taste.
As has already been pointed out, the cheap, and therefore indecorous, articles of daily consumption in modern industrial communities are commonly machine products; and the generic feature of the physiognomy of machine-made goods as compared with the hand-wrought article is their greater perfection in workmanship and greater accuracy in the detail execution of the design. Hence it comes about that the visible imperfections of the hand-wrought goods, being honorific, are accounted marks of superiority in point of beauty, or serviceability, or both. Hence has arisen that exaltation of the defective362, of which John Ruskin and William Morris were such eager spokesmen in their time; and on this ground their propaganda of crudity363 and wasted effort has been taken up and carried forward since their time. And hence also the propaganda for a return to handicraft and household industry. So much of the work and speculations364 of this group of men as fairly comes under the characterization here given would have been impossible at a time when the visibly more perfect goods were not the cheaper.
It is of course only as to the economic value of this school of aesthetic teaching that anything is intended to be said or can be said here. What is said is not to be taken in the sense of depreciation365, but chiefly as a characterization of the tendency of this teaching in its effect on consumption and on the production of consumable goods.
The manner in which the bias of this growth of taste has worked itself out in production is perhaps most cogently366 exemplified in the book manufacture with which Morris busied himself during the later years of his life; but what holds true of the work of the Kelmscott Press in an eminent degree, holds true with but slightly abated367 force when applied to latter-day artistic book-making generally—as to type, paper, illustration, binding368 materials, and binder's work. The claims to excellence369 put forward by the later products of the bookmaker's industry rest in some measure on the degree of its approximation to the crudities of the time when the work of book-making was a doubtful struggle with refractory370 materials carried on by means of insufficient371 appliances. These products, since they require hand labor, are more expensive; they are also less convenient for use than the books turned out with a view to serviceability alone; they therefore argue ability on the part of the purchaser to consume freely, as well as ability to waste time and effort. It is on this basis that the printers of today are returning to "old-style," and other more or less obsolete372 styles of type which are less legible and give a cruder appearance to the page than the "modern." Even a scientific periodical, with ostensibly no purpose but the most effective presentation of matter with which its science is concerned, will concede so much to the demands of this pecuniary beauty as to publish its scientific discussions in oldstyle type, on laid paper, and with uncut edges. But books which are not ostensibly concerned with the effective presentation of their contents alone, of course go farther in this direction. Here we have a somewhat cruder type, printed on hand-laid, deckel-edged paper, with excessive margins373 and uncut leaves, with bindings of a painstaking374 crudeness and elaborate ineptitude. The Kelmscott Press reduced the matter to an absurdity—as seen from the point of view of brute serviceability alone—by issuing books for modern use, edited with the obsolete spelling, printed in black-letter, and bound in limp vellum fitted with thongs375. As a further characteristic feature which fixes the economic place of artistic book-making, there is the fact that these more elegant books are, at their best, printed in limited editions. A limited edition is in effect a guarantee—somewhat crude, it is true—that this book is scarce and that it therefore is costly and lends pecuniary distinction to its consumer.
