When a crime is committed in some place, attracting public attention either through the atrocity1 of the case or the strangeness of the criminal deed—for instance, one that is not connected with bloodshed, but with intellectual fraud—there are at once two tendencies that make themselves felt in the public conscience. One of them, pervading2 the overwhelming majority of individual consciences, asks: How is this? What for? Why did that man commit such a crime? This question is asked by everybody and occupies mostly the attention of those who do not look upon the case from the point of view of criminology. On the other hand, those who occupy themselves with criminal law represent the other tendency, which manifests itself when acquainted with the news of this crime. This is a limited portion of the public conscience, which tries to study the problem from the standpoint of the technical jurist. The lawyers, the judges, the officials of the police, ask themselves: What is the name of the crime committed by that man under such circumstances? Must it be classed us murder or patricide3, attempted or incompleted manslaughter, and, if directed against property, is it theft, or illegal appropriation4, or fraud? And the entire apparatus5 of practical criminal justice forgets at once the first problem, which occupies the majority of the public conscience, the question of the causes that led to this crime, in order to devote itself exclusively to the technical side of the problem which constitutes the juridical anatomy6 of the inhuman7 and antisocial deed perpetrated by the criminal.
In these two tendencies you have a photographic reproduction of the two schools of criminology. The classic school, which looks upon the crime as a juridical problem, occupies itself with its name, its definition, its juridical analysis, leaves the personality of the criminal in the background and remembers it only so far as exceptional circumstances explicitly8 stated in the law books refer to it: whether he is a minor9, a deaf-mute, whether it is a case of insanity10, whether he was drunk at the time the crime was committed. Only in these strictly11 defined cases does the classic school occupy itself theoretically with the personality of the criminal. But ninety times in one hundred these exceptional circumstances do not exist or cannot be shown to exist, and penal12 justice limits itself to the technical definition of the fact. But when the case comes up in the criminal court, or before the jurors, practice demonstrates that there is seldom a discussion between the lawyers of the defense13 and the judges for the purpose of ascertaining14 the most exact definition of the fact, of determining whether it is a case of attempted or merely projected crime, of finding out whether there are any of the juridical elements defined in this or that article of the code. The judge is rather face to face with the problem of ascertaining why, under what conditions, for what reasons, the man has committed the crime. This is the supreme16 and simple human problem. But hitherto it has been left to a more or less perspicacious17, more or less gifted, empiricism, and there have been no scientific standards, no methodical collection of facts, no observations and conclusions, save those of the positive school of criminology. This school alone makes an attempt to solve in every case of crime the problem of its natural origin, of the reasons and conditions that induced a man to commit such and such a crime.
For instance, about 3,000 cases of manslaughter are registered every year in Italy. Now, open any work inspired by the classic school of criminology, and ask the author why 3,000 men are the victims of manslaughter every year in Italy, and how it is that there are not sometimes only as many as, say, 300 cases, the number committed in England, which has nearly the same number of inhabitants as Italy; and how it is that there are not sometimes 300,000 such cases in Italy instead of 3,000?
It is useless to open any work of classical criminology for this purpose, for you will not find an answer to these questions in than. No one, from Beccaria to Carrara, has ever thought of this problem, and they could not have asked it, considering their point of departure and their method. In fact, the classic criminologists accept the phenomenon of criminality as an accomplished18 fact. They analyze19 it from the point of view of the technical jurist, without asking how this criminal fact may have been produced, and why it repeats itself in greater or smaller numbers from year to year, in every country. The theory of a free will, which is their foundation, excludes the possibility of this scientific question, for according to it the crime is the product of the fiat20 of the human will. And if that is admitted as a fact, there is nothing left to account for. The manslaughter was committed, because the criminal wanted to commit it; and that is all there is to it. Once the theory of a free will is accepted as a fact, the deed depends on the fiat, the voluntary determination, of the criminal, and all is said.
But if, on the other hand, the positive school of criminology denies, on the ground of researches in scientific physiological21 psychology22, that the human will is free and does not admit that one is a criminal because he wants to be, but declares that a man commits this or that crime only when he lives in definitely determined23 conditions of personality and environment which induce him necessarily to act in a certain way, then alone does the problem of the origin of criminality begin to be submitted to a preliminary analysis, and then alone does criminal law step out of the narrow and arid24 limits of technical jurisprudence and become a true social and human science in the highest and noblest meaning of the word. It is vain to insist with such stubbornness as that of the classic school of criminology on juristic formulas by which the distinction between illegal appropriation and theft, between fraud and other forms of crime against property, and so forth25, is determined, when this method does not give to society one single word which would throw light upon the reasons that make a man a criminal and upon the efficacious remedy by which society could protect itself against criminality.
It is true that the classic school of criminology has likewise its remedy against crime—namely, punishment. But this is the only remedy of that school, and in all the legislation inspired by the theories of that school in all the countries of the civilized26 world there is no other remedy against crime but repression27.
But Bentham has said: Every time that punishment is inflicted28 it proves its inefficacy, for it did not prevent the committal of that crime. Therefore, this remedy is worthless. And a deeper study of the cause of crime demonstrates that if a man does not commit a certain crime, this is due to entirely29 different reasons, than a fear of the penalty, very strong and fundamental reasons which are not to be found in the threats of legislators. These threats, if nevertheless carried out by police and prison keepers, run counter to those conditions. A man who intends to commit a crime, or who is carried away by a violent passion, by a psychological hurricane which drowns his moral sense, is not checked by threats of punishment, because the volcanic30 eruption31 of passion prevents him from reflecting. Or he may decide to commit a crime after due premeditation and preparation, and in that case the penalty is powerless to check him, because he hopes to escape with impunity32. All criminals will tell you unanimously that the only thing which impelled33 them when they were deliberating a crime was the expectation that they would go scot free. If they had but the least suspicion that they might be detected and punished they would not have committed the crime. The only exception is the case in which a crime is the result of a mental explosion caused by a violent outburst of passion. And if you wish to have a very convincing illustration of the psychological inefficacy of legal threats, you have but to think of that curious crime which has now assumed a frequency never known to former centuries, namely the making of counterfeit34 money. For since paper money—from want or for reasons of expediency—has become a substitute of metal coin in the civilized countries, the making of counterfeit paper money has become very frequent in the nineteenth century. Now a counterfeiter35, in committing his crime, must compel his mind to imitate closely the inscription36 of the bill, letter for letter, including that threatening passage, which says: "The law punishes counterfeiting37 ..." etc. Can you see before your mind's eye a counterfeiter, in the act of engraving38 on the stone or the others may ignore the penalty that awaits them, but he cannot. This illustration is convincing, for in cases of other crimes one may always assume that the criminal acted without thinking of the future, even when he was not in a transport of passion. But in the case of the counterfeiter the very act of committing the crime reminds him of the threat of the law, and yet he is imperturbable39 while perpetrating it.