The special attractiveness of these book-products to the book-buyer of cultivated taste lies, of course, not in a conscious, naive recognition of their costliness and superior clumsiness. Here, as in the parallel case of the superiority of hand-wrought articles over machine products, the conscious ground of preference is an intrinsic excellence imputed to the costlier and more awkward article. The superior excellence imputed to the book which imitates the products of antique and obsolete processes is conceived to be chiefly a superior utility in the aesthetic respect; but it is not unusual to find a well-bred book-lover insisting that the clumsier product is also more serviceable as a vehicle of printed speech. So far as regards the superior aesthetic value of the decadent376 book, the chances are that the book-lover's contention377 has some ground. The book is designed with an eye single to its beauty, and the result is commonly some measure of success on the part of the designer. What is insisted on here, however, is that the canon of taste under which the designer works is a canon formed under the surveillance of the law of conspicuous waste, and that this law acts selectively to eliminate any canon of taste that does not conform to its demands. That is to say, while the decadent book may be beautiful, the limits within which the designer may work are fixed378 by requirements of a non-aesthetic kind. The product, if it is beautiful, must also at the same time be costly and ill adapted to its ostensible use. This mandatory379 canon of taste in the case of the book-designer, however, is not shaped entirely380 by the law of waste in its first form; the canon is to some extent shaped in conformity381 to that secondary expression of the predatory temperament, veneration382 for the archaic or obsolete, which in one of its special developments is called classicism. In aesthetic theory it might be extremely difficult, if not quite impracticable, to draw a line between the canon of classicism, or regard for the archaic, and the canon of beauty. For the aesthetic purpose such a distinction need scarcely be drawn383, and indeed it need not exist. For a theory of taste the expression of an accepted ideal of archaism, on whatever basis it may have been accepted, is perhaps best rated as an element of beauty; there need be no question of its legitimation384. But for the present purpose—for the purpose of determining what economic grounds are present in the accepted canons of taste and what is their significance for the distribution and consumption of goods—the distinction is not similarly beside the point. The position of machine products in the civilized scheme of consumption serves to point out the nature of the relation which subsists385 between the canon of conspicuous waste and the code of proprieties in consumption. Neither in matters of art and taste proper, nor as regards the current sense of the serviceability of goods, does this canon act as a principle of innovation or initiative. It does not go into the future as a creative principle which makes innovations and adds new items of consumption and new elements of cost. The principle in question is, in a certain sense, a negative rather than a positive law. It is a regulative rather than a creative principle. It very rarely initiates386 or originates any usage or custom directly. Its action is selective only. Conspicuous wastefulness does not directly afford ground for variation and growth, but conformity to its requirements is a condition to the survival of such innovations as may be made on other grounds. In whatever way usages and customs and methods of expenditure arise, they are all subject to the selective action of this norm of reputability; and the degree in which they conform to its requirements is a test of their fitness to survive in the competition with other similar usages and customs. Other thing being equal, the more obviously wasteful usage or method stands the better chance of survival under this law. The law of conspicuous waste does not account for the origin of variations, but only for the persistence387 of such forms as are fit to survive under its dominance. It acts to conserve388 the fit, not to originate the acceptable. Its office is to prove all things and to hold fast that which is good for its purpose.
点击收听单词发音
1 conspicuous | |
adj.明眼的,惹人注目的;炫耀的,摆阔气的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 sage | |
n.圣人,哲人;adj.贤明的,明智的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 decency | |
n.体面,得体,合宜,正派,庄重 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 constraining | |
强迫( constrain的现在分词 ); 强使; 限制; 约束 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 appreciable | |
adj.明显的,可见的,可估量的,可觉察的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 utensils | |
器具,用具,器皿( utensil的名词复数 ); 器物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 apparatus | |
n.装置,器械;器具,设备 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 scrutiny | |
n.详细检查,仔细观察 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 pro | |
n.赞成,赞成的意见,赞成者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 accredited | |
adj.可接受的;可信任的;公认的;质量合格的v.相信( accredit的过去式和过去分词 );委托;委任;把…归结于 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 wasteful | |
adj.(造成)浪费的,挥霍的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 wastefulness | |
浪费,挥霍,耗费 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 habitual | |
adj.习惯性的;通常的,惯常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 isolated | |
adj.与世隔绝的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 pecuniary | |
adj.金钱的;金钱上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 expenditure | |
n.(时间、劳力、金钱等)支出;使用,消耗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 habitually | |
ad.习惯地,通常地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 admonish | |
v.训戒;警告;劝告 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 dominant | |
adj.支配的,统治的;占优势的;显性的;n.主因,要素,主要的人(或物);显性基因 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 insistence | |
n.坚持;强调;坚决主张 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 assent | |
v.批准,认可;n.批准,认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 inviolate | |
adj.未亵渎的,未受侵犯的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 offenses | |
n.进攻( offense的名词复数 );(球队的)前锋;进攻方法;攻势 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 offense | |
n.犯规,违法行为;冒犯,得罪 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 offender | |
n.冒犯者,违反者,犯罪者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 incur | |
vt.招致,蒙受,遭遇 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 obloquy | |
n.斥责,大骂 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 naive | |
adj.幼稚的,轻信的;天真的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 accrues | |
v.增加( accrue的第三人称单数 );(通过自然增长)产生;获得;(使钱款、债务)积累 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 cult | |
n.异教,邪教;时尚,狂热的崇拜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 proprieties | |
n.礼仪,礼节;礼貌( propriety的名词复数 );规矩;正当;合适 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 mitigate | |
vt.(使)减轻,(使)缓和 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 turpitude | |
n.可耻;邪恶 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 noted | |
adj.著名的,知名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 condone | |
v.宽恕;原谅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 worthy | |
adj.(of)值得的,配得上的;有价值的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 nurtured | |
养育( nurture的过去式和过去分词 ); 培育; 滋长; 助长 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 extenuating | |
adj.使减轻的,情有可原的v.(用偏袒的辩解或借口)减轻( extenuate的现在分词 );低估,藐视 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 prone | |
adj.(to)易于…的,很可能…的;俯卧的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 violations | |
违反( violation的名词复数 ); 冒犯; 违反(行为、事例); 强奸 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 violation | |
n.违反(行为),违背(行为),侵犯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 peculiar | |
adj.古怪的,异常的;特殊的,特有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 precipitate | |
adj.突如其来的;vt.使突然发生;n.沉淀物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 meritorious | |
adj.值得赞赏的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 meritoriousness | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 devout | |
adj.虔诚的,虔敬的,衷心的 (n.devoutness) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 conceits | |
高傲( conceit的名词复数 ); 自以为; 巧妙的词语; 别出心裁的比喻 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 pointed | |
adj.尖的,直截了当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 edifices | |
n.大建筑物( edifice的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 cults | |
n.迷信( cult的名词复数 );狂热的崇拜;(有极端宗教信仰的)异教团体 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 impute | |
v.归咎于 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 imputed | |
v.把(错误等)归咎于( impute的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 predilection | |
n.偏好 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 splendor | |
n.光彩;壮丽,华丽;显赫,辉煌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 mellowing | |
软化,醇化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 abject | |
adj.极可怜的,卑屈的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 shamefulness | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 indigence | |
n.贫穷 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 beholder | |
n.观看者,旁观者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 pecuniarily | |
adv.在金钱上,在金钱方面 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 imperative | |
n.命令,需要;规则;祈使语气;adj.强制的;紧急的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 latitude | |
n.纬度,行动或言论的自由(范围),(pl.)地区 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 aesthetic | |
adj.美学的,审美的,有美感 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 dwelling | |
n.住宅,住所,寓所 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 dwellings | |
n.住处,处所( dwelling的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 sanctuary | |
n.圣所,圣堂,寺庙;禁猎区,保护区 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 conspicuously | |
ad.明显地,惹人注目地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 denominations | |
n.宗派( denomination的名词复数 );教派;面额;名称 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 Christian | |
adj.基督教徒的;n.基督教徒 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 well-being | |
n.安康,安乐,幸福 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 scrupulously | |
adv.一丝不苟地;小心翼翼地,多顾虑地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 ostensible | |
adj.(指理由)表面的,假装的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 mortifying | |
adj.抑制的,苦修的v.使受辱( mortify的现在分词 );伤害(人的感情);克制;抑制(肉体、情感等) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 austere | |
adj.艰苦的;朴素的,朴实无华的;严峻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 austerely | |
adv.严格地,朴质地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 discomfort | |
n.不舒服,不安,难过,困难,不方便 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 pertains | |