Crime has its natural causes, which lie outside of that mathematical point called the free will of the criminal. Aside from being a juridical phenomenon, which it would be well to examine by itself, every crime is above all a natural and social phenomenon, and should be studied primarily as such. We need not go through so hard a course of study merely for the purpose of walking over the razor edge of juristic definitions and to find out, for instance, that from the time Romagnosi made a distinction between incompleted and attempted crime rivers of ink have been spilled in the attempt to find the distinguishing elements of these two degrees of crime. And finally, when the German legislator concluded to make no distinction between incompleted and attempted crime and to recognize only the completed crime in his code of 1871, we witnessed the spectacle of Carrara praising that legislator for leaving that subtile distinction out of his code. A strange conclusion on the part of a science, which cudgels its brains for a century to find the marks of distinction between attempted and incompleted crime, and then praises the legislator for ignoring it. And another classic jurist, Buccellati, proposed to do away with the theory of attempted crime by simply defining it as a crime by itself, or as—a violation40 of police laws! A science which comes to such conclusions is a science which moves in metaphysical abstractions, and we shall see that all these finespun questions which abound41 in classical science lose all practical value before the necessity of saving society from the plague of crime.
The method which we, on the other hand, have inaugurated is the following: Before we study crime from the point of view of a juristic phenomenon, we must study the causes to which the annual recurrence42 of crimes in all countries is due. These are natural causes, which I have classified under the three heads of anthropological43, telluric and social. Every crime, from the smallest to the most atrocious, is the result of the interaction of these three causes, the anthropological condition of the criminal, the telluric environment in which he is living, and the social environment in which he is born, living and operating. It is a vain beginning to separate the meshes44 of this net of criminality. There are still those who would maintain the one-sided standpoint that the origin of crime may be traced to only one of these elements, for instance, to the social element alone. So far as I am concerned, I have combatted this opinion from the very inauguration45 of the positive school of criminology, and I combat it today. It is certainly easy enough to think that the entire origin of all crime is due to the unfavorable social conditions in which the criminal lives. But an objective, methodical, observation demonstrates that social conditions alone do not suffice to explain the origin of criminality, although it is true that the prevalence of the influence of social conditions is an incontestable fact in the case of the greater number of crimes, especially of the lesser46 ones. But there are crimes which cannot be explained by the influence of social conditions alone. If you regard the general condition of misery47 as the sole source of criminality, then you cannot get around the difficulty that out of one thousand individuals living in misery from the day of their birth to that of their death only one hundred or two hundred become criminals, while the other nine hundred or eight hundred either sink into biological weakness, or become harmless maniacs48, or commit suicide without perpetrating any crime. If poverty were the sole determining cause, one thousand out of one thousand poor ought to become criminals. If only two hundred become criminals, while one hundred commit suicide, one hundred end as maniacs, and the other six hundred remain honest in their social condition, then poverty alone is not sufficient to explain criminality. We must add the anthropological and telluric factor. Only by means of these three elements of natural influence can criminality be explained. Of course, the influence of either the anthropological or telluric or social element varies from case to case. If you have a case of simple theft, you may have a far greater influence of the social factor than of the anthropological factor. On the other hand, if you have a case of murder, the anthropological element will have a far greater influence than the social. And so on in every case of crime, and every individual that you will have to judge on the bench of the criminal.
The anthropological factor. It is precisely49 here that the genius of Cesare Lombroso established a new science, because in his search after the causes of crime he studied the anthropological condition of the criminal. This condition concerns not only the organic and anatomical constitution, but also the psychological, it represents the organic and psychological personality of the criminal. Every one of us inherits at birth, and personifies in life, a certain organic and psychological combination. This constitutes the individual factor of human activity, which either remains50 normal through life, or becomes criminal or insane. The anthropological factor, then, must not be restricted, as some laymen51 would restrict it, to the study of the form of the skull52 or the bones of the criminal. Lombroso had to begin his studies with the anatomical conditions of the criminal, because the skulls53 may be studied most easily in the museums. But he continued by also studying the brain and the other physiological conditions of the individual, the state of sensibility, and the circulation of matter. And this entire series of studies is but a necessary scientific introduction to the study of the psychology of the criminal, which is precisely the one problem that is of direct and immediate54 importance. It is this problem which the lawyer and the public prosecutor55 should solve before discussing the juridical aspect of any crime, for this reveals the causes which induced the criminal to commit a crime. At present there is no methodical standard for a psychological investigation56, although such an investigation was introduced into the scope of classic penal law. But for this reason the results of the positive school penetrate57 into the lecture rooms of the universities of jurisprudence, whenever a law is required for the judicial58 arraignment59 of the criminal as a living and feeling human being. And even though the positive school is not mentioned, all profess60 to be studying the material furnished by it, for instance, its analyses of the sentiments of the criminal, his moral sense, his behavior before, during and after the criminal act, the presence of remorse61 which people, judging the criminal after their own feelings, always suppose the criminal to feel, while, in fact, it is seldom present. This is the anthropological factor, which may assume a pathological form, in which case articles 46 and 47 of the penal code remember that there is such a thing as the personality of the criminal. However, aside from insanity, there are thousands of other organic and psychological conditions of the personality of criminals, which a judge might perhaps lump together under the name of extenuating62 circumstances, but which science desires to have thoroughly63 investigated. This is not done today, and for this reason the idea of extenuating circumstances constitutes a denial of justice.
This same anthropological factor also includes that which each one of us has: the race character. Nowadays the influence of race on the destinies of peoples and persons is much discussed in sociology, and there are one-sided schools that pretend to solve the problems of history and society by means of that racial influence alone, to which they attribute an absolute importance. But while there are some who maintain that the history of peoples is nothing but the exclusive product of racial character, there are others who insist that the social conditions of peoples and individuals are alone determining. The one is as much a one-sided and incomplete theory as the other. The study of collective society or of the single individual has resulted in the understanding that the life of society and of the individual is always the product of the inextricable net of the anthropological, telluric and social elements. Hence the influence of the race cannot be ignored in the study of nations and personalities65, although it is not the exclusive factor which would suffice to explain the criminality of a nation or an individual. Study, for instance, manslaughter in Italy, and, although you will find it difficult to isolate66 one of the factors of criminality from the network of the other circumstances and conditions that produce it, yet there are such eloquent67 instances of the influence of racial character, that it would be like denying the existence of daylight if one tried to ignore the influence of the ethnical factor on criminality.