关于( pertain的第三人称单数 ); 有关; 存在; 适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 luxurious | |
adj.精美而昂贵的;豪华的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 paraphernalia | |
n.装备;随身用品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 destined | |
adj.命中注定的;(for)以…为目的地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 contrived | |
adj.不自然的,做作的;虚构的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 inconvenient | |
adj.不方便的,令人感到麻烦的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 consort | |
v.相伴;结交 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 domain | |
n.(活动等)领域,范围;领地,势力范围 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 demeanor | |
n.行为;风度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 aloof | |
adj.远离的;冷淡的,漠不关心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 leisurely | |
adj.悠闲的;从容的,慢慢的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 sensuous | |
adj.激发美感的;感官的,感觉上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 pervading | |
v.遍及,弥漫( pervade的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 exterior | |
adj.外部的,外在的;表面的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 rehearsal | |
n.排练,排演;练习 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 garb | |
n.服装,装束 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 sects | |
n.宗派,教派( sect的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 sanctuaries | |
n.避难所( sanctuary的名词复数 );庇护;圣所;庇护所 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 exacting | |
adj.苛求的,要求严格的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 consistency | |
n.一贯性,前后一致,稳定性;(液体的)浓度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 pointedly | |
adv.尖地,明显地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 exalted | |
adj.(地位等)高的,崇高的;尊贵的,高尚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 agility | |
n.敏捷,活泼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 dexterous | |
adj.灵敏的;灵巧的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 temperament | |
n.气质,性格,性情 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 propensities | |
n.倾向,习性( propensity的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 suffusion | |
n.充满 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 eke | |
v.勉强度日,节约使用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 scant | |
adj.不充分的,不足的;v.减缩,限制,忽略 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 authentic | |
a.真的,真正的;可靠的,可信的,有根据的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 apprehension | |
n.理解,领悟;逮捕,拘捕;忧虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 consonant | |
n.辅音;adj.[音]符合的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 dignified | |
a.可敬的,高贵的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 intercourse | |
n.性交;交流,交往,交际 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 underlying | |
adj.在下面的,含蓄的,潜在的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 emulation | |
n.竞争;仿效 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 standing | |
n.持续,地位;adj.永久的,不动的,直立的,不流动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 condemning | |
v.(通常因道义上的原因而)谴责( condemn的现在分词 );宣判;宣布…不能使用;迫使…陷于不幸的境地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 indirectly | |
adv.间接地,不直接了当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 serene | |
adj. 安详的,宁静的,平静的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 poetic | |
adj.富有诗意的,有诗人气质的,善于抒情的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 auditors | |
n.审计员,稽核员( auditor的名词复数 );(大学课程的)旁听生 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 profusion | |
n.挥霍;丰富 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 opulence | |
n.财富,富裕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 celestial | |
adj.天体的;天上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 abodes | |
住所( abode的名词复数 ); 公寓; (在某地的)暂住; 逗留 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 corps | |
n.(通信等兵种的)部队;(同类作的)一组 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 shimmer | |
v./n.发微光,发闪光;微光 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 crasser | |
adj.愚笨的,粗鲁的,全然不顾他人的( crass的比较级 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 descend | |
vt./vi.传下来,下来,下降 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 unbearable | |
adj.不能容忍的;忍受不住的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 tangible | |
adj.有形的,可触摸的,确凿的,实际的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 cleansed | |
弄干净,清洗( cleanse的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 profane | |
adj.亵神的,亵渎的;vt.亵渎,玷污 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 judgment | |
n.审判;判断力,识别力,看法,意见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 homely | |
adj.家常的,简朴的;不漂亮的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 dependence | |
n.依靠,依赖;信任,信赖;隶属 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 wrought | |
v.引起;以…原料制作;运转;adj.制造的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 aluminum | |
n.(aluminium)铝 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 costlier | |
adj.昂贵的( costly的比较级 );代价高的;引起困难的;造成损失的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 machinery | |
n.(总称)机械,机器;机构 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141 brute | |
n.野兽,兽性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142 rejection | |
n.拒绝,被拒,抛弃,被弃 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143 plausible | |
adj.似真实的,似乎有理的,似乎可信的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144 conclusive | |
adj.最后的,结论的;确凿的,消除怀疑的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145 inspection | |
n.检查,审查,检阅 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146 citation | |
n.引用,引证,引用文;传票 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147 derives | |
v.得到( derive的第三人称单数 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148 lighter | |
n.打火机,点火器;驳船;v.用驳船运送;light的比较级 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149 appreciably | |
adv.相当大地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150 contemplating | |
深思,细想,仔细考虑( contemplate的现在分词 ); 注视,凝视; 考虑接受(发生某事的可能性); 深思熟虑,沉思,苦思冥想 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151 procured | |
v.(努力)取得, (设法)获得( procure的过去式和过去分词 );拉皮条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
152 nominal | |
adj.名义上的;(金额、租金)微不足道的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
153 derived | |
vi.起源;由来;衍生;导出v.得到( derive的过去式和过去分词 );(从…中)得到获得;源于;(从…中)提取 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
154 costly | |
adj.昂贵的,价值高的,豪华的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
155 costliness | |
昂贵的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
156 appreciation | |
n.评价;欣赏;感谢;领会,理解;价格上涨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
157 legitimately | |
ad.合法地;正当地,合理地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
158 labor | |
n.劳动,努力,工作,劳工;分娩;vi.劳动,努力,苦干;vt.详细分析;麻烦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
159 adornment | |
n.装饰;装饰品 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
160 coveted | |
adj.令人垂涎的;垂涎的,梦寐以求的v.贪求,觊觎(covet的过去分词);垂涎;贪图 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
161 monopolized | |
v.垄断( monopolize的过去式和过去分词 );独占;专卖;专营 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
162 wards | |
区( ward的名词复数 ); 病房; 受监护的未成年者; 被人照顾或控制的状态 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
163 enjoyment | |
n.乐趣;享有;享用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
164 monopolization | |
n.独占,专卖,垄断 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
165 gems | |
growth; economy; management; and customer satisfaction 增长 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
166 relatively | |
adv.比较...地,相对地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
167 incentive | |
n.刺激;动力;鼓励;诱因;动机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
168 ornament | |
v.装饰,美化;n.装饰,装饰物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
169 ornaments | |
n.装饰( ornament的名词复数 );点缀;装饰品;首饰v.装饰,点缀,美化( ornament的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
170 generalization | |
n.普遍性,一般性,概括 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
171 perfectly | |
adv.完美地,无可非议地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
172 attire | |
v.穿衣,装扮[同]array;n.衣着;盛装 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
173 sincerity | |
n.真诚,诚意;真实 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
174 Vogue | |
n.时髦,时尚;adj.流行的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
175 gloss | |
n.光泽,光滑;虚饰;注释;vt.加光泽于;掩饰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
176 glossy | |
adj.平滑的;有光泽的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
177 bonnet | |
n.无边女帽;童帽 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
178 apprehend | |
vt.理解,领悟,逮捕,拘捕,忧虑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
179 juxtaposition | |
n.毗邻,并置,并列 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
180 civilized | |
a.有教养的,文雅的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
181 instinctively | |
adv.本能地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
182 affected | |
adj.不自然的,假装的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
183 cleave | |
v.(clave;cleaved)粘着,粘住;坚持;依恋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
184 eschew | |
v.避开,戒绝 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
185 appreciative | |
adj.有鉴赏力的,有眼力的;感激的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
186 mire | |
n.泥沼,泥泞;v.使...陷于泥泞,使...陷入困境 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
187 admiration | |
n.钦佩,赞美,羡慕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
188 specifies | |
v.指定( specify的第三人称单数 );详述;提出…的条件;使具有特性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
189 propriety | |
n.正当行为;正当;适当 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
190 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
191 rigidly | |
adv.刻板地,僵化地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
192 ethnic | |
adj.人种的,种族的,异教徒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
193 bent | |
n.爱好,癖好;adj.弯的;决心的,一心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
194 imputation | |
n.归罪,责难 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
195 thrift | |
adj.节约,节俭;n.节俭,节约 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
196 rehabilitated | |
改造(罪犯等)( rehabilitate的过去式和过去分词 ); 使恢复正常生活; 使恢复原状; 修复 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
197 decorative | |
adj.装饰的,可作装饰的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
198 negate | |
vt.否定,否认;取消,使无效 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
199 inadequate | |
adj.(for,to)不充足的,不适当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
200 antelopes | |
羚羊( antelope的名词复数 ); 羚羊皮革 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
201 futility | |
n.无用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
202 lucrative | |
adj.赚钱的,可获利的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
203 supervision | |
n.监督,管理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
204 artistic | |
adj.艺术(家)的,美术(家)的;善于艺术创作的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