In Italy there are two currents of criminality, two tendencies which are almost diametrically opposed to one another. The crimes due to hot blood and muscle grow in intensity68 from northern to southern Italy, while the crimes against property increase from south to north. In northern Italy, where movable property is more developed, the crime of theft assumes a greater intensity, while crimes due to conditions of the blood are decreasing on account of the lesser poverty and the resulting lesser degeneration of the people. In the south, on the other hand, crimes against property are less frequent and crimes of blood more frequent. Still there also are in southern Italy certain cases where criminality of the blood is less frequent, and you cannot explain this in any other way than by the influence of racial character. If you take a geographical69 map of manslaughter in Italy, you will see that from the minimum, from Lombardy, Piedmont, and Venice, the intensity increases until it reaches its maximum in the insular70 and peninsular extreme of the south. But even there you will find certain cases in which manslaughter shows a lesser intensity.
For instance, the province of Benevent is surrounded by other provinces which show a maximum of crimes due to conditions of blood, while it registers a smaller number. Naples, again, shows a considerably71 smaller number of such cases than the provinces surrounding it, but it has a greater number of unpremeditated cases of manslaughter. Messina, Catania and Syracuse have a remarkably72 smaller number of blood crimes than Trapani, Girgenti and Palermo. It has been attempted to claim that this difference in criminality is due to social condition's, because the agricultural conditions in eastern Sicily are less degrading than those of Girgenti and Trapani, where the sulphur mines compel the miners to live miserably73. But we should like to ask the following question in opposition74 to this idea: Why and in what respect are the agricultural conditions in some provinces better than in others? This condition is merely itself a result, not a cause of the first degree.
Since the theory of historical materialism75, which I prefer to call economic determinism, has demonstrated that political, moral and intellectual phenomena76 are reactions on the economic conditions of any time and place, the attempt has been made to interpret this theory very narrowly and to pretend that the economic condition of a nation is a primary cause and not determined by any other. For my part, ever since I have demonstrated the perfect accord between the Marxian and the Darwinian theories, I have said: Very well, the economic conditions of a nation explain its political, moral, intellectual conditions, but the economic condition is in its turn the result of other factors. For instance, how can the industrialism of England in the nineteenth century be explained? Take away the coal mines (the telluric environment), and you could not have the economic conditions of England as they are. For the economic conditions are a result of favorable or unfavorable telluric conditions which are acted upon by the intelligence and energy of a certain race. Catania, Messina, Syracuse, are in a better economic condition, because they have better geographical conditions and a different race (of Grecian blood) than the other Sicilian provinces. So it is in Apulia and Naples, which have likewise a considerable mixture of Grecian blood. The northern tourists are still attracted by our art and visit the ruins of Taormina or Pesto, which are the relics77 of the Grecian race. And it is the Grecian blood which explains the lesser frequency of bloody78 crimes in those provinces. This is therefore evidently the influence of the race. And I maintain that the same fact is due in the province of Benevent to the admixture of Langobardian blood. For the Duchy of Benevent has had an influx79 of Langobardian elements since the seventh century. And as we know that the German and Anglo-Saxon race has the smallest tendency towards bloody crimes, the beneficial influence of this racial character in Benevent explains itself. On the other hand, there is much Saracen blood in the western and southern provinces of Sicily, and this explains the greater number of bloody crimes there. It is evident that the organic character of the inhabitants of that island, where you may still see the brutal80 and barbarian81 features of the Saracen by the side of those of the blond, cool and quiet Norman, contains a transfusion82 of the blood of diverse races. But it is also true that wherever a certain race has been predominant, there its influence is left behind in the individual and collective life.
Let this be enough so far as the anthropological factor of criminality is concerned. There are, furthermore, the telluric factors, that is to say, the physical environment in which we live and to which we pay no attention. It requires much philosophy, said Rousseau, to note the things with which we are in daily contact, because the habitual83 influence of a thing makes it more difficult to be aware of it. This applies also to the immediate influence of the physical conditions on human morality, notwithstanding the spiritualist prejudices which still weigh upon our daily lives. For instance, if it is claimed in the name of supernaturalism and psychism84 that a man is unhappy because he is vicious, it is equivalent to making a one-sided statement. For it is just as true to say that a man becomes vicious because he is unhappy. Want is the strongest poison for the human body and soul. It is the fountain head of all inhuman and antisocial feeling. Where want spreads out its wings, there the sentiments of love, of affection, of brotherhood85, are impossible.
Take a look at the figures of the peasant in the far-off arid Campagna, the little government employee, the laborer86, the little shop-keeper. When work is assured, when living is certain, though poor, then want, cruel want, is in the distance, and every good sentiment can germinate87 and develop in the human heart. The family then lives in a favorable environment, the parents agree, the children are affectionate. And when the laborer, a bronzed statue of humanity, returns from, his smoky shop and meets his white-haired mother, the embodiment of half a century of immaculate virtue88 and heroic sacrifices, then he can, tired, but assured of his daily bread, give room to feelings of affection, and he will cordially invite his mother to share his frugal89 meal. But let the same man, in the same environment, be haunted by the spectre of want and lack of employment, and you will see the moral atmosphere in his family changing as from day into night. There is no work, and the laborer comes home without any wages. The wife, who does not know how to feed the children, reproaches her husband with the suffering of his family. The man, having been turned away from the doors of ten offices, feels his dignity as an honest laborer assailed90 in the very bosom91 of his own family, because he has vainly asked society for honest employment. And the bonds of affection and union are loosened in that family. Its members no longer agree. There are too many children, and when the poor old mother approaches her son, she reads in his dark and agitated92 mien93 the lack of tenderness and feels in her mother heart that her boy, poisoned by the spectre of want, is perhaps casting evil looks at her and harboring the unfilial thought: "Better an open grave in the cemetery94 than one mouth more to feed at home!"
It is true, that want alone is not sufficient to prepare the soil in the environment of that suffering family for the roots of real crime and to develop it. Want will weaken the love and mutual95 respect among the members of that family, but it will not be strong enough alone to arm the hands of the man for a matricidal deed, unless he should get into a pathological mental condition, which is very exceptional and rare. But the conclusions of the positive school are confirmed in this case as in any other. In order that crime may develop, it is necessary that anthropological, social and telluric factors should act together.
We generally forget the conditions of the physical environment in which we live, because supernatural prejudice tells us that the body is a beast which we must forget in order to elevate ourselves into a spiritual life. Manzoni could designate the Middle Ages by the term "dirty." because they neglected the demands of elementary hygiene96, and thus of human morality. For where the requirements of our physical body are neglected or offended, there no flower can bloom. The telluric environment has a great influence on our physical activity, by way of our nervous system. We feel differently disposed, according to whether a south or a north wind blows. When Garibaldi was on the Pampas, he observed that his companions were irascible and prone97 to violent quarrels, when the Pampero blew, and that their behavior changed, when this wind ceased. The great founders98 of criminal statistics, Quetelet and Guerry, observed that the change of seasons carried with it a change in criminality. Sexual crimes are less frequent in winter than in spring and summer. And with reference to this point I have maintained, and still maintain, that it is due to the combined effects of temperature and social conditions, if crimes against property increase in winter. For lack of employment, the want of food and shelter, intensify99 the misery and lead to attacks on property. On the other hand, the cold by itself reduces sexual crimes and personal assaults. And those who claim that the longer intercourse100 between people in summer time has also a social influence, are also partly in the right.