205 herd | |
n.兽群,牧群;vt.使集中,把…赶在一起 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
206 simplicity | |
n.简单,简易;朴素;直率,单纯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
207 possessed | |
adj.疯狂的;拥有的,占有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
208 exempt | |
adj.免除的;v.使免除;n.免税者,被免除义务者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
209 scattered | |
adj.分散的,稀疏的;散步的;疏疏落落的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
210 sporadically | |
adv.偶发地,零星地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
211 radical | |
n.激进份子,原子团,根号;adj.根本的,激进的,彻底的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
212 thrifty | |
adj.节俭的;兴旺的;健壮的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
213 confirmation | |
n.证实,确认,批准 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
214 divergence | |
n.分歧,岔开 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
215 diverge | |
v.分叉,分歧,离题,使...岔开,使转向 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
216 mobility | |
n.可动性,变动性,情感不定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
217 attained | |
(通常经过努力)实现( attain的过去式和过去分词 ); 达到; 获得; 达到(某年龄、水平、状况) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
218 exemption | |
n.豁免,免税额,免除 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
219 demonstration | |
n.表明,示范,论证,示威 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
220 exclusion | |
n.拒绝,排除,排斥,远足,远途旅行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
221 rustic | |
adj.乡村的,有乡村特色的;n.乡下人,乡巴佬 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
222 rusticity | |
n.乡村的特点、风格或气息 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
223 shamming | |
假装,冒充( sham的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
224 bowers | |
n.(女子的)卧室( bower的名词复数 );船首锚;阴凉处;鞠躬的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
225 circuitous | |
adj.迂回的路的,迂曲的,绕行的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
226 outgrown | |
长[发展] 得超过(某物)的范围( outgrow的过去分词 ); 长[发展]得不能再要(某物); 长得比…快; 生长速度超过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
227 outgrow | |
vt.长大得使…不再适用;成长得不再要 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
228 variants | |
n.变体( variant的名词复数 );变种;变型;(词等的)变体 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
229 reconstruction | |
n.重建,再现,复原 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
230 vigor | |
n.活力,精力,元气 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
231 lavish | |
adj.无节制的;浪费的;vt.慷慨地给予,挥霍 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
232 discrepancy | |
n.不同;不符;差异;矛盾 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
233 chary | |
adj.谨慎的,细心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
234 beech | |
n.山毛榉;adj.山毛榉的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
235 hemlock | |
n.毒胡萝卜,铁杉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
236 maple | |
n.槭树,枫树,槭木 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
237 brittle | |
adj.易碎的;脆弱的;冷淡的;(声音)尖利的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
238 willow | |
n.柳树 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
239 derogate | |
v.贬低,诽谤 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
240 spokes | |
n.(车轮的)辐条( spoke的名词复数 );轮辐;破坏某人的计划;阻挠某人的行动 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
241 fowl | |
n.家禽,鸡,禽肉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
242 hogs | |
n.(尤指喂肥供食用的)猪( hog的名词复数 );(供食用的)阉公猪;彻底地做某事;自私的或贪婪的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
243 abjures | |
v.发誓放弃( abjure的第三人称单数 );郑重放弃(意见);宣布撤回(声明等);避免 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
244 eminent | |
adj.显赫的,杰出的,有名的,优良的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
245 fidelity | |
n.忠诚,忠实;精确 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
246 subservience | |
n.有利,有益;从属(地位),附属性;屈从,恭顺;媚态 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
247 filthiest | |
filthy(肮脏的,污秽的)的最高级形式 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
248 fawning | |
adj.乞怜的,奉承的v.(尤指狗等)跳过来往人身上蹭以示亲热( fawn的现在分词 );巴结;讨好 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
249 inflict | |
vt.(on)把…强加给,使遭受,使承担 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
250 propensity | |
n.倾向;习性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
251 commendable | |
adj.值得称赞的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
252 grotesque | |
adj.怪诞的,丑陋的;n.怪诞的图案,怪人(物) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
253 grotesqueness | |
参考例句: |
|
|
254 scarcity | |
n.缺乏,不足,萧条 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
255 canine | |
adj.犬的,犬科的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
256 prevailing | |
adj.盛行的;占优势的;主要的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
257 bestowed | |
赠给,授予( bestow的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
258 attachment | |
n.附属物,附件;依恋;依附 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
259 tenacity | |
n.坚韧 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
260 benevolent | |
adj.仁慈的,乐善好施的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
261 aptitude | |
n.(学习方面的)才能,资质,天资 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
262 animate | |
v.赋于生命,鼓励;adj.有生命的,有生气的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
263 discretion | |
n.谨慎;随意处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
264 aggression | |
n.进攻,侵略,侵犯,侵害 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
265 outstrip | |
v.超过,跑过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
266 gambling | |
n.赌博;投机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
267 aesthetically | |
adv.美地,艺术地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
268 legitimates | |
v.合情合理的( legitimate的第三人称单数 );合法的;法律认可的;法定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
269 pretensions | |
自称( pretension的名词复数 ); 自命不凡; 要求; 权力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
270 countenance | |
n.脸色,面容;面部表情;vt.支持,赞同 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
271 abeyance | |
n.搁置,缓办,中止,产权未定 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
272 constraint | |
n.(on)约束,限制;限制(或约束)性的事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
273 alteration | |
n.变更,改变;蚀变 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
274 eloquence | |
n.雄辩;口才,修辞 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
275 apprehended | |
逮捕,拘押( apprehend的过去式和过去分词 ); 理解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
276 mimicry | |
n.(生物)拟态,模仿 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
277 judgments | |
判断( judgment的名词复数 ); 鉴定; 评价; 审判 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
278 posture | |
n.姿势,姿态,心态,态度;v.作出某种姿势 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
279 decided | |
adj.决定了的,坚决的;明显的,明确的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
280 equestrian | |
adj.骑马的;n.马术 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
281 distressing | |
a.使人痛苦的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
282 distress | |
n.苦恼,痛苦,不舒适;不幸;vt.使悲痛 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
283 indigenous | |
adj.土产的,土生土长的,本地的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
284 controversy | |
n.争论,辩论,争吵 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
285 robust | |
adj.强壮的,强健的,粗野的,需要体力的,浓的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
286 maidens | |
处女( maiden的名词复数 ); 少女; 未婚女子; (板球运动)未得分的一轮投球 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
287 chivalric | |
有武士气概的,有武士风范的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
288 delicacy | |
n.精致,细微,微妙,精良;美味,佳肴 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
289 attenuated | |
v.(使)变细( attenuate的过去式和过去分词 );(使)变薄;(使)变小;减弱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
290 tenaciously | |
坚持地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
291 lackadaisical | |
adj.无精打采的,无兴趣的;adv.无精打采地,不决断地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
292 continental | |
adj.大陆的,大陆性的,欧洲大陆的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
293 translucent | |
adj.半透明的;透明的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
294 hazardously | |
adv.冒险地,有危险地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
295 archaic | |
adj.(语言、词汇等)古代的,已不通用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
296 obedience | |
n.服从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
297 exigencies | |
n.急切需要 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
298 definitive | |
adj.确切的,权威性的;最后的,决定性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
299 diminutive | |
adj.小巧可爱的,小的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
300 incapable | |
adj.无能力的,不能做某事的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
301 constricted | |
adj.抑制的,约束的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
302 persistent | |
adj.坚持不懈的,执意的;持续的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
303 deformed | |
adj.畸形的;变形的;丑的,破相了的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
304 repulsiveness | |
参考例句: |
|
|
305 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
306 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
307 coalesce | |
v.联合,结合,合并 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
308 elimination | |
n.排除,消除,消灭 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
309 antedating | |
v.(在历史上)比…为早( antedate的现在分词 );先于;早于;(在信、支票等上)填写比实际日期早的日期 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
310 advent | |
n.(重要事件等的)到来,来临 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
311 straightforward | |
adj.正直的,坦率的;易懂的,简单的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
312 proclivity | |
n.倾向,癖性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
313 physiological | |
adj.生理学的,生理学上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
314 craving | |
n.渴望,热望 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
315 circumvented | |
v.设法克服或避免(某事物),回避( circumvent的过去式和过去分词 );绕过,绕行,绕道旅行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
316 auxiliary | |
adj.辅助的,备用的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
317 alleged | |
a.被指控的,嫌疑的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
318 ingenuity | |
n.别出心裁;善于发明创造 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
319 irrelevant | |
adj.不恰当的,无关系的,不相干的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
320 bias | |
n.偏见,偏心,偏袒;vt.使有偏见 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
321 remarkable | |
adj.显著的,异常的,非凡的,值得注意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
322 mantles | |
vt.&vi.覆盖(mantle的第三人称单数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
323 ineptitude | |
n.不适当;愚笨,愚昧的言行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
324 generic | |
adj.一般的,普通的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
325 tenements | |
n.房屋,住户,租房子( tenement的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
326 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
327 emulative | |
adj.好胜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
328 superfluous | |