The most eloquent fact in this respect was mentioned by Murro, when he pointed101 out that this change in the frequency of bloody crimes, greater in the warm months than in winter, applied102 also to prisoners. Statistics show that breach103 of discipline is most frequent in hot seasons. The social factor does not enter there, because the social life is there the same in winter and in summer. This is, therefore, a practical proof of the influence of climate, and it is re-enforced by the fact that delirium104 and epilepsy in insane asylums105 are also more frequent in hot than in cold months. The influence of the telluric factors, then, cannot be denied, and the influence of the social factor intensifies107 it, as I have already shown by its most drastic and characteristic example, that of want. One can, therefore, understand that a man, whose morality has been shaken by the pressure of increasing want, may be led to commit a crime against property or persons.
It is certainly quite evident, that economic misery has an undeniable influence on criminality. And if you consider, that about 300,000 criminals are sentenced in Italy every year, 180,000 of them for minor crimes, and 120,000 for crimes which belong to the gravest class, you can easily see that the greater part of them due mainly to social conditions, for which it should not be so very difficult to find a remedy. The work of the legislator may be slow, difficult, and inadequate108, so far as the telluric and anthropological factors are concerned. But it could surely be rapid, efficacious and prompt, so far as the social factors influencing criminality are concerned.
We have now demonstrated that crime has its natural source in the combined interaction of three classes of causes, the anthropological (organic and psychological) factor, the telluric factor, and the social factor. And by this last factor we must not only mean want, but any other condition of administrative109 instability in political, moral, and intellectual life. Every social condition which makes the life of man in society insincere and imperfect is a social factor contributing towards criminality. The economic factor is in evidence in our civilization wherever the law of free competition, which is but a form of disguised cannibalism110, establishes the rule: Your death is my life. The competition of laborers111 for a limited number of places is equivalent to saying that those who secure a living do so at the expense of those who do not. And this is a disguised form of cannibalism. While it does not devour112 the competitor as primitive113 mankind did, it paralyzes him by calumnies114, recommendations, protection, money, which, secure the place for the best bargainer and leave the most honest, talented, and self-respecting to the pangs115 of starvation.
Moreover, the economic factor exerts its crime-breeding influence also under the form of a superabundance of wealth. Indeed, in our present society, which is in the downward stage of transition from glorious bourgeois116 civilization, which constituted a golden page of human history in the 19th century, wealth itself is a source of crime. For the rich, who do not enjoy the advantage of manual or intellectual work, suffer from the corruption117 of leisure and vice118. Gambling119 throws them into an unhealthy fever; the struggle and race for money poison their daily lives. And although the rich may keep out of reach of the penal code, still they have condemned120 themselves to a life devoted122 to hypocritical ceremonies, which are devoid123 of moral sentiment. And this life leads them to a sportive form of criminality. To cheat at gambling is the inevitable124 fate of these parasites125. In order to kill time they give themselves up to games of chance, and those who do not care for that devote themselves to the sport of adultery, which in that class is a pastime even among the best friends, on account of sheer mental poverty. And all because man's mind unoccupied is the devil's own forge, as the English poet says.
We have now surveyed briefly126 the natural genesis of crime, as a natural social phenomenon, brought about by the interaction of anthropological, telluric, and social influences, which in any determined moment act upon a personality standing64 on the cross road of vice and virtue, crime and honesty. This scientific deduction127 gives rise to a series of investigations128 which satisfy the mind and supply it with a real understanding of things, far better than the theory that a man is a criminal because he wants to be. No, a man commits crime because he finds himself in certain physical and social conditions, from which the evil plant of crime takes life and strength. Thus we obtain the origin of that sad human figure which is the product of the interaction of those factors, an abnormal man, a man not adapted to the conditions of the social environment in which he is born, so that emigration becomes an ever more permanent phenomenon for the greater portion of men, for whom the accident of birth will less and less determine the course of their future life. And the abnormal man who is below the minimum of adaptability129 to social life and bears the marks of organic degeneration, develops either a passive or an aggressive form of abnormality and becomes a criminal.
Among these abnormal human beings, two groups must be particularly distinguished130. Limiting our observations to those who are true aggressively antisocial abnormals, that is to say, who are not adapted to a certain social order and attack it by crimes, we must distinguish those who for egoistic or ferocious131 reasons attack society by atavistic forms of the struggle for existence by committing socalled common crimes in the shape of fraud or violence, thereby132 opposing or abolishing conditions in which their fellow beings may live. This is the atavistic type of criminals which represents an involutionary, or retrogressive, form of abnormality, due to an arrested development or an atavistic reversion to a savage133 and primitive type. These constitute the majority in the world of criminals and must be distinguished from the minority, who are evolutionary134, or progressive, abnormals, that may also commit crime in a violent form, but must not be confounded with the others, because they do not act from egoistic motives135, but rebel from altruistic137 motives against the injustice138 of the present order. These altruistic criminals feel the sufferings and horrors due to the injustice surrounding them and may go so far as to commit murder, which must always be condemned, but which must not be confounded with atavistic or egoistic murder. Recourse to personal violence is always objectionable from the point of view of higher manhood, which desires that human life should always be held in respect. But the reasons for such a crime are different, being egoistic in the one, and altruistic in the other case. The evolutionary abnormal is often an instrument of human progress, not in the form of criminality, but in that of intellectual and moral rebellion against conditions which are sanctioned by laws that frequently punish such an evolutionary rebellion harder than atavistic crime, as they do in Russia, where capital punishment has been abolished for common crimes, but retained for political violations139 of the law! We are living in an epoch140 of transition from the old to the new, and contemporaneous humanity has an uneasy moral conscience in this critical time. The ruling classes are losing their clearness of vision, so that they promise monuments to those political murderers who promoted their own historical victories, but would condemn121 like any common criminal him who now devotes his soul to a revolutionary ideal, would throw into prison the pioneer of new human ideals, just as Russia is excommunicating the rebel Tolstoi. I mention Leo Tolstoi advisedly for the purpose of giving a precise illustration of my heterodox thought in reference to this question. We are opposed to any form of personal violence (with the sole exception of self-defense), we cannot approve of any form of personal assault, no matter what may be its motive136. Therefore we cannot have words of praise or excuse for political murder, though it may be inspired by altruistic motives. We can demand that the legislator should distinguish between the psychological sources of these two forms of murder, the egoistic and the altruistic form. But we condemn them both, because they are inhuman forms of violence. Ideas do not make victorious141 headway by force of arms. Ideas must be combatted by ideas, and it is only by the propaganda of the idea that we can prepare humanity for its future. Violence is always a means of preventing the sincere and fruitful diffusion142 of an idea. We do not say this merely for the abnormals of the lower classes. We refer with scientific serenity143 also to the upper classes, who would suppress by violence every manifestation144 of revolt against the social iniquities145, every affirmation of faith in a better future.
This is the conception of our science, which thus succeeds in distinguishing traits of character even among the unlucky and forlorn people of the criminal world, while the classic school of criminology regards a criminal as a sort of abstract and normal man, with the exception of cases of minors146, deaf mutes, inebriates147, and maniacs.
In fact, the classic school of criminology regards all thieves as THE thief, all murderers as THE murderer, and the human shape disappears in the mind of the legislator, while it re-appears before the judge. Before the essayist and legislator, the criminal is a sort of moving dummy148, on whose hack149 the judge may paste an article of the penal code. If you leave out of consideration the established cases of exceptional and rare human psychology mentioned in the penal code, all other cases serve the judge merely as an excuse to select from the criminal code the number of that article which will fit the criminal dummy, and if he should paste 404 instead of 407 on its back, the court of appeals would resist, any change of numbers. And if this dummy came to life and said: "The question of my number may be very important for you, but if you would study all the conditions that compelled me to take other people's things, you would realize that this importance is very diagrammatic," the judge would answer: "That's all right for the justice of the future, but it isn't now. You are number 404 of the criminal code, and after leaving this court room with this number pasted legally on your back, you will receive another number, for you will enter prison as number 404 and will exchange it for entry number 1525, or some other, because your personality as a man disappears entirely before the enactment150 of social justice!" And then it is pretended that this man, whose personality is thus absurdly ignored, should leave prison cured of all degeneration, and if he falls back into the path of thorns of his misery and commits another crime, the judge simply pastes another article over the other, by adding number 80 or 81, which refer to cases of relapse, to number
404!
In this way the classic school of criminology came to its unit of punishment, which it heralded151 as its great progress. In the Middle Ages, the diversity of punishment was greater. But in the 19th century the classic school of criminology combatted dishonoring punishment, corporeal152 punishment, confiscation153, professional punishment, capital punishment, with its ideal of one sole penalty, the only panacea154 for crime and criminals, prison.
We have, indeed, prohibitory measures and fines even today. But in substance the whole punitive155 armory156 is reduced to imprisonment157, since fines are likewise convertible158 into so many days or months of imprisonment. Solitary159 confinement160 is the ideal of the classic school of criminology. But experience proves that this penalty has as much effect on the disease of criminality, as the remedy of a physician would have, who would sit in the door of a hospital and tell every patient seeking relief: "Whatever may be your disease, I have only one medicine and that is a decoction of rhubarb. You have heart trouble? Well, then, the problem for me is simply—how big a dose of rhubarb decoction shall I give you?"
And measuring doses of penalty is the foundation of the criminal code. That is so true that this code is in its last analysis but a table of criminal logarithms for figuring out penalties. Woe161 to the judge who makes a mistake in sentencing a 19 year old offender162 who was drunk when he sinned, but had premeditated his deed. Woe to the judge, if he misses his calculation in adding or subtracting the third, or sixth, or one half, corresponding to the prescribed extenuating or aggravating163 circumstances! If he makes a miscalculation, the court of appeals is invoked164 by the defendant165, and the inexorable court of appeals tells the judge: "Figure this over again. You have been unjust." The only question for the judge is this: Add your sums and subtract your deductions166, and the prisoner is sentenced to one year, seven months, and thirteen days. Not one day more or less! But the human spectator asks: "If the criminal should happen to be reformed before the expiration167 of his term, should he be retained in prison?" The judge replies: "I don't care, he stays in one year, seven months, and thirteen days!"
Then the human spectator says: "But suppose the criminal should not yet be fit for human society at the expiration of his term?" The judge replies: "At the expiration of his term he leaves prison, for when he has absolved168 his last day, he has paid his debt!"
This is the same case as that of the imaginary physician who says: "You have heart trouble? Then take a quart of rhubarb decoction and stay twelve days in the hospital." Another patient says: "I have broken my leg." And the doctor: "All right, take a pint169 of rhubarb decoction and 17 days in the hospital." A third has inflammation of the lungs, and the doctor prescribes three quarts of rhubarb decoction and three months in the hospital. "But if my inflammation is cured before that time?" "No matter," says the doctor, "you stay in three months." "But if I am not cured of my lung trouble after three months?" "No matter," says the doctor, "you leave after three months."
To such results have wise men been led by a system of penal justice, which is a denial of all elementary common sense. They have forgotten the personality of the criminal and occupied themselves exclusively with crime as an abstract juristic phenomenon. In the same manner, the old style medicine occupied itself with disease as such, as an abstract pathological phenomenon, without taking into account the personality of the patient. The ancient physicians did not consider whether a patient was well or ill nourished, young or old, strong or weak, nervous or fullblooded. They cured fever as fever, pleurisy as pleurisy. Modern medicine, on the other hand, declares that disease must be studied in the living person of the patient. And the same disease may require different treatment, if the condition of the patient is different.
Criminal justice has taken the same historical course of development as medicine. The classic school of criminology is still in the same stage, in which medicine was before the middle of the 19th century. It deals with theft, murder, fraud, as such. But that which claims so much of the attention of society has been forgotten by the classic school. For that school has forgotten to study the murderer, the thief, the forger170, and without that study their crimes cannot be understood.
Crime is one of the conditions required for the study of the criminal. But, the same crime may require the application of different remedies to the personalities of different criminals, according to the different anthropological and social conditions of the various criminals. There is a fundamental distinction between the anthropological and social types of criminals, whom I have divided into five categories, which are today unanimously accepted by criminalist anthropologists, since the Geneva congress offered an opportunity to explain the misapprehension which led some foreign scientists to believe that the Italian school regarded one of these types (the born criminal) merely as an organic anomaly.
Just a word concerning each one of these five types.
The born criminal is a victim of that which I will call (seeing that science has not yet solved this problem) criminal neurosis, which is very analogous171 to epileptic neurosis, but which is not in itself sufficient to make one a criminal. Our adversaries172 had the idea that the mere15 possession of a crooked173 nose or a slanting174 skull stamped a man as predisposed by birth to murder or theft. But a man may he a born criminal, that is to say, he may have some congenital degeneration which predisposes him toward crime, and yet he may die at the age of 80 without having committed any crime, because he was fortunate enough to live in an environment which did not offer him any temptation to commit crime. Again, are not many predisposed toward insanity without ever becoming insane? If the same individual were to live under unfavorable conditions, without any education, if he were to find himself in unhealthy telluric surroundings, in a mine, a rice field, or a miasmatic175 swamp, he would become insane. But if instead of living in conditions that condemn him to lunacy he were to be under no necessity to struggle for his daily bread, if he could live in affluence176, he might exhibit some eccentricity177 of character, but would not cross the threshold of an insane asylum106. The same happens in the case of criminality. One may have a congenital predisposition toward crime, but if he lives in favorable surroundings, he will live to the end of his natural life without violating any criminal or moral law. At any rate we must drop the prejudice that only those are criminals on whose backs the judge has pasted a number. For there are many scoundrels at large who commit crime with impunity, or who brush the edge of the criminal law in the most repulsive178 immorality179 without violating it.
This misunderstanding was explained at the congress of Geneva by the statement that the interaction of the social and telluric environment is required also in the case of the born criminal. And now we may take it for granted that my classification of five types is everywhere accepted. These are the following: The born criminal who has a congenital predisposition for crime; the insane criminal suffering from some clinical form of mental alienation180, and whom even our existing penal code had to recognize; the habitual criminal, that is to say one who has acquired the habit of crime mainly through the ineffective measures employed by society for the prevention and repression of crime. A common figure in our large industrial centers is that of the abandoned child which has to go begging from its earliest youth in order to collect an income for the enterprising boss or for its poor family, without an opportunity to educate its moral sense in the filth181 of the streets. It is punished for the first time by the law and sent to prison or to a reformatory, where it is inevitably182 corrupted183. Then, when such an individual comes out of prison, he is stigmatized184 as a thief or forger, watched by the police, and if he secures work in some shop, the owner is indirectly185 induced to discharge him, so that he must inevitably fall back upon crime.
Thus one acquires crime as a habit, a product of social rottenness, due to the ineffective measures for the prevention and repression of crime. There is furthermore the occasional criminal, who commits very insignificant186 criminal acts, more because he is led astray by his conditions of life than because the aggressive energy of a degenerate187 personality impels188 him. If he is not made worse by a prison life, he may find an opportunity to return to a normal life in society. Finally there is the passionate189 criminal, who, like the insane criminal, has received attention from the positive school of criminology; which, however, did not come to any definite conclusions regarding him, such as may be gathered by means of the experimental method through study in prisons, insane asylums, or in freedom. The relations between passion and crime have so far been studied on a field in which no solution was possible. For the classic school considers such a crime according to the greater or smaller intensity and violence of passion and comes to the conclusion that the degree of responsibility decreases to the extent that the intensity of a passion increases, and vice versa. The problem cannot be solved in this way. There are passions which may rise to the highest degree of intensity without reducing the responsibility. For instance, is one who murders from motives of revenge a passionate criminal who must be excused?
The classic school of criminology says "No," and for my part I agree with them. Francesco Carrara says: "There are blind passions, and others which are reasonable. Blind passions deprive one of free will, reasonable ones do not. Blind and excusable passions are fear, honor, love, reasonable and inexcusable ones are hatred190 and revenge." But how so? I have studied murderers who killed for revenge and who told me that the desire for revenge took hold of them like a fever, so that they "forgot even to eat." Hate and revenge can take possession of a man to such an extent that he becomes blind with passion. The truth is that passion must be considered not so far as its violence or quantity are concerned, but rather as to its quality. We must distinguish between social and anti-social passion, the one favoring the conditions of life for the species and collectivity, the other antagonistic191 to the development of the collectivity. In the first case, we have love, injured honor, etc, which are passions normally useful to society, and aberrations192 of which may be excused more or less according to individual cases. On the other hand, we have inexcusable passions, because their psychological tendency is to antagonize the development of society. They are antisocial, and cannot be excused, and hate and revenge are among them.
The positive school therefore admits that a passion is excusable, when the moral sense of a man is normal, when his past record is clear, and when his crime is due to a social passion, which makes it excusable.
We shall see tomorrow what remedies the positive school of criminology proposes for each one of these categories of criminals, in distinction from the measuring of doses of imprisonment advocated by the classic school.
We have thus exhausted193 in a short and general review the subject of the natural origin of criminality.—To sum up, crime is a social phenomenon, due to the interaction of anthropological, telluric, and social factors. This law brings about what I have called criminal saturation194, which means that every society has the criminality which it deserves, and which produces by means of its geographical and social conditions such quantities and qualities of crime as correspond to the development of each collective human group.
Thus the old saying of Imetelet is confirmed: "There is an annual balance of crime, which must be paid and settled with greater regularity195 than the accounts of the national revenue." However, we positivists give to this statement a less fatalistic interpretation196, since we have demonstrated that crime is not our immutable197 destiny, even though it is a vain beginning to attempt to attenuate198 or eliminate crime by mere schemes. The truth is that the balance of crime is determined by the physical and social environment. But by changing the condition of the social environment, which is most easily modified, the legislator may alter the influence of the telluric environment and the organic and psychic199 conditions of the population, control the greater portion of crimes, and reduce them considerably. It is our firm conviction that a truly civilized legislator can attenuate the plague of criminality, not so much by means of the criminal code, as by means of remedies which are latent in the remainder of the social life and of legislation. And the experience of the most advanced countries confirms this by the beneficent and preventive influence of criminal legislation resting on efficacious social reforms.
We arrive, then, at this scientific conclusion: In the society of the future, the necessity for penal justice will be reduced to the extent that social justice grows intensively and extensively.
点击收听单词发音
1 atrocity | |
n.残暴,暴行 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
2 pervading | |
v.遍及,弥漫( pervade的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
3 patricide | |
n.杀父 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
4 appropriation | |
n.拨款,批准支出 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
5 apparatus | |
n.装置,器械;器具,设备 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
6 anatomy | |
n.解剖学,解剖;功能,结构,组织 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
7 inhuman | |
adj.残忍的,不人道的,无人性的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
8 explicitly | |
ad.明确地,显然地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
9 minor | |
adj.较小(少)的,较次要的;n.辅修学科;vi.辅修 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
10 insanity | |
n.疯狂,精神错乱;极端的愚蠢,荒唐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
11 strictly | |
adv.严厉地,严格地;严密地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
12 penal | |
adj.刑罚的;刑法上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
13 defense | |
n.防御,保卫;[pl.]防务工事;辩护,答辩 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
14 ascertaining | |
v.弄清,确定,查明( ascertain的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
15 mere | |
adj.纯粹的;仅仅,只不过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
16 supreme | |
adj.极度的,最重要的;至高的,最高的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
17 perspicacious | |
adj.聪颖的,敏锐的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
18 accomplished | |
adj.有才艺的;有造诣的;达到了的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
19 analyze | |
vt.分析,解析 (=analyse) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
20 fiat | |
n.命令,法令,批准;vt.批准,颁布 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
21 physiological | |
adj.生理学的,生理学上的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
22 psychology | |
n.心理,心理学,心理状态 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
23 determined | |
adj.坚定的;有决心的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
24 arid | |
adj.干旱的;(土地)贫瘠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
25 forth | |
adv.向前;向外,往外 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
26 civilized | |
a.有教养的,文雅的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
27 repression | |
n.镇压,抑制,抑压 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
28 inflicted | |
把…强加给,使承受,遭受( inflict的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
29 entirely | |
ad.全部地,完整地;完全地,彻底地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
30 volcanic | |
adj.火山的;象火山的;由火山引起的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
31 eruption | |
n.火山爆发;(战争等)爆发;(疾病等)发作 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
32 impunity | |
n.(惩罚、损失、伤害等的)免除 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
33 impelled | |
v.推动、推进或敦促某人做某事( impel的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
34 counterfeit | |
vt.伪造,仿造;adj.伪造的,假冒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
35 counterfeiter | |
n.伪造者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
36 inscription | |
n.(尤指石块上的)刻印文字,铭文,碑文 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
37 counterfeiting | |
n.伪造v.仿制,造假( counterfeit的现在分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
38 engraving | |
n.版画;雕刻(作品);雕刻艺术;镌版术v.在(硬物)上雕刻(字,画等)( engrave的现在分词 );将某事物深深印在(记忆或头脑中) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
39 imperturbable | |
adj.镇静的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
40 violation | |
n.违反(行为),违背(行为),侵犯 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
41 abound | |
vi.大量存在;(in,with)充满,富于 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
42 recurrence | |
n.复发,反复,重现 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
43 anthropological | |
adj.人类学的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
44 meshes | |
网孔( mesh的名词复数 ); 网状物; 陷阱; 困境 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
45 inauguration | |
n.开幕、就职典礼 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
46 lesser | |
adj.次要的,较小的;adv.较小地,较少地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
47 misery | |
n.痛苦,苦恼,苦难;悲惨的境遇,贫苦 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
48 maniacs | |
n.疯子(maniac的复数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
49 precisely | |
adv.恰好,正好,精确地,细致地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
50 remains | |
n.剩余物,残留物;遗体,遗迹 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
51 laymen | |
门外汉,外行人( layman的名词复数 ); 普通教徒(有别于神职人员) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
52 skull | |
n.头骨;颅骨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
53 skulls | |
颅骨( skull的名词复数 ); 脑袋; 脑子; 脑瓜 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
54 immediate | |
adj.立即的;直接的,最接近的;紧靠的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
55 prosecutor | |
n.起诉人;检察官,公诉人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
56 investigation | |
n.调查,调查研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
57 penetrate | |
v.透(渗)入;刺入,刺穿;洞察,了解 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
58 judicial | |
adj.司法的,法庭的,审判的,明断的,公正的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
59 arraignment | |
n.提问,传讯,责难 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
60 profess | |
v.声称,冒称,以...为业,正式接受入教,表明信仰 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
61 remorse | |
n.痛恨,悔恨,自责 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
62 extenuating | |
adj.使减轻的,情有可原的v.(用偏袒的辩解或借口)减轻( extenuate的现在分词 );低估,藐视 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
63 thoroughly | |
adv.完全地,彻底地,十足地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
64 standing | |
n.持续,地位;adj.永久的,不动的,直立的,不流动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
65 personalities | |
n. 诽谤,(对某人容貌、性格等所进行的)人身攻击; 人身攻击;人格, 个性, 名人( personality的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
66 isolate | |
vt.使孤立,隔离 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
67 eloquent | |
adj.雄辩的,口才流利的;明白显示出的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
68 intensity | |
n.强烈,剧烈;强度;烈度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
69 geographical | |
adj.地理的;地区(性)的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
70 insular | |
adj.岛屿的,心胸狭窄的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
71 considerably | |
adv.极大地;相当大地;在很大程度上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
72 remarkably | |
ad.不同寻常地,相当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
73 miserably | |
adv.痛苦地;悲惨地;糟糕地;极度地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
74 opposition | |
n.反对,敌对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
75 materialism | |
n.[哲]唯物主义,唯物论;物质至上 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
76 phenomena | |
n.现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
77 relics | |
[pl.]n.遗物,遗迹,遗产;遗体,尸骸 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
78 bloody | |
adj.非常的的;流血的;残忍的;adv.很;vt.血染 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
79 influx | |
n.流入,注入 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
80 brutal | |
adj.残忍的,野蛮的,不讲理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
81 barbarian | |
n.野蛮人;adj.野蛮(人)的;未开化的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
82 transfusion | |
n.输血,输液 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
83 habitual | |
adj.习惯性的;通常的,惯常的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
84 psychism | |
心灵论 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
85 brotherhood | |
n.兄弟般的关系,手中情谊 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
86 laborer | |
n.劳动者,劳工 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
87 germinate | |
v.发芽;发生;发展 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
88 virtue | |
n.德行,美德;贞操;优点;功效,效力 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
89 frugal | |
adj.节俭的,节约的,少量的,微量的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
90 assailed | |
v.攻击( assail的过去式和过去分词 );困扰;质问;毅然应对 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
91 bosom | |
n.胸,胸部;胸怀;内心;adj.亲密的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
92 agitated | |
adj.被鼓动的,不安的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
93 mien | |
n.风采;态度 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
94 cemetery | |
n.坟墓,墓地,坟场 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
95 mutual | |
adj.相互的,彼此的;共同的,共有的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
96 hygiene | |
n.健康法,卫生学 (a.hygienic) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
97 prone | |
adj.(to)易于…的,很可能…的;俯卧的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
98 founders | |
n.创始人( founder的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
99 intensify | |
vt.加强;变强;加剧 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
100 intercourse | |
n.性交;交流,交往,交际 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
101 pointed | |
adj.尖的,直截了当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
102 applied | |
adj.应用的;v.应用,适用 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
103 breach | |
n.违反,不履行;破裂;vt.冲破,攻破 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
104 delirium | |
n. 神智昏迷,说胡话;极度兴奋 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
105 asylums | |
n.避难所( asylum的名词复数 );庇护;政治避难;精神病院 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
106 asylum | |
n.避难所,庇护所,避难 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
107 intensifies | |
n.(使)增强, (使)加剧( intensify的名词复数 )v.(使)增强, (使)加剧( intensify的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
108 inadequate | |
adj.(for,to)不充足的,不适当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
109 administrative | |
adj.行政的,管理的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
110 cannibalism | |
n.同类相食;吃人肉 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
111 laborers | |
n.体力劳动者,工人( laborer的名词复数 );(熟练工人的)辅助工 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
112 devour | |
v.吞没;贪婪地注视或谛听,贪读;使着迷 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
113 primitive | |
adj.原始的;简单的;n.原(始)人,原始事物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
114 calumnies | |
n.诬蔑,诽谤,中伤(的话)( calumny的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
115 pangs | |
突然的剧痛( pang的名词复数 ); 悲痛 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
116 bourgeois | |
adj./n.追求物质享受的(人);中产阶级分子 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
117 corruption | |
n.腐败,堕落,贪污 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
118 vice | |
n.坏事;恶习;[pl.]台钳,老虎钳;adj.副的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
119 gambling | |
n.赌博;投机 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
120 condemned | |
adj. 被责难的, 被宣告有罪的 动词condemn的过去式和过去分词 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
121 condemn | |
vt.谴责,指责;宣判(罪犯),判刑 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
122 devoted | |
adj.忠诚的,忠实的,热心的,献身于...的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
123 devoid | |
adj.全无的,缺乏的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
124 inevitable | |
adj.不可避免的,必然发生的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
125 parasites | |
寄生物( parasite的名词复数 ); 靠他人为生的人; 诸虫 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
126 briefly | |
adv.简单地,简短地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
127 deduction | |
n.减除,扣除,减除额;推论,推理,演绎 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
128 investigations | |
(正式的)调查( investigation的名词复数 ); 侦查; 科学研究; 学术研究 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
129 adaptability | |
n.适应性 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
130 distinguished | |
adj.卓越的,杰出的,著名的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
131 ferocious | |
adj.凶猛的,残暴的,极度的,十分强烈的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
132 thereby | |
adv.因此,从而 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
133 savage | |
adj.野蛮的;凶恶的,残暴的;n.未开化的人 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
134 evolutionary | |
adj.进化的;演化的,演变的;[生]进化论的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
135 motives | |
n.动机,目的( motive的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
136 motive | |
n.动机,目的;adv.发动的,运动的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
137 altruistic | |
adj.无私的,为他人着想的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
138 injustice | |
n.非正义,不公正,不公平,侵犯(别人的)权利 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
139 violations | |
违反( violation的名词复数 ); 冒犯; 违反(行为、事例); 强奸 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
140 epoch | |
n.(新)时代;历元 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
141 victorious | |
adj.胜利的,得胜的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
142 diffusion | |
n.流布;普及;散漫 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
143 serenity | |
n.宁静,沉着,晴朗 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
144 manifestation | |
n.表现形式;表明;现象 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
145 iniquities | |
n.邪恶( iniquity的名词复数 );极不公正 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
146 minors | |
n.未成年人( minor的名词复数 );副修科目;小公司;[逻辑学]小前提v.[主美国英语]副修,选修,兼修( minor的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
147 inebriates | |
vt.使酒醉,灌醉(inebriate的第三人称单数形式) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
148 dummy | |
n.假的东西;(哄婴儿的)橡皮奶头 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
149 hack | |
n.劈,砍,出租马车;v.劈,砍,干咳 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
150 enactment | |
n.演出,担任…角色;制订,通过 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
151 heralded | |
v.预示( herald的过去式和过去分词 );宣布(好或重要) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
152 corporeal | |
adj.肉体的,身体的;物质的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
153 confiscation | |
n. 没收, 充公, 征收 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
154 panacea | |
n.万灵药;治百病的灵药 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
155 punitive | |
adj.惩罚的,刑罚的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
156 armory | |
n.纹章,兵工厂,军械库 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
157 imprisonment | |
n.关押,监禁,坐牢 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
158 convertible | |
adj.可改变的,可交换,同意义的;n.有活动摺篷的汽车 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
159 solitary | |
adj.孤独的,独立的,荒凉的;n.隐士 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
160 confinement | |
n.幽禁,拘留,监禁;分娩;限制,局限 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
161 woe | |
n.悲哀,苦痛,不幸,困难;int.用来表达悲伤或惊慌 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
162 offender | |
n.冒犯者,违反者,犯罪者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
163 aggravating | |
adj.恼人的,讨厌的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
164 invoked | |
v.援引( invoke的过去式和过去分词 );行使(权利等);祈求救助;恳求 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
165 defendant | |
n.被告;adj.处于被告地位的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
166 deductions | |
扣除( deduction的名词复数 ); 结论; 扣除的量; 推演 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
167 expiration | |
n.终结,期满,呼气,呼出物 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
168 absolved | |
宣告…无罪,赦免…的罪行,宽恕…的罪行( absolve的过去式和过去分词 ); 不受责难,免除责任 [义务] ,开脱(罪责) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
169 pint | |
n.品脱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
170 forger | |
v.伪造;n.(钱、文件等的)伪造者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
171 analogous | |
adj.相似的;类似的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
172 adversaries | |
n.对手,敌手( adversary的名词复数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
173 crooked | |
adj.弯曲的;不诚实的,狡猾的,不正当的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
174 slanting | |
倾斜的,歪斜的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
175 miasmatic | |
adj.毒气的,沼气的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
176 affluence | |
n.充裕,富足 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
177 eccentricity | |
n.古怪,反常,怪癖 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
178 repulsive | |
adj.排斥的,使人反感的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
179 immorality | |
n. 不道德, 无道义 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
180 alienation | |
n.疏远;离间;异化 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
181 filth | |
n.肮脏,污物,污秽;淫猥 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
182 inevitably | |
adv.不可避免地;必然发生地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
183 corrupted | |
(使)败坏( corrupt的过去式和过去分词 ); (使)腐化; 引起(计算机文件等的)错误; 破坏 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
184 stigmatized | |
v.使受耻辱,指责,污辱( stigmatize的过去式和过去分词 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
185 indirectly | |
adv.间接地,不直接了当地 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
186 insignificant | |
adj.无关紧要的,可忽略的,无意义的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
187 degenerate | |
v.退步,堕落;adj.退步的,堕落的;n.堕落者 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
188 impels | |
v.推动、推进或敦促某人做某事( impel的第三人称单数 ) | |
参考例句: |
|
|
189 passionate | |
adj.热情的,热烈的,激昂的,易动情的,易怒的,性情暴躁的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
190 hatred | |
n.憎恶,憎恨,仇恨 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
191 antagonistic | |
adj.敌对的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
192 aberrations | |
n.偏差( aberration的名词复数 );差错;脱离常规;心理失常 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
193 exhausted | |
adj.极其疲惫的,精疲力尽的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
194 saturation | |
n.饱和(状态);浸透 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
195 regularity | |
n.规律性,规则性;匀称,整齐 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
196 interpretation | |
n.解释,说明,描述;艺术处理 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
197 immutable | |
adj.不可改变的,永恒的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
198 attenuate | |
v.使变小,使减弱 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
199 psychic | |
n.对超自然力敏感的人;adj.有超自然力的 | |
参考例句: |
|
|
欢迎访问英文小说网 |