adj.过多的,过剩的,多余的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
329 margin | |
n.页边空白;差额;余地,余裕;边,边缘 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
330 complacent | |
adj.自满的;自鸣得意的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
331 modicum | |
n.少量,一小份 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
332 disapproving | |
adj.不满的,反对的v.不赞成( disapprove的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
333 fortified | |
adj. 加强的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
334 misgiving | |
n.疑虑,担忧,害怕 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
335 misgivings | |
n.疑虑,担忧,害怕;疑虑,担心,恐惧( misgiving的名词复数 );疑惧 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
336 formulating | |
v.构想出( formulate的现在分词 );规划;确切地阐述;用公式表示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
337 maxim | |
n.格言,箴言 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
338 thoroughly | |
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
339 dubious | |
adj.怀疑的,无把握的;有问题的,靠不住的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
340 linen | |
n.亚麻布,亚麻线,亚麻制品;adj.亚麻布制的,亚麻的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
341 gauged | |
adj.校准的;标准的;量规的;量计的v.(用仪器)测量( gauge的过去式和过去分词 );估计;计量;划分 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
342 aggregate | |
adj.总计的,集合的;n.总数;v.合计;集合 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
343 muster | |
v.集合,收集,鼓起,激起;n.集合,检阅,集合人员,点名册 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
344 alacrity | |
n.敏捷,轻快,乐意 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
345 divest | |
v.脱去,剥除 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
346 oversight | |
n.勘漏,失察,疏忽 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
347 retail | |
v./n.零售;adv.以零售价格 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
348 advantageous | |
adj.有利的;有帮助的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
349 voucher | |
n.收据;传票;凭单,凭证 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
350 constituent | |
n.选民;成分,组分;adj.组成的,构成的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
351 afterward | |
adv.后来;以后 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
352 futile | |
adj.无效的,无用的,无希望的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
353 approbation | |
n.称赞;认可 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
354 felicitous | |
adj.恰当的,巧妙的;n.恰当,贴切 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
355 bungling | |
adj.笨拙的,粗劣的v.搞糟,完不成( bungle的现在分词 );笨手笨脚地做;失败;完不成 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
356 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
357 embodied | |
v.表现( embody的过去式和过去分词 );象征;包括;包含 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
358 obnoxious | |
adj.极恼人的,讨人厌的,可憎的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
359 formulated | |
v.构想出( formulate的过去式和过去分词 );规划;确切地阐述;用公式表示 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
360 odious | |
adj.可憎的,讨厌的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
361 discriminate | |
v.区别,辨别,区分;有区别地对待 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
362 defective | |
adj.有毛病的,有问题的,有瑕疵的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
363 crudity | |
n.粗糙,生硬;adj.粗略的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
364 speculations | |
n.投机买卖( speculation的名词复数 );思考;投机活动;推断 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
365 depreciation | |
n.价值低落,贬值,蔑视,贬低 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
366 cogently | |
adv.痛切地,中肯地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
367 abated | |
减少( abate的过去式和过去分词 ); 减去; 降价; 撤消(诉讼) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
368 binding | |
有约束力的,有效的,应遵守的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
369 excellence | |
n.优秀,杰出,(pl.)优点,美德 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
370 refractory | |
adj.倔强的,难驾驭的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
371 insufficient | |
adj.(for,of)不足的,不够的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
372 obsolete | |
adj.已废弃的,过时的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
373 margins | |
边( margin的名词复数 ); 利润; 页边空白; 差数 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
374 painstaking | |
adj.苦干的;艰苦的,费力的,刻苦的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
375 thongs | |
的东西 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
376 decadent | |
adj.颓废的,衰落的,堕落的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
377 contention | |
n.争论,争辩,论战;论点,主张 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
378 fixed | |
adj.固定的,不变的,准备好的;(计算机)固定的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
379 mandatory | |
adj.命令的;强制的;义务的;n.受托者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
380 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
381 conformity | |
n.一致,遵从,顺从 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
382 veneration | |
n.尊敬,崇拜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
383 drawn | |
v.拖,拉,拔出;adj.憔悴的,紧张的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
384 legitimation | |
n. 合法, 合法化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
385 subsists | |
v.(靠很少的钱或食物)维持生活,生存下去( subsist的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
386 initiates | |
v.开始( initiate的第三人称单数 );传授;发起;接纳新成员 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
387 persistence | |
n.坚持,持续,存留 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
388 conserve | |
vt.保存,保护,节约,节省,守恒,不灭 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